Skip to main content

Modal Meinongianism: Conceiving the Impossible

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 18))

Abstract

Modal Meinongianism—the version of Meinongianism invented by Graham Priest—presupposes that we can think about absolute impossibilities. I defend the view that we can, by tidying up a couple of loose ends in Priest’s arguments to this effect from his book Towards Non-Being.

It is impossible to construct a regular polygon of nineteen sides with ruler and compass; it is possible but very complicated to construct one of seventeen sides. In whatever sense I can imagine the possible construction, I can imagine the impossible construction just as well

David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Priest dealt both with intentional states directed toward objects, such as fearing John, dreaming of Obama, imagining a tree in the garden, and with so-called propositional states, such as fearing that John comes along, dreaming that Obama wins the elections again, imagining that the tree starts talking to me. In the following, we will deal only with the latter kind of states.

  2. 2.

    Philosophers debate on the nature of absolute necessity, and thus impossibility, but it is fair to say that the three main kinds of absolute necessities/impossibilities are usually taken to be the logical, the mathematical and the metaphysical. I will not get into the issue of whether one of them is reducible to another (e.g., the mathematical to the logical, as it is for logicists).

  3. 3.

    As Yablo (1993), p. 4, has remarked, in spite of that “in other words” it is doubtful that here Hume is really giving the same maxim twice. It is one thing to say that, when we (clearly) conceive something, what is conceived comes with the idea that it could exist embedded in by default. It is another thing to say that we can only imagine the possible. It is the latter claim that will be on stage in the following, as the target (HP).

  4. 4.

    Contradictions are often invoked as a paradigmatic case of absolute impossibility, and will come handy later on, too. The example may not sound good in the context of a discussion of Priest’s work, given that he is (in)famous for believing that some contradictions are true. However, modal Meinongianism can be formulated as a consistent theory: one can be a modal Meinongian without thereby being a dialetheist.

  5. 5.

    I am very grateful to the Editors of Synthese for allowing me to reuse that material.

  6. 6.

    Arguments for the claim that we can conceive impossible situations can be found in Byrne (2007), Fiocco (2007), Jago (2014).

  7. 7.

    Triggered by a nice suggestion by two anonymous reviewers.

  8. 8.

    I do not buy this view either. Take a cognitive (as opposed to merely environmental) conception of information, and consider what can be learned by a rational, finite and fallible agent—one of us. We can learn that a complex formula, whose truth value we were ignorant of until we computed its long truth table, is a tautology. For all we knew before carrying out the computation, the formula’s being false was a way things could be. In this sense, pace Wittgenstein (6.1251), there are surprises in logic. A beautiful book defending this view is Jago (2014).

  9. 9.

    I agree with Yablo on this: “Almost never in philosophy are we able to analyze an intentional notion outright, in genuinely independent terms: so that a novice could learn, say, what memory and perception were just by consulting their analyses. About all one can normally hope for is to locate the target phenomenon relative to salient alternatives, and to find the kind of internal structure in it that would explain some of its characteristic behavior.” (Yablo 1993, pp. 25–6).

  10. 10.

    Here is a passage of Naming and Necessity, in which Kripke appears to endorse such an error theory. It is the famous example of the table: “But whatever we imagine counterfactually having happened to [the table] other than what actually did, one thing we cannot imagine happening to this thing is that it, given that it is composed of molecules, should still have existed and not have been composed of molecules. We can imagine having discovered that it wasn’t composed of molecules. But once we know that this is a thing composed of molecules—that this is the very nature of the substance of which it is made—we can’t then, at least if the way I see it is correct, imagine that this thing might have failed to have been composed of molecules.” (Kripke 1980, pp. 126–7).

  11. 11.

    “There is something amiss when a claim of the type ‘Suppose that Socrates had never gone into philosophy...’ is met with the challenge to demonstrate how you know that it is Socrates that is the object of your supposition. The same might be said of the question how you know that the subject of the proposition that Socrates is a philosopher is the same as the subject of the proposition that Socrates was married [...]. The theme that unites the last two deflationary thoughts is that one can ‘give’ a possible world or a representational content in a non-qualitative way by relying on stipulation.” (Divers 2002, p. 272).

  12. 12.

    “When I use the word ‘Socrates’ inside an explicitly worldly context, ‘at w’, or inside an implicitly worldly (modal or counterfactual) context [...] I do not thereby make it the case, nor do I come to know, that such a world is a possible world. It is this crucial point that underlies the complaint against [the claim that stipulative conceivability entails possibility]. It is one question how we know which objects are the objects of our de re modal thought and talk, and perhaps there stipulation has a legitimate role. It is another question altogether how we know what is modally true of those objects, and there stipulation has no legitimate role to play.” (Divers 2002, p. 273).

  13. 13.

    There is a different issue concerning cases in which one supposedly fails to conceive what one meant to conceive, nicely pointed out to me by an anonymous referee. The issue has to do with one’s lacking certain information which is plainly required for the stipulation to succeed. I’ll just pick the referee’s example: one thinks one imagines that Goldbach’s Conjecture has been refuted, but one has misunderstood the content of Goldbach’s Conjecture. In fact, what the person labels thus is the claim that there is a greatest prime number. It seems to me that in this case one actually misdescribes what one is conceiving, but that this failure is just orthogonal to the distinction between the stipulative and telescopic conceptions. In particular, it has little to do with “insufficient granularity” in the sense relevant for van Inwagen’s point: one can imagine in the greatest detail the standard proof that there is no largest prime while mistakenly labeling the proved claim as ‘the negation of Goldbach’s Conjecture’.

References

  • Balcerak Jackson, M. (2016). On imagining, supposing and conceiving. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2008). Modal meinoniganism for fictional objects. Metaphysics, 9, 205–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2012). Existence as a real property. Synthse Library. Dordrecht and New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2013). Impossible worlds. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F., & Schoonen, T. (2017). Conceivability and possibility: Some dilemmas for humeans. Synthese. Online first.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2007). Possibility and imagination. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 125–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–99). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chihara, C. (1998). The worlds of possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1967). Identity through possible worlds: Some questions. Noûs, 1, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Divers, J. (2002). Possible worlds. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiocco, M. (2007). Conceivability, imagination and modal knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 364–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. (2011). Imagination. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T., & Hawthorne, J. (Eds.). (2002). Conceivability and possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. (1997). Imagininability, conceivability, possibility and the mind-body problem. Philosophical Studies, 87, 61–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (1996). Meinongian logic: The Semantics of existence and nonexistence. DeGruyter: Berlin and New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jago, M. (2014). The impossible. An essay on hyperintensionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1969). Transworld heirlines. In M. Loux (Ed.), The possible and the actual (pp. 88–109). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiourti, I. (2010). Real impossible worlds: The bounds of possibility. PhD thesis, University of St Andrews.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 620–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2014). You really do imagine it: Against error theories of imagination. Nous, 50, 90–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, P. (2006). How things might have been: Individuals, kinds, and essential properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markman, K., Klein, W., & Surh, J. (Eds.). (2009). Handbook of imagination and mental simulation. New York: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (2013). Impossible worlds. Philosophy Compass, 8, 360–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1980). Nonexistent objects. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L., & Jago, M. (2013). Transworld identity. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/identity-transworld/.

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1998). What is so bad about contradictions? Journal of Philosophy, 95, 410–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being: The logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2nd expanded ed. 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language and reality (Philosophical Papers). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 48, 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rantala, V. (1982). Impossible world semantics and logical omniscience. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 35, 106–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. (1978). Meinongian theories and a russellian paradox. Noûs, 12, 153–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. (1980). Exploring Meinong’s jungle and beyond. Canberra: RSSS Australian National University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2007). Two conceivability arguments compared. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107, 27–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92, 67–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2015). Remarks on the logic of imagination: A step towards understanding doxastic control through imagination. Synthese. Online first.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2002). The conceivability of naturalism. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (pp. 401–39). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1983). Abstract objects: An introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1997). A classically-based theory of impossible worlds. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38, 640–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franz Berto .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Berto, F. (2019). Modal Meinongianism: Conceiving the Impossible. In: Başkent, C., Ferguson, T. (eds) Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-25365-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics