Skip to main content

Mathematical Proofs and Scientific Discovery

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Critical Reflection on Automated Science

Part of the book series: Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology ((HPHST,volume 1))

Abstract

The idea that science can be automated is so deeply related to the view that the method of mathematics is the axiomatic method, that confuting the claim that mathematical knowledge can be extended by means of the axiomatic method is almost equivalent to confuting the claim that science can be automated. I argue that the axiomatic view is inadequate as a view of the method of mathematics and that the analytic view is to be preferred. But, if the method of mathematics and natural sciences is the analytic method, then the advancement of knowledge cannot be mechanized, since non-deductive reasoning plays a crucial role in the analytic method, and non-deductive reasoning cannot be fully mechanized.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On CTM, see Rescorla (2017).

  2. 2.

    For a survey on Gödel’s theorems, see Raatikainen (2018).

  3. 3.

    This approach seems to forget that Hilbert did not seek formalization for the sake of formalization. Formalization was not an end, rather it was a means in Hilbert’s view. His main aim was to give a secure foundation to mathematics through the formalization of a part of it. And this goal cannot be reached because of Gödel’s results. So, it is difficult to overstate the relevance of those results for Hilbert’s view. That some limited portion of mathematics can be formalized or shown to be complete, but it is not possible to formalize the all of mathematics or prove its completeness in general, it is not something that can salvage Hilbert’s perspective “by changing its goals slightly,” rather it is a complete defeat of Hilbert’s view, since it shows the unfeasibility of its main goal. For example, according to Weyl, the relevance of Gödel’s results cannot be overstated, since because of those results the “ultimate foundations and the ultimate meaning of mathematics remain an open problem [...]. The undecisive outcome of Hilbert’s bold enterprise cannot fail to affect the philosophical interpretation” (Weyl 1949, p. 219).

  4. 4.

    The origin of the analytic method may be traced back to the works of the mathematician Hippocrates of Chios and the physician Hippocrates of Cos, and was firstly explicitly formulated by Plato in Meno, Phaedo and the Republic. Here I can only give a sketch of the analytic method. For an extensive presentation of the analytic view, see Cellucci (2013, 2017).

  5. 5.

    For a survey of the main conceptions of method that have been put forward so far, see Cellucci (2013, 2017). On the analytic method, see also Hintikka and Remes (1974), and Lakatos (1978, Vol. 2, Chap. 5). On the axiomatic method, see also Rodin (2014, part I).

  6. 6.

    The claim that in deduction the conclusion is contained in the premises has to be understood as meaning that the conclusion either is literally a part of the premises or implies nothing that is not already implied by the premises. The claim that deduction is non-ampliative has been disputed by some philosophers. For example, Dummett famously objects that, if deductive rules were non-ampliative, then, “as soon as we had acknowledged the truth of the axioms of a mathematical theory, we should thereby know all the theorems. Obviously, this is nonsense” (Dummett 1991, p. 195). On this issue, which cannot be treated here for reason of space, and for a possible rejoinder to Dummett’s objection, see Cellucci (2017, Sect. 12.7), and Sterpetti (2018, Sect. 6).

  7. 7.

    This view is controversial. For a defense of the claim that a logic of discovery has to be deductive, see e.g. Jantzen (2015).

  8. 8.

    On this sort of asymmetry between deductive and non-deductive reasoning with respect to mechanizability, cf. Cellucci (2017, p. 306): “there is no algorithm for discovering hypotheses, and hence for obtaining the solution [of a given mathematical problem] by analysis, while [...] there is an algorithm for enumerating all deductions from given axioms, and hence for obtaining the solution [of that problem] by synthesis.”

  9. 9.

    This view can, at least in part, be traced back to Lakatos (1976), where Lakatos, by relying on the work of Pólya, strongly criticized the occultation of the heuristic steps that are crucial to the development of mathematics.

  10. 10.

    For an extensive treatment of this issue, see Cellucci (2013, Sect. 20.4); Sterpetti and Bertolaso (2018).

  11. 11.

    I cannot analyse here the discoveries allegedly made by computer programs. This is a topic for future research. Briefly, the main questions one has to address when dealing with this issue are: (1) whether hypotheses are really produced by programs, since often either a set of hypotheses or a set of heuristic strategies to routinely produce hypotheses from given inputs are already present in the so-called background knowledge of programs (see e.g. Marcus 2018); (2) whether programs can only produce results that can be obtained through a merely exploratory search of a well-defined space of possibilities, or they are also able to make innovative discoveries, i.e. discoveries that originate from the formulation of new concepts, i.e. concepts that cannot easily be derived from current ones, and modify the very space of possibilities (see e.g. Wiggins 2006).

  12. 12.

    On whether mathematics is theorem proving or problem solving, see Cellucci (2017, Chap. 20).

  13. 13.

    For a defense of the claim that the axiomatic view is inadequate also because there is no non-circular way of proving that deduction is truth-preserving, see Cellucci (2006).

  14. 14.

    In fact, things are more complicated. When one climbs the hierarchy of sets, the stronger axioms that become available lead to “more intractable instances of undecidable sentences” (Koellner 2011, Sect. 1). For example, at the third infinite level one can formulate Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis. These instances of independence “are more intractable in that no simple iteration of the hierarchy of types leads to their resolution” (Ibidem). I will not address this issue here.

  15. 15.

    On disagreement in mathematics, see Sterpetti (2018).

  16. 16.

    On this issue, see Sterpetti (2018).

  17. 17.

    For an account of the resolution of Fermat’s Last Theorem inspired by the analytic view, see (Cellucci 2017, Sect. 12.13).

  18. 18.

    This claim might appear disputable to those who claim that ampliative reasoning is actually performed by machines. As already said, for reason of space, I have to leave the analysis of the claim that machines do autonomously perform ampliative reasoning for future work.

References

  • Alama, J., and J. Korbmacher. 2018. The Lambda Calculus. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/lambda-calculus/.

  • Allen, J.F. 2001. In Silico Veritas. Data-Mining and Automated Discovery: The Truth Is in There. EMBO Reports 2: 542–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C. 2008. The End of Theory: The Data Deluge Makes the Scientific Method Obsolete. Wired Magazine, 23 June.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, F. 1961–1986. Works. Stuttgart Bad Cannstatt: Frommann Holzboog.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. 2016. Non-Deductive Methods in Mathematics. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/mathematics-nondeductive/.

  • Bell, J., and G. Hellman. 2006. Pluralism and the Foundations of Mathematics. In: Scientific Pluralism, ed. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, 64–79. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. 1990. On “Seeing” the Truth of the Gödel Sentence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 655–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Introductory Note to *1951. In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume III, ed. S. Feferman et al., 290–304. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byers, W. 2007. How Mathematicians Think. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calude, C.S., and D. Thompson. 2016. Incompleteness, Undecidability and Automated Proofs. In: Computer Algebra in Scientific Computing. CASC 2016, ed. V. Gerdt et al., 134–155. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. 2006. The Question Hume Didn’t Ask: Why Should We Accept Deductive Inferences? In: Demonstrative and Non-Demonstrative Reasoning, ed. C. Cellucci and P. Pecere, 207–235. Cassino: Edizioni dell’Università degli Studi di Cassino.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Why Proof? What is a Proof? In: Deduction, Computation, Experiment. Exploring the Effectiveness of Proof, ed. R. Lupacchini and G. Corsi, 1–27. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Si può meccanizzare l’induzione? In: Vittorio Somenzi. Antologia e Testimonianze 1918-2003, B. Continenza et al. (a cura di), 362–364. Mantova: Fondazione Banca Agricola Mantovana.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Rethinking Logic. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Rethinking Knowledge. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colton, S. 2002. Automated Theory Formation in Pure Mathematics. London: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curry, H.B. 1934. Functionality in Combinatory Logic. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 20: 584–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. 1990. Is Mathematical Insight Algorithmic? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 659–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Introductory Note to *193? In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume III, ed. S. Feferman et al., 156–163. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 1991. The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dybjer, P., and E. Palmgren. 2016. Intuitionistic Type Theory. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/type-theory-intuitionistic/.

  • Feferman, S. 1998. In the Light of Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. 1990. Strong AI and the Problem of “Second-Order” Algorithms. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 663–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. 1991. The Hierarchies of Knowledge and the Mathematics of Discovery. Minds and Machines 1: 75–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. *193?. Undecidable Diophantine Propositions. In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume III (1995), ed. S. Feferman et al., 164–175. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1951. Some Basic Theorems on the Foundations of Mathematics and Their Implications. In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume III (1995), ed. S. Feferman et al., 304–323. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. *1961/?. The Modern Development of the Foundations of Mathematics in the Light of Philosophy. In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume III (1995), ed. S. Feferman et al., 374–387. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964. What Is Cantor’s Continuum Problem? In: Kurt Gödel. Collected Works. Volume II (1990), ed. S. Feferman et al., 254–270. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 19834. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamming, R.W. 1980. The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics. The American Mathematical Monthly 87: 81–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, P.J. 1973. Computation and Deduction. In: Proceedings of the 2nd Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science Symposium, 105–118. Prague: Czechoslovak Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. 1970. Axiomatic Thinking. Philosophia Mathematica, ser. 1, 7: 1–12, 1st ed., 1918.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., and U. Remes. 1974. The Method of Analysis. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L. 2015. Philosophy of Mathematics. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/philosophy-mathematics/.

  • Horsten, L., and P. Welch. 2016. Introduction. In: Gödel’s Disjunction, ed. L. Horsten and P. Welch, 1–l5. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, W.A. 1980. The Formulae-as-Types Notion of Construction. In: To H.B. Curry. Essays on Combinatory Logic, Lambda Calculus and Formalism, ed. J.R. Hindley and J.P. Seldin, 479–490. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jantzen, B.C. 2015. Discovery Without a ‘Logic’ Would Be a Miracle. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0926-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1992. Lectures on Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • King, R.D., et al. 2009. The Automation of Science. Science 324: 85–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koellner, P. 2011. Independence and Large Cardinals. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/independence-large-cardinals/.

  • ———. 2014. Large Cardinals and Determinacy. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/large-cardinals-determinacy/.

  • ———. 2016. Gödel’s Disjunction. In: Gödel’s Disjunction, ed. L. Horsten and P. Welch, 148–188. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R.A. 1979. Algorithm = Logic + Control. Communications of the ACM 22: 424–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.A. 2013. The Church-Turing ‘Thesis’ as a Special Corollary of Gödel’s Completeness Theorem. In: Computability, ed. B.J. Copeland, C.J. Posy, and O. Shagrir, 77–104. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. 1976. Proofs and Refutations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Philosophical Papers. In 2 Vol. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P.S. 1951. A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities, 1st French edition, 1814. New York: Dover Publications

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1981. A Confutation of Convergent Realism. Philosophy of Science 48: 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leach-Krouse, G. 2016. Provability, Mechanism, and the Diagonal Problem. In: Gödel’s Disjunction, ed. L. Horsten and P. Welch, 211–242. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G. 2003. Proofs and Programs. Synthese 134: 85–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Reflections on Concrete Incompleteness. Philosophia Mathematica 19: 255–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, J.R. 1961. Minds, Machines, and Gödel. Philosophy 36: 112–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. 1988. Believing the Axioms I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53: 481–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäenpää, P. 1997. From Backward Reduction to Configurational Analysis. In Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics: History and Philosophy, ed. M. Otte and M. Panza, 201–226. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, G. 2018. Innateness, AlphaZero, and Artificial Intelligence. arXiv:1801.05667v1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matiyasevič, Y. 2003. Enumerable Sets Are Diophantine. In: Mathematical Logic in the 20th Century, ed. G.E. Sacks, 269–273. Singapore: Singapore University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mazzocchi, F. 2015. Could Big Data Be the End of Theory in Science? A Few Remarks on the Epistemology of Data-Driven Science. EMBO Reports 16: 1250–1255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muggleton, S., and L. De Raedt. 1994. Inductive Logic Programming. Theory and Methods. Journal of Logic Programming 19–20: 629–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., J.C. Shaw, and H.A. Simon. 1957. Empirical Explorations of the Logic Theory Machine: A Case Study in Heuristic. In: Proceedings of the 1957 Western Joint Computer Conference, 218–230. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. 1989. The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pólya, G. 1941. Heuristic Reasoning and the Theory of Probability. The American Mathematical Monthly 48: 450–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 2005. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Portoraro, F. 2019. Automated Reasoning. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/reasoning-automated/.

  • Prawitz, D. 2008. Proofs Verifying Programs and Programs Producing Proofs: A Conceptual Analysis. In: Deduction, Computation, Experiment. Exploring the Effectiveness of Proof, ed. R. Lupacchini and G. Corsi, 81–94. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The Status of Mathematical Knowledge. In: From a Heuristic Point of View. Essays in Honour of Carlo Cellucci, ed. E. Ippoliti and C. Cozzo, 73–90. Newcastle Upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raatikainen, P. 2005. On the Philosophical Relevance of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. Revue internationale de philosophie 4: 513–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/goedel-incompleteness/.

  • Rathjen, M., and W. Sieg. 2018. Proof Theory. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/proof-theory/.

  • Rescorla, M. 2017. The Computational Theory of Mind. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/computational-mind/.

  • Rodin, A. 2014. Axiomatic Method and Category Theory. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schickore, J. 2014. Scientific Discovery. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/scientific-discovery/.

  • Shapiro, S. 2016. Idealization, Mechanism, and Knowability. In: Gödel’s Disjunction, ed. L. Horsten and P. Welch, 189–207. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sørensen, M.H., and P. Urzyczyn. 2006. Lectures on the Curry-Howard Isomorphism. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sparkes, A., et al. 2010. Towards Robot Scientists for Autonomous Scientific Discovery. Automated Experimentation 2: 1. https://doi.org/10.1186/1759-4499-2-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterpetti, F. 2018. Mathematical Knowledge and Naturalism. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-9953-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterpetti, F., and M. Bertolaso. 2018. The Pursuit of Knowledge and the Problem of the Unconceived Alternatives. Topoi. An International Review of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9551-7.

  • von Plato, J. 2018. The Development of Proof Theory. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/proof-theory-development/.

  • Wadler, P. 2015. Propositions as Types. Communications of the ACM 58: 75–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. 1949. Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, G.A. 2006. Searching for Computational Creativity. New Generation Computing 24: 209–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2016. Absolute Provability and Safe Knowledge of Axioms. In: Gödel’s Disjunction, ed. L. Horsten and P. Welch, 243–253. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wos, L., F. Pereira, R. Hong, et al. 1985. An Overview of Automated Reasoning and Related Fields. Journal of Automated Reasoning 1: 5–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zach, R. 2016. Hilbert’s Program. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/hilbert-program/.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Carlo Cellucci for careful reading and commenting on an earlier draft of this chapter.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabio Sterpetti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sterpetti, F. (2020). Mathematical Proofs and Scientific Discovery. In: Bertolaso, M., Sterpetti, F. (eds) A Critical Reflection on Automated Science. Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-25001-0_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics