Skip to main content

Abstract

This book seeks to find an explanation and a normative frame for the relationship between the Commission and the persons subject to its rule-making. This relationship is not entirely uncharted territory. Instead, there are a number of theoretical vantage points which offer views on it. I will enter the discussion of the relationship between the Commission and its subjects from these well established theories relating to non-legislative rule-making as ‘administrative’ action, to Commission rule-making being defined by the rule of law and to this rule-making as a democratic exercise of authority. This chapter discusses the delegated and implementing rule-making from these three perspectives and draws insight into how the relationship between the Commission and the persons subject to its rule-making should be framed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Consolidated Version of the Treaty on European Union [2010] OJ C83/13 (TEU).

  2. 2.

    For example, Mendes (2016a). So, generally, also Hofmann et al. (2011). Even though, when specifically dealing with delegated and implementing acts, they are described as ‘subordinate legislation’. ibid. chapter 15.

  3. 3.

    Mendes (2016a).

  4. 4.

    Hofmann et al. (2011).

  5. 5.

    An example for explicitly deriving the understanding of administrations from national law is Schwarze (2006).

  6. 6.

    For an explanation of the phenomenon cf. Chernilo (2011), p. 98. For an account of the problem it causes for EU law cf. Joerges (2004), p. 149. Even though this latter contribution focuses on private law, there is no reason to believe EU public law to be unaffected.

  7. 7.

    Cf the entry for ‘administer’ in The New Oxford Dictionary of English (Oxford University Press 1998). A similar, very general understanding is that of administration as “philosophy in action”. Hodgkinson (1978), p. 3.

  8. 8.

    Held (1996), p. 157.

  9. 9.

    See the ‘Herrschaftssoziologie’ developed by Weber, specifically his thoughts on ‘bu¨rokratische Herrschaft’: Weber (1964) ch. IX (2).

  10. 10.

    Mayntz (1978), p. 5. Weber is still widely cited today where-ever research on administration or bureaucracy is conducted, and his account of administrations remains orthodoxy to this day. Bugarič (2007), p. 484. Thus, for example, Anchrit Wille’s account of a ‘normal’ administration is a Weberian administration. Wille (2013).

  11. 11.

    Any author writing in English about Weber will be faced with a dilemma in translation: Weber uses the term ‘Herrschaft’ which is not congruent with any term in the English language (although possibly closest to ‘rule’ as in ‘the rule of Victoria I’ or ‘British colonial rule’). While it is mostly translated as ‘authority’ in English, this translation is somewhat misleading. ‘Herrschaft’ is much more archaic (and can be coercive), and ‘authority’ appears tame in comparison.

  12. 12.

    For a short discussion see also Robertson (1982), p. 19 et seq.

  13. 13.

    While Weber discusses a number of forms of administrations, according to him the form that an administration takes in a modern state is that of a bureaucracy (Weber 1964, p. 697). Indeed, the bureaucratic form is so accepted that today one might even use the terms ‘administration’ and ‘bureaucracy’ interchangeably. See, for example Peuker (2011).

  14. 14.

    Weber (1964), p. 703 et seq.

  15. 15.

    Art. 5 TEU.

  16. 16.

    This situation is central to the claim by Peter Lindseth that the EU as a whole has an administrative character. Cf Lindseth (2011); Lindseth (2012), p. 101. For a discussion see: Isiksel (2012), p. 128, Bartolini (2012), p. 139, deWitte (2012), p. 148 and Kelemen (2011), p. 157.

  17. 17.

    Delegated and Implementing Acts can consequently be described as a case of ‘double delegation’. Cf Vincze (2018).

  18. 18.

    Although it should be pointed out that the opposition of ‘rational’ with ‘political’ appears not entirely accurate given that ‘politics’ have their own logic and rationality. For a discussion of different rationalities see Snellen (2002), p. 326.

  19. 19.

    Such as arguably brought forward by the Court in Case C-355/10 European Parliament v Council of the European Union (Schengen Border Code) (2012) electronic reports of cases: Court reports – general (ECLI:EU:C:2012:516). Cf also den Heijer and Tauschinsky (2013), p. 513. For a critical discussion of the idea that administrations are rational and non-political see Fisher (2007).

  20. 20.

    Olsen (2003), p. 510.

  21. 21.

    For a description see i.e. Hood (1991), p. 3.

  22. 22.

    Stewart and Clarke (1987), p. 161; Fountain (2001), p. 55; Walker (2011), p. 707.

  23. 23.

    Habermas (1996) pp. 169, 186 et seq.

  24. 24.

    For an explanation of transmission belt theories see Stewart (1975), p. 1675 et seq. or van Gestel (2014), p. 33. For a criticism of a discourse oriented description of the transmission belt model see Seidenfeld (1992), p. 1517.

  25. 25.

    Habermas (1996), p. 190.

  26. 26.

    ibid. p. 191.

  27. 27.

    ibid. p. 192.

  28. 28.

    See, for example the description of existing participation possibilities and the critique of them being too closed and instrumentalised in Mendes (2011), chaps. 6–8.

  29. 29.

    The 2016 IIA Interinstitutional Agreement of Better Law-Making [2016] Council Document, 15506/15 envisages a greater role for consultations and impact assessment, and thus for participative mechanisms, also for delegated and implementing acts. However, such tools can necessarily only apply to a small number of delegated and implementing acts, given the frequency of Commission acts and the effort and resources necessary to conduct consultations and impact assessments.

  30. 30.

    See, for example, Gaus (1931), p. 120.

  31. 31.

    Gaus (1947), p. 23.

  32. 32.

    Even though this aspect is where the focus of the Commission lies. See European Commission, ‘European Governance - A White Paper’ (Communication) COM(2001)428 final and European Commission, ‘Communication from the Commission to the European Parliament, the Council, the European Economic and Social Committee and the Committee of the Regions: Better regulation for better results – An EU agenda’ (Communication) COM(2015) 215 final.

  33. 33.

    See, for example, Commission Implementing Regulation (EU) 2018/746 of 18 May 2018 amending Implementing Regulation (EU) No 809/2014 as regards modification of single applications and payment claims and checks [2018] OJ L125/1; Commission Delegated Regulation (EU) 2018/1063 of 16 May 2018 amending and correcting Delegated Regulation (EU) 2015/2446 supplementing Regulation (EU) No 952/2013 of the European Parliament and of the Council as regards detailed rules concerning certain provisions of the Union Customs Code [2018] OJ L192/1.

  34. 34.

    Shapiro (2001), p. 94.

  35. 35.

    Art 2 TEU.

  36. 36.

    Mak and Taekema (2016), p. 269; Baratta (2016), p. 358.

  37. 37.

    Arthurs (1979), p. 5. Even though Arthurs uses Dicey’s definition of the rule of law in his argument, he also states that this is simply because it allows for the problem to become most clear, and not because other conceptualisation would not be subject to the same problems.

  38. 38.

    Leisner (1977), p. 541, but see the contrary view argued by Badura: Badura (1968), p. 446.

  39. 39.

    Palombella (2016), p. 37.

  40. 40.

    Tamanaha (2004).

  41. 41.

    Ibid. p. 3, Waldron (2002), p. 137.

  42. 42.

    This notion is explained in Dicey (1956), p. 60, but is prevalent throughout the book.

  43. 43.

    For a contribution differentiation between ‘normal’ case law and offensive judicial activism see Heydon (2003), p. 9.

  44. 44.

    Leisner (1977).

  45. 45.

    Hayek (1973), pp. 72–73 and 124–144.

  46. 46.

    Thus, one commentator even describes the ‘rule of law’ and the ‘Rechtsstaat’ as contradicting concepts. See Peerenboom (2004), p. 2.

  47. 47.

    Sordi (2010), p. 33.

  48. 48.

    Rohr (2002), p. 14 et seq.

  49. 49.

    Somek (2004), p. 53 et seq.

  50. 50.

    Fallon (1997), p. 1.

  51. 51.

    Bedner (2010), p. 48.

  52. 52.

    Ibid. 51. On the first of these criteria see also Mak and Taekema (2016) with further references, as well as Schmidt-Aßmann (2004), p. 542.

  53. 53.

    Separation of powers terminology sits uncomfortably with the institutional set up of the EU. Lenaerts and Verhoeven (2002) However, in want of another term, these denominations will be used here.

  54. 54.

    Leisner (1977), p. 539.

  55. 55.

    ibid. p. 537.

  56. 56.

    Schmidt-Aßmann (n 52) p. 542. To the question whether this normative content stems from the inherent normative core of the principle, or from the specific normative context in which it is used (such as the German constitution in the case of the commentator, or the EU Treaties in the present case), Schmidt-Aßmann answers that even though human rights will provide much of the normative force, it is the rule of law which will give these norms structural effect.

  57. 57.

    Tamanaha (2004), p. 23 et seq.

  58. 58.

    Less historic German doctrine would express this as that it is a part of the concept of ‘law’ that it is intended to secure order and peace as well as rationality and reliability. Cf Badura (1968), p. 448.

  59. 59.

    Tamanaha (2004), p. 24.

  60. 60.

    German jurisprudence is much more reticent here (see, for example, Schmidt-Aßmann (n 52) p. 546 than, in principle, UK jurisprudence.

  61. 61.

    Palombella (2016), p. 43.

  62. 62.

    Peerenboom (2004), pp. 5, 9, von Bogdandy (2017), p. 506.

  63. 63.

    Bedner (2010), p. 59.

  64. 64.

    von Bogdandy (2000), p. 150.

  65. 65.

    As described by Philp (2009), p. 28 or Somek (2008) ch. 1.

  66. 66.

    The focus on the ‘technical’ nature of delegated and implementing acts is very much alive in the jurisprudence of the CJEU. Cf Case C-270/12 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland v European Parliament and Council of the European Union (2013) electronic reports of cases: Court reports – general (ECLI:EU:C:2014:18).

  67. 67.

    See, for example, Habermas (2008), p. 444, Nullmeier and Pritzlaff (2010).

  68. 68.

    Whether and in how far participative mechanism can function as substitutes for representation, or as independent means of instituting democracy depends on the mechanism and situation in question, and on factors such as how is the ‘people’ able to exert influence, how free they are in their expression and what role this influence plays in the adoption process.

  69. 69.

    See, for example, Nettesheim (2005), p. 358 or Kuo (2012), p. 855.

  70. 70.

    This is more true for popular media than for academic reports: see: https://www.express.co.uk/news/uk/818260/Juncker-bashed-Brexit-revealed-EU-Commission-democratic-deficiency-Shanker-Singham or more critically: https://www.economist.com/the-economist-explains/2017/07/14/does-it-make-sense-to-refer-to-eu-officials-as-unelected-bureaucrats. However, this ‘undemo-craticness’ is also a political trope: https://www.channelnewsasia.com/news/world/orban-rails-against-undemocratic-western-europe-10571470, and has been mentioned in some more official reports: Schmidt (2015), pp. 40–48.

  71. 71.

    Brandsma and Blom-Hansen (2017).

  72. 72.

    Gianluca Sgueo, ‘External Expertise in EU Policy-Making: The Quest for Transparency’ (SSRN Working Paper, 2017); Lafarge (2018).

  73. 73.

    Alemanno and Meeuwse (2013), p. 76.

  74. 74.

    Even though this appears to be the predominant assumption: “[t]he world owes to the Federalist Papers the idea that the principle of democracy finds its most important expression in representative institutions”; von Bogdandy (2012), pp. 315, 326. Cunningham assigns the equation of democracy with representative electoral mechanisms to Schumpeter: Cunningham (2002), p. 9.

  75. 75.

    Thus, for example, Holmes (1995).

  76. 76.

    Canovan (2002), p. 29.

  77. 77.

    ibid. p. 29 et seq.

  78. 78.

    Kelman and Hamilton (1989), p. 54 et seq.

  79. 79.

    Endicott (2014), p. 49.

  80. 80.

    This is summed up well by Larry Ribstein with a view to fiduciary relationships: “parties in the limited category of relationships involving open-ended delegation of power cannot contract to limit the manager’s power without undermining the beneficiary’s objective in delegating power”. Ribstein (2011), p. 904.

  81. 81.

    Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union (2010) [2010] OJ C83/389 (EU Charter) art 41. Even though the charter lists individual rights, ‘good administration’ arguably is of broader application. For an elaboration on ‘good administration’ see Fortsakis (2005), p. 207; Mendes (2009).

  82. 82.

    Woods (1999), p. 39; Kohler-Koch and Rittberger (2006), pp. 29, 37.

  83. 83.

    Fortsakis (2005), Mendes (2009), p. 3 et seq.

  84. 84.

    Nehl (2009), p. 336 et seq, 339 et seq.

  85. 85.

    Barnes (1988), p. 58.

  86. 86.

    The transformations of Easter European States, which are increasingly being accused of having become ‘undemocratic’ even as they followed the democratic processes initially is a case in point.

  87. 87.

    Braithwaite (1998), p. 344.

  88. 88.

    For a focus on the power or ‘space of freedom’ aspect of discretion, cf., for example, Calvert et al. (1989), p. 588; Forstyh (1999), p. 5; Franchino (2000), p. 155. Cf also Cartwright J. who famously (though dissenting) claimed that administrative organs, acting within the province of their powers are a law unto themselves. Roncarelli v Duplessis [1959] SCR 121, p. 167, 168.

  89. 89.

    Mendes (2016b), p. 419.

  90. 90.

    For an explanation of these see Pesch (2005).

  91. 91.

    Tomuschat (1999), p. 95, see also 161 et seq. Tomuschat here refers to states, but his statement can be taken to use states as the paradigmatic case for organisations of public authority.

  92. 92.

    Waldron (2012), p. 200.

  93. 93.

    Mashaw (1981), p. 885; Stewart (2014), p. 211.

  94. 94.

    This ‘duty of regard’ can be connected to the ‘other-regarding’ nature of public authority, described in Rothstein and Teorell (2008), p. 165 and Smith (2015), p. 130.

  95. 95.

    But cf. how Raz connects trust to ‘paternalistic’ aspects of government: Raz (2001), p. 122 et seq. I disagree with Raz’ definition of the problem as being one of coercion, as I find his juxtaposition of liberty and coercion too binary a model. Also, I find his definition of ‘paternalism’ to include any action which has the good of the one acted upon in mind as over-inclusive. For similar points of criticism see Wolfe (2001).

  96. 96.

    See the discussion in Canovan (2002), p. 30 et seq.

  97. 97.

    von Bogdandy (2017), p. 503.

  98. 98.

    Confucius TAmes and Rosemont (1998). The most cited passage here is in book 12, section 7, however, the concept of trust or trustworthiness is mentioned frequently throughout the analects. For the modern impact see Koehn (2001), p. 415. For an elaboration on the Chinese term that Confucius uses and its translation into the western concept of trust see: Wee (2011), p. 516.

  99. 99.

    Charles de Secondat (Baron de Montesquieu), The Spirit of Laws (Thomas Nugenttr, first published 1752, Batoche Books 2001), cf. also Natelson (2004), p. 1132.

  100. 100.

    John Locke, Second Treatise of Government (first published 1690, Project Gutenberg, 2010) specifically Section 139 et seq.

  101. 101.

    Cf Doernberg (1985), p. 52 and Maloy (2009), p. 492.

  102. 102.

    Weil (1987), p. 759.

  103. 103.

    For example, TNS opinion & social, Standard Eurobarometer 83: Public Opinion in the European Union (First Results) (2015) (http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/eb/eb83/eb83_first_en.pdf) p. 6 et seq. For an analysis of such polls see Dalton (2005), p. 133.

  104. 104.

    The model of authority based on trust is linked to, but differs from arguments about the morality of law, as it is about deference to trust actors, not about deference to the institution of ‘law’: Tyler (1998), p. 277 For an account of the morality of law, the strong relational aspects of which connect rather well to the relational approach presented here, see Fuller (1973).

  105. 105.

    For this definition of authority, see Kelman and Hamilton (1989), p. 53.

  106. 106.

    For a definition of trust as the belief in goodwill, see the seminal work: Baier (1986), p. 234. The term ‘goodwill’ hereby should not be over-interpreted: it can refer merely to the willingness of a person to not exploit the vulnerabilities of another, such as formulated in the definition of trust in Blair and Stout (2001), p. 1740. For a more recent, elaborate description of trust (partly criticising Baier), see Lagerspetz and Hertzberg (2013).

  107. 107.

    For an elaboration on this argument with further references for empirical evidence see Tyler (1998), p. 272 et seq.

  108. 108.

    This belief should be differentiated from the belief that matters would be worse without government: Dunn (1988), p. 287. The kinds of behaviours necessary to assert these two differ markedly. Generally, being trusted increases the degrees of freedom of the trusted, opening up new possibilities for action and being forgiven more easily for minor mistakes: Offe (1999), p. 51.

  109. 109.

    This is of course a rather short and compacted account of the way that trust and authority connect. The concept of trust alone has long been a puzzle to many thinkers, as, for example, Hawthorn’s insistence that the conditions for trust are impossible to meet, shows: Hawthorn (1988). ‘Authority’ is no less debated a concept.

  110. 110.

    Farina C and ABA Committee on Government Standards (1993), p. 292.

  111. 111.

    Cf in the same line, though with different terms, Raz’ condition of government respecting its citizens and providing ‘full citizenship’ in order for the people to reasonably trust them. Without the reasonable expectancy of this trust, government cannot be justified to use coercive means for the good of the people. Raz (2001).

  112. 112.

    Cf also O’Neill (2002).

  113. 113.

    Because of this, Luhmann treats trust as a leap of faith: Luhmann (1968), pp. 23, 31.

  114. 114.

    Warren (1999), p. 331. Some commentators describe trust as the outcome of the cost-benefit analysis of the risk of becoming vulnerable (for example Hardin 1998 or Coleman 1990, p. 91 et seq). While I find this description questionable, I also submit that the precise reasons for trust are not very relevant for the further treatment of the subject here. For a discussion of the rational choice and more behavioural conceptualisations of trust see already Held (1968), p. 156.

  115. 115.

    Patterson (1999), p. 153.

  116. 116.

    For a comparison and an elaboration of the relation of the kind of trust or trust-worthiness regarding trust in an institution with trust as the more interpersonal, psycho-sociological attitude of trust see: Braithwaite (1998), p. 344 et seq.

  117. 117.

    For a more empirical reasoning that the Commission in the fulfilment of its duties indeed relies on trust relationships see; Tsakatika (2005), p. 198 et seq, Tsakatika (2008).

  118. 118.

    Braithwaite (1998), p. 353 et seq.

  119. 119.

    In as much as it is possible to speak of a ‘decision’ here. For a discussion of the intentional aspects of trust see Mansbridge (1999), p. 294 et seq.

  120. 120.

    Interestingly, most writers on trust treat trustworthiness as something to be determined by a person when considering whether or not to trust without switching the perspective to what this means for those who rely on being trusted (with the no- table exception of Mitchell (2001), p. 591). However, the point that trustworthiness is a matter of judgement is strongly made: Tyler (1998), p. 280 et seq. For further reasoning on trustworthiness and trust see: Harré (1999) p. 258, O’Neill (2002).

  121. 121.

    Patterson (1999), p. 154, Shapiro (1987), p. 623.

  122. 122.

    Of course it depends what this authority is founded on: Indirect trust can be established by someone trusted, but not by someone whose authority is based on control by its subjects or to whose power they submit to for instrumental reasons (according to a principal- agent model of delegated authority).

  123. 123.

    For a more general argument of such a restriction virtually never being the case and there thus always being a direct dependency of the persons subject to a decision on the decisions by government bodies, see Pettit (1998), p. 300 et seq.

  124. 124.

    Specifically which these are is the subject of the following chapter.

  125. 125.

    Braithwaite (1998).

  126. 126.

    Shapiro (1987), p. 626.

  127. 127.

    Indeed, behaviour can be based on impersonal trust in spite of a situation of individual attitudes of suspicion, such as when President Bill Clinton was voted into office in 1997 despite the majority of voters reporting that they distrusted him personally. Cf Patterson (1999), p. 200 et seq. For a slightly different definition of ‘personal’ vs ‘impersonal’ trust, namely as motivated in their goodwill in relational or independent terms, see Pettit (1998). In Pettit’s term, political trust has necessarily a personal component, even if it is institutionalised. Ibid. p. 299 et seq.

  128. 128.

    Cf Shapiro (2012), relying on Tamar Frankel (see Frankel 1983, p. 795; Frankel 1995, p. 1209 and cf. Braithwaite (1998), relying on Paul Finn (see Finn 1994, p. 224).

  129. 129.

    At least a public kind of trust. For an elaboration of the origins of the concept see Watson (1962), p. 329. Relationships where trust creates authority are also understood as fiduciary relationship by Tyler and Huo (2002), pp. 62–63.

  130. 130.

    von Bogdandy (2017), p. 501.

References

  • Alemanno A, Meeuwse A (2013) Impact assessment of EU non-legislative rulemaking: the missing link in ‘new comitology’. Eur Law J 19(1):76

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthurs HW (1979) Rethinking administrative law: a slightly Dicey business. Osgoode Hall Law J 17(1):1

    Google Scholar 

  • Badura P (1968) Auftrag und Grenzen der Verwaltung im sozialen Rechtsstaat. Die öffentliche Verwaltung 13–14:446

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier A (1986) Trust and antitrust. Ethics 96(2):231

    Google Scholar 

  • Baratta R (2016) Rule of law ‘dialogues’ within the EU: a legal assessment. Hague J Rule Law 8:357

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes B (1988) The nature of power. Polity Press, p 58

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolini S (2012) Special book review symposium power and legitimacy. Eur Const Law Rev 8:139

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedner A (2010) An elementary approach to the rule of law. Hague J Rule Law 2:48

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair MM, Stout LA (2001) Trust, trustworthiness, and the behavioral foundations of corporate law. Univ Pa Law Rev 149(6):1735

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite J (1998) Institutionalizing Distrust, Enculturing Trust. In: Braithwaite V, Levi M (eds) Trust & Governance. Russell Sage Foundation, p 344

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandsma G-J, Blom-Hansen J (2017) Controlling the EU-executive? The politics of delegation in the European Union. Oxford University Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Bugarič B (2007) Openness and transparency in public administration: challenges for public law. Wisconsin Int Law J 22(3):484

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvert RL, McCubbins MD, Weingast BR (1989) A theory of political control and agency discretion. Am J Polit Sci 33(3):588

    Google Scholar 

  • Canovan M (2002) Taking politics to the people: populism as the ideology of democracy. In: Meny Y, Surel Y (eds) Democracies and the populist challenge. Palgrave, p 29

    Google Scholar 

  • Chernilo D (2011) The critique of methodological nationalism: theory and history. Thesis Eleven 106(1):98

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JS (1990) Foundations of social theory. Belknap Press, p 91 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham F (2002) Theories of democracy: a critical introduction. Routledge, p 9

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalton RJ (2005) The social transformation of trust in government. Int Rev Sociol 15(1):133

    Google Scholar 

  • den Heijer M, Tauschinsky E (2013) Where human rights meet administrative law: essential elements and limits to delegation: European Court of Justice, Grand Chamber C-355/10: European Parliament v. Council of the European Union. Eur Const Law Rev 9(3):513

    Google Scholar 

  • deWitte B (2012) Special book review symposium power and legitimacy. Eur Const Law Rev 8:148

    Google Scholar 

  • Dicey AV (1956) Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution, 9th edn. Macmillan & Co, p 60

    Google Scholar 

  • Doernberg DL (1985) “We the people”: John Locke, collective constitutional rights, and standing to challenge government action. Calif Law Rev 73:52

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn J (1988) Trust and political agency. In: Gambetta D (ed) Trust: making and breaking cooperative relations. Basil Blackwell, p 287

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott T (2014) Arbitrariness. Can J Law Jurisp 28(1):49

    Google Scholar 

  • Fallon RH (1997) “The rule of law” as a concept in constitutional discourse. Columbia Law Rev 97(1):1

    Google Scholar 

  • Farina C, ABA Committee on Government Standards (1993) Keeping faith: government ethics & government ethics regulation. Adm Law Rev 45:287

    Google Scholar 

  • Finn P (1994) Public trust and public accountability. Griffiths Law Rev 3(2):224

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher E (2007) Risk regulation and administrative constitutionalism. Hart

    Google Scholar 

  • Forstyh A (1999) Administrative discretion and urban and regional planners’ values. J Plan Lit 14(1):5

    Google Scholar 

  • Fortsakis T (2005) Principles governing good administration. Eur Public Law 11(2):207

    Google Scholar 

  • Fountain JE (2001) Paradoxes of public sector customer service. Governance 14(1):55

    Google Scholar 

  • Franchino F (2000) The Commission’s executive discretion: information and comitology. J Theor Polit 12(2):155

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankel T (1983) Fiduciary law. Calif Law Rev 71(3):795

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankel T (1995) Fiduciary duties as default rules. Oregon Law Rev 74:1209

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller LL (1973) The morality of law, Revised edn. Yale University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus JM (1931) Notes on administration. Am Polit Sci Rev 25(1):120

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus JM (1947) Reflections on administration. University Alabama, p 23

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. William Rehg tr, MIT Press, pp 169, 186 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (2008) The constitutionalization of international law and the legitimation problems of a constitution for world society. Constellations 15(4):444

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin R (1998) Trust in Government. In: Braithwaite V, Levi M (eds) Trust & Governance. Russell Sage, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R (1999) Trust and its surrogates: psychological foundations of political process. In: Warren ME (ed) Democracy & trust. Cambridge University Press, p 258

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorn G (1988) Three ironies in trust. In: Gambetta D (ed) Trust: making and breaking cooperative relations. Basil Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1973) Law, legislation and liberty: rules and order, Routledge & Kegan Paul, vol I, pp 72–73 and 124–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Held D (1996) Models of democracy, 2nd edn. Stanford University Press, p 157

    Google Scholar 

  • Held V (1968) On the meaning of trust. Ethics 78(2):156

    Google Scholar 

  • Heydon D (2003) Judicial activism and the death of the rule of law. Quadrant 47(1–2):9

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkinson C (1978) Towards a philosophy of administration. Blackwell, Oxford, p 3

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann H, Rowe G, Türk A (2011) Administrative law and policy of the European Union. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes S (1995) Passions and constraint: on the theory of liberal democracy. University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hood CC (1991) A public Management for all seasons? Public Adm 69:3

    Google Scholar 

  • Isiksel T (2012) Special book review symposium power and legitimacy. Eur Const Law Rev 8:128

    Google Scholar 

  • Joerges C (2004) The challenges of Europeanization in the realm of private law: a plea for a new legal discipline. Duke J Comp Int Law 14:149

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen D (2011) The European Union’s legitimacy: administrative not constitutional, or administrative then constitutional? Columbia J Eur Law 18:157

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelman HC, Hamilton VL (1989) Crimes of obedience: towards a social psychology of authority and responsibility. Yale University Press, New Haven, p 54 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Koehn D (2001) Confucian trustworthiness and the practice of business in China. Bus Ethics Q 11(3):415

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler-Koch B, Rittberger B (2006) The ‘governance turn’ in EU studies. J Common Mark Stud 44:27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuo M-S (2012) From administrative law to administrative legitimation? Transnational administrative law and the process of European integration. Int Comp Law Q 61(4):855

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafarge F (2018) The impact of the better regulation policy on EU delegated and implementing acts rule-making. In: Tauschinsky E, Weiß W (eds) The legislative choice between delegated and implementing acts in EU law: walking a labyrinth. Edward Elgar

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerspetz O, Hertzberg L (2013) Trust in Wittgenstein. In: Mäkelä P, Townley C (eds) Trust: analytical and applied perspective. Rodopi

    Google Scholar 

  • Leisner W (1977) Rechtsstaat – ein Widerspruch in sich? Juristenzeitung 32(17):537

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenaerts K, Verhoeven A (2002) Institutional balance as a guarantee for democracy in EU governance. In: Joerges C, Dehousse R (eds) Good governance in Europe’s integrated market. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindseth P (2011) Power and legitimacy: reconciling Europe and the Nation State. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindseth P (2012) Constitutionalism beyond the state? The administrative character of European governance revisited. Cardozo Law Rev 33(5):101

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann N (1968) Vertrauen: ein Mechanismus zur Reduktion sozialer Komplexität. Stuttgart, p 23, 31

    Google Scholar 

  • Mak E, Taekema S (2016) The European Union’s rule of law agenda: identifying its core and contextualizing its application. Hague J Rule Law 8:25

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloy JS (2009) Two concepts of trust. J Polit 71(2):492

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge J (1999) Altruistic trust. In: Warren ME (ed) Democracy & trust. Cambridge University Press, p 294 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Mashaw JL (1981) Administrative due process: the quest for a dignitary theory. Bost Univ Law Rev 885:61

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayntz R (1978) Soziologie deröffentlichen Verwaltung. Juristischer Verlag CF Müller, p 5

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes J (2009) Good Administration in EU Law and the European Code of Good Administrative Behaviour. EUI Working Paper 2009/09, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes J (2011) Participation in EU rule-making: a rights-based approach. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes J (2016a) The making of delegated and implementing acts: legitimacy beyond inter- institutional balances. In: Bergstöm CF, Ritleng D (eds) Law-making by the EU Commission: the new system. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes J (2016b) Discretion, care and public interests in the EU administration: probing the limits of the law. Common Mark Law Rev 53:419

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell LE (2001) The importance of being trusted. Bost Univ Law Rev 591:81

    Google Scholar 

  • Natelson RG (2004) The constitution and the public trust. Buffalo Law Rev 52:1077

    Google Scholar 

  • Nehl H-P (2009) Good administration as a procedural right and/ or general principle? In: Hofmann H, Türk A (eds) Legal challenges in EU administrative law. Edward Elgar. p 336 et seq, 339 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Nettesheim M (2005) Developing a theory of democracy for the European Union. Berkeley J Int Law 23(2):358

    Google Scholar 

  • Nullmeier F, Pritzlaff T (2010) The great chain of legitimacy – justifying transnational democracy. TranState Working Paper 123, Bremen

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill O (2002) A question of trust. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Offe C (1999) How can we trust our fellow citizens? In: Warren ME (ed) Democracy & trust. Cambridge University Press, p 51

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsen JP (2003) Towards a European administrative space? J Eur Publ Policy 10(4):506

    Google Scholar 

  • Palombella G (2016) Beyond legality – before democracy: rule of law caveats in the EU two-level system. In: Closa C, Kochenov D (eds) Reinforcing rule of law oversight in the European Union. Cambridge University Press, p 37

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson O (1999) Liberty against the democratic state: on the historical contemporary sources of American distrust. In: Warren ME (ed) Democracy & trust. Cambridge University Press, p 153

    Google Scholar 

  • Peerenboom R (2004) Varieties of rule of law. In: Peerenboom R (ed) Asian discourses of rule of law. Routledge, p 2

    Google Scholar 

  • Pesch U (2005) The Predicaments of Publicness. Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (1998) Republican theory and political trust. In: Braithwaite V, Levi M (eds) Trust & governance. Russel Sage Foundation, p 300 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Peuker E (2011) Bürokratie und Demokratie in Europa. Mohr Siebeck

    Google Scholar 

  • Philp M (2009) Delimiting democratic accountability. Polit Stud 57:28

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2001) Liberty and trust. In: George R (ed) Natural law, liberalism, and morality: contemporary essays. Oxford University Press, p 122 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Ribstein LE (2011) Fencing fiduciary duties. Bost Univ Law Rev 899:91

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson KG (1982) Public secrets: a study in the development of government secrecy, New York, p 19 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohr JA (2002) Dicey’s ghost and administrative law. Adm Soc 34(1):8

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein B, Teorell J (2008) What is quality of government? A theory of impartial government institutions. Governance 21(2):165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt-Aßmann E (2004) Der Rechtsstaat. In: Isensee J, Kirchhof P (eds) Handbuch des Staatsrechts, vol II, 3rd edn. p 542

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt VA (2015) The Eurozone’s Crisis of Democratic Legitimacy: Can the EU Rebuild Public Trust and Support for European Economic Integration? European Economy Discussion Paper 015, Luxembourg, pp 40–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarze J (2006) European administrative law, 2nd edn. Sweet and Maxwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidenfeld M (1992) A civic republican justification for the bureaucratic state. Harv Law Rev 105:1511

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro M (2001) The institutionalization of European administrative space. In: Sweet AS, Sandholtz W, Fligstein N (eds) The institutionalization of Europe. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 94

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro S (1987) The social control of impersonal trust. Am J Sociol 93(3):623

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro S (2012) The grammar of trust. In: Pixley J (ed) New perspectives on emotion in finance. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith L (2015) Loyalty and politics: from case law to statute law. J Equity 9:130

    Google Scholar 

  • Snellen I (2002) Conciliation of rationalities: the essence of public administration. Adm Theory Pract 24(2):323

    Google Scholar 

  • Somek A (2004) Dogmatischer Pragmatismus: die Normativitätskrise der Europäischen Union. In: Hammer S, and others (eds) Demokratie und sozialer Rechtsstaat in Europa: Festschrift für Theo Öhlinger. Wien, p 53 et seq

    Google Scholar 

  • Somek A (2008) Individualism. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sordi B (2010) Revolution, Rechtsstaat and the rule of law: historical reflections on the emergence of administrative law in Europe. In: Rose-Ackerman S, Lindseth P (eds) Comparative administrative law. Edward Elgar Publishing, p 33

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart J, Clarke M (1987) The public service orientation: issues and dilemmas. Public Adm 65:161

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart RB (1975) The reformation of American administrative law. Harv Law Rev 88(8):1667

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart RB (2014) Remedying disregard in global regulatory governance: accountability, participation and responsiveness. Am J Int Law 108:211

    Google Scholar 

  • Tamanaha BZ (2004) On the rule of law: history, politics, theory. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Tames R, Rosemont H (1998) The analects of Confucius: a philosophical translation. Ballantine Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomuschat C (1999) International law: ensuring the survival of mankind on the eve of a New Century. Recueil des cours: Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law, vol 281. Martinus Nijhoff, p 95

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakatika M (2005) Claims to legitimacy: the European Commission between continuity and change. J Common Mark Stud 43(1):193

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakatika M (2008) Political responsibility and the European Union. Manchester University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyler TR (1998) Trust and democratic governance. In: Braithwaite V, Levi M (eds) Trust & governance. Russel Sage Foundation, p 277

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyler TR, Huo YJ (2002) Trust in the law: encouraging cooperation with the police and the courts. Russell Sage Foundation, pp 62–63

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gestel R (2014) Primacy of the European legislature? Delegated rule-making and the decline of the “Transmission Belt” theory. Theory Pract Legis 2(1):33

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincze A (2018) Delegation versus implementation: a de-construction of the promise of the Lisbon treaty. In: Tauschinsky E, Weiß W (eds) The legislative choice between delegated and implementing acts in EU law: walking a labyrinth. Edward Elgar

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy A (2000) Information und Kommunikation in der Europäischen Union: föderale Strukturen in supranationalem Umfeld. In: Hoffmann-Riem W, Schmidt-Aßmann E (eds) Verwaltungsrecht in der Informationsgesellschaft. Nomos, p 150

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy A (2012) The European lesson for international democracy: the significance of Arts. 9-12 EU treaty for international organizations. Eur J Int Law 23(2):315, 326

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bogdandy A (2017) Jenseits der Rechtsgemeinschaft – Begriffsarbeit in der europäischen Sinn und Rechtsstaatlichkeitskrise. Eur Secur 4:487

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2002) Is the rule of law an essentially contested concept (in Florida)? Law Philos 21:137

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2012) How law protects dignity. Camb Law J 71(1):200

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker RM (2011) Market orientation and public service performance: new public management gone mad? Public Adm Rev 71(5):707

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren ME (1999) Democratic theory and trust. In: Warren ME (ed) Democracy and trust. Cambridge University Press, p 331

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson A (1962) The origins of Fiducia. Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte 79:329

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1964) Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Köln, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Wee C (2011) Xin, trust and confucius’ ethics. Philos East West 61(3):516

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil F (1987) The stranger, prudence, and trust in Hobbes’s theory. Theory Soc 759:15

    Google Scholar 

  • Wille A (2013) The normalization of the European Commission: politics and bureaucracy in the EU executive. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe C (2001) Being worthy of trust: a response to Joseph Raz. In: George R (ed) Natural law, liberalism, and morality: contemporary essays. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods N (1999) Good governance in international organizations. Glob Gov 5(1):39

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tauschinsky, R.E. (2020). Commission Discretion. In: A Fiduciary Approach to Delegated and Implementing Rule-Making in the EU. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-26300-3_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-26300-3_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-26299-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-26300-3

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics