Skip to main content

Practical Imagination

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Imposed Rationality and Besieged Imagination

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations ((PPCE,volume 9))

  • 108 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter presents the concept of practical imagination as a specification of the general concept of imagination. This type of imagination participates in the representation and anticipation of possible scenarios in which we see ourselves performing a course of action and living its consequences; it is from this anticipation that we make our decisions and act. By virtue of this, practical imagination is mainly counterfactual, and its exercise is limited to the field of the possible and realizable.

The internal relationship between practical rationality and imagination allows us, in turn, to differentiate the latter into the four practical contexts in which practical rationality can be differentiated, so that we can speak of ethical, moral, political and legal imagination. These four forms of imagination are developed as enablers of ethical, moral, legal and political rationality. This will be illustrated through the contributions of classical thinkers such as Aristotle and the Stoics in the case of ethical imagination, Hume and Kant for moral imagination, whereas the anticipation of institutional and legal arrangements that articulate our political and legal imagination will be presented from a wide variety of contributions that range from Plato to Marx.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    With the emergence of human language, the capacity to exercise imagination enabled increasing levels of cooperation that constituted a significant evolutionary advantage (Knight et al. 2004; Cosmides and Tooby 1992, 2000).

  2. 2.

    This type of imagination is a modal imagination insofar as it represents different possibilities conceived by an individual (Kripke 1985; Nichols 2004; Chalmers 2002; Sosa 2000). This opens the field to questions on the modal epistemology concerning how knowledge of what is possible is attainable, which in the case of practical imagination could lead, for example, to research on moral knowledge. However, this kind of problems do not fall within the scope of this work, so the discussions associated with the counterfactual imagination as modal imagination leading to issues of modal epistemology will not be considered.

  3. 3.

    The significant contribution Modzelewski (2017) has made consists in the development of an education of emotions aiming at stimulating citizen’s dispositions in democratic societies.

  4. 4.

    Besides its Hegelian resemblance, this formulation is convergent with Andy Clark’s concept of extended mind and in consequence, the mentioned processes could be subsumed under the category of extended cognition (Clark and Chalmers 1998; Clark 2008; Clark et al. 2018).

  5. 5.

    I take the differentiation of these five types of practical rationality from Habermas (1993) and Forst (2002, 2012).

  6. 6.

    The role of advising and assisting that means-ends rationality has, is implied in Hume’s position in his “slave passage” and which has been further developed by contemporary non-cognitive ethics theories, which having a restricted version of rationality, only focusing on this role of practical reason.

  7. 7.

    In his “middle dialogues” Plato affirms that imagination is a combination of doxa and aisthesis, that is, sensation combined with thought, which led him to warn that phantasia depends on the senses, leading to a way of thinking based on appearances (Plato 2015; Lyons 2005).

  8. 8.

    Regarding this, imagination differs from conceiving because to think or make judgements does not depend exclusively on us, and that is why we can incur in truth or error; in the case of the imagination, it cannot be true or false since it does not depend on anything external to the agent, and since it only depends on the agent, it can be exercised at will. From such exercise, it is possible to create fictions (427 b 16–21, 56) that can be located in the future or even be timeless.

    In addition, according to Aristotle, imagination differs from understanding in the effect produced by the objects referred to. In the case of understanding, when we think something is terrible, we experience a strong impression, but when we imagine, that impression does not arise, but we experience it as someone contemplating a painting, because it is fictitious (427 b 23–24, 56).

    According to Aristotle, the imagination is not a sense either, since the senses are always either a potentiality or an actuality (sight and seeing), while an image can be given without potentiality or actuality, as it happens in dreams. Additionally, perception is always present and available to the agent, which does not happen with the imagination (428 a 5–16, 57).

  9. 9.

    I am especially grateful to María Julia Bertomeu, who suggested this way of understanding moral imagination in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. A similar way of understanding this exercise of moral imagination can be found in what John Rawls calls the ‘categorical imperative procedure’ (Rawls 2000: 168–70).

  10. 10.

    The relationship between imagination, power and utopia is clearly explained by Broncano (2009: 251–6) and Acosta (2017: 541).

References

  • Acosta, Yamandú. 2017. Utopía. In Diccionario de justicia, ed. Carlos Pereda, 539–542. México: Siglo XXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hanna. 1961. The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and Its Political Significance. In Between Past and Future: Six Exercises in Political Though, 197–226. New York: The Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 2016. De anima. Trans. Christopher Shields. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics in Hannah Arendt’s Thought. In Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics, 121–147. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broncano, Fernando. 2009. La melancolía del cyborg. Barcelona: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, Ruth M.J. 2005. The Rational Imagination: How People Create Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castoriadis, Cornelius. 1975. The Imaginary Institution of Society. Trans. Kathleen Blamey. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Crossroads in the Laberynth. Trans. Martin H. Ryle and Kate Soper. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Figures of the Thinkable. Trans. Helen Arnold. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David J. 2002. Does Conceivability Entail Possibility? In Conceivability and Possibility, ed. Tamar Szabo Gendler and John Hawthorne, 145–200. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andy. 2008. Supersizing the Mind. Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andy, and David Chalmers. 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58 (1): 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andy, S. Orestis Palermos, and J. Adam Carter. 2018. New Human: Ethics, Trust and the Extended Mind. In Extended Epistemology, ed. Adam J. Carter, Andy Clark, Kallestrup Jesper, S. Orestis Palermos, and Duncan Pritchard, 331–351. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conill, Jesús. 2006. Ética hermenéutica: Crítica desde la facticidad. Madrid: Tecnos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, Leda, and John Tooby. 1992. Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange. In The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, ed. Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and JohnTooby, 163–228. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Evolutionary Psychology and the Emotions. In Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland-Jones, 91–115. New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrara, Alessandro. 1998. Reflective Authenticity: Rethinking the Project of Modernity. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, Leon. 1962. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer. 2002. Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, Edward J. 1961. Imagination. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans Georg. 1989. Truth and Method. Second revised edition. Trans. rev: Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, Raymond. 2010. Politics and the Imagination. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1993. On the Pragmatic, the Ethical, and the Moral Employments of Practical Reason. In Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Trans. Ciaran P. Cronin, 1–18. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1960. In A Treatise on Human Nature, ed. Lewis A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Oxford at Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007a. Critique of Judgement. Trans. James Creed Meredith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. In Anthropology, History and Education. Trans. Robert Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, Chris, Michael Studdert-Kennedy, and James R. Hurford, eds. 2004. The Evolutionary Emergence of Language: Social Function and the Origins of Linguistic Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine. 2008. The Normativity of Instrumental Reason. In The Constitution of Agency. Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology, 27–68. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul. 1985. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1982. Second Treatise of Government. Wheeling: Harlan Davidson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, John D. 2005. Before Imagination: Embodied Thought from Montaigne to Rousseau. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullen, Matthew N., and Keith D. Markman. 2002. Affective Impact of Close Counterfactuals. Implications of Possible Futurs for Possible Pasts. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 38 (1): 64–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona. 2000. Imagining Oneself Otherwise. In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, 124–150. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makkreel, Rudolf. 1990. Imagination and Interpretation in Kant. The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgement. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 2009. Philosophy and Critical Theory. In Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, 99–117. London: MayFlyBooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, George H. 1972. Mind, Self & Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modzelewski, Helena. 2017. Emociones, educación y democracia: una proyección de la teoría de las emociones de Martha Nussbaum. México: Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas-UNAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, Shaun. 2004. Imagining and believing: The promise of a single code. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62, (Special issue on Art, Mind, and Cognitive Science): 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, Gustavo. 2004. Medios, capacidades y justicia distributiva. México: Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas-UNAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 2015. Theaetetus and Sophist, ed. Christopher Rowe. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2000. Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seneca, Lucius. 2015. Letters on Ethics. Trans. Margaret Graver and A.A. Long. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, Ernest. 2000. Modal and Other A Priori Epistemology: How Can We Know What Is Possible and What’s Impossible? The Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (Suppl): 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 1984. Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 2004. Modern Social Imaginaries. London: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, Philip E., and Geoffrey Parker. 2005. Counterfactual Thought Experiments: Why We Cannot Live Without Them and How We Can Learn to Live with Them. In Unmaking the West: Counterfactuals, Contingency, and Causations, ed. Philip E. Tetlock, Richard Ned Lebow, and Geoffrey Parker, 3–35. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, Richard. 1984. The Thread of Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pereira, G. (2019). Practical Imagination. In: Imposed Rationality and Besieged Imagination. Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-26520-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics