Skip to main content

Before and After Legal Positivity: Peremptory Norms from Global and Transnational Social Practice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Legal Positivism in a Global and Transnational Age

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 131))

  • 874 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter examines the difficulties legal positivism faces explaining the formation and content of peremptory norms. On the one hand, these norms have a universal, peremptory and non-derogable character, based on the importance of their content, which appears to be in tension with the positivist vision of international law as an artificial creation, grounded on state sovereignty and consent. On the other hand, there is the seemingly paradoxical claim that peremptory norms arise from state practice, requiring acceptance and recognition by the international community as a whole. Unravelling this paradox, requires an explanation that reaches beyond the formal sources of international law, to the normative social foundations for international legal order and obligation. The chapter argues that this requires an enquiry into the social foundations for legal obligation as such, which runs counter to the methodological underpinnings of legal positivism, and touches upon the necessary moral foundations to any legal system. An adequate justification of peremptory norms in any legal order requires the setting aside of mistaken understandings of the relationship between social practice, reasons and rules within the positivist tradition; and the recovery of an account of norms constitutive of social cooperation to achieve common ends. With that recovery, the chapter explores some workable foundations for understanding peremptory norms, as ethical foundations to legal order and evaluative criteria for the integration of global, transnational and national legal orders.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Orakhelashvili (2006), p. 32.

  2. 2.

    Sztucki (1974), p. 64; Weil (1983); Koskenniemi (2005a), pp. 309–325.

  3. 3.

    Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), 23 May 1969, 1155 UNTS 331, Art. 53.

  4. 4.

    Hall (2001), pp. 269–284; Rommen (1998), pp. 62–138.

  5. 5.

    Lotus Case, 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, 18.

  6. 6.

    Weil (1983), p. 421.

  7. 7.

    Lotus Case, 18.

  8. 8.

    Weil (1983), pp. 420–423.

  9. 9.

    Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties between States and International Organizations, 21 March 1986 (not yet in force).

  10. 10.

    ILC, Draft articles on responsibility of states for internationally wrongful acts, with commentaries [2001] Yearbook of the International Law Commission, Vol. II, Part Two.

  11. 11.

    Kolb (2015), p. 2.

  12. 12.

    Kolb (2015), ch 1.

  13. 13.

    Finnis (2011a), ch 1; Finnis (2000).

  14. 14.

    Tasioulas (2016), pp. 107–108.

  15. 15.

    Case Concerning Barcelona Traction, Light and Power Company, Limited [1970] ICJ Rep. 3, p. 32. See also: Byers (1997) and De Wet (2013).

  16. 16.

    ILC (1966), p. 248.

  17. 17.

    Janis (1988), pp. 362–363; Kolb (2015), chs 1 and 4.

  18. 18.

    O’Connell (2014), pp. 84–85.

  19. 19.

    American Law Institute, Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States (1987), §102, comment k; §702, illustration 11.

  20. 20.

    ILC (2006), p. 189.

  21. 21.

    Kolb (2015), chs 5 and 6.

  22. 22.

    See e.g. Retter (2011), pp. 540–548; Criddle and Fox-Decent (2009), pp. 339–342.

  23. 23.

    Weil (1983), p. 427.

  24. 24.

    Shaw (2008), pp. 126–127.

  25. 25.

    Criddle and Fox-Decent (2009), pp. 339–340.

  26. 26.

    Hall (2001), pp. 289–291.

  27. 27.

    Lesaffer (2009), pp. 437–438.

  28. 28.

    For discussion on the conceptual coherence of a relative understanding of sovereignty (as opposed to absolute) see Jorge Emilio Núñez’s chapter in this book. Whether relative or absolute, the question still remains as to why prior acts of state can bind subsequent acts.

  29. 29.

    Triepel (1899). See also: Nussbaum (1954), pp. 234–236; Hall (2001), pp. 283–284; Lev (2011), pp. 137–138.

  30. 30.

    MacGibbon (1954).

  31. 31.

    Brierly (1963), pp. 51–52.

  32. 32.

    Santos (1987), pp. 297–298; Santos (2002), p. 437; Twining (2000), pp. 229–231.

  33. 33.

    Kelsen (1949), pp. 1–40; Rigaux (1998), pp. 329–341.

  34. 34.

    Kelsen (1949), pp. 111 and 116–117.

  35. 35.

    Kelsen (1949), p. 33; Kelsen (1967), p. 119.

  36. 36.

    Kelsen (1949), p. 115.

  37. 37.

    Kelsen (1949), p. 351; Hart (1983), pp. 317–321.

  38. 38.

    Kelsen (1949), p. 369; Kelsen (1952), pp. 417–418.

  39. 39.

    Kelsen (1949), pp. 325–327 and 363–388.

  40. 40.

    Rigaux (1998).

  41. 41.

    Hart (1983), Twining (2009), ch 15.4.

  42. 42.

    Weatherall (2015), Hanna (2018). See e.g. Al-Adsani v. United Kingdom (2001), Merits, App. No. 35763/97, [2001] ECHR 761; Siderman de Blake v. Argentina, 965 F.2d 699 (1992); Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (DRC v. Rwanda), Jurisdiction and Admissibility [2006] ICJ Rep. 6; Jurisdictional Immunities of the State (Germany v. Italy: Greece Intervening) [2012] ICJ Rep. 99.

  43. 43.

    Lujpen (1967), pp. 28–35.

  44. 44.

    Hart (1994), p. 236.

  45. 45.

    Hart (1994), p. 234.

  46. 46.

    For further discussion of the problem of the relationship between Kelsen’s system of norm and legal practice see Matthew Nicholson’s chapter in this book.

  47. 47.

    Kant (1996), p. 17.

  48. 48.

    Kelsen (1949), p. 437.

  49. 49.

    Hart (1994), pp. 84–91 and 100–110.

  50. 50.

    Finnis (2011b), pp. 104–109.

  51. 51.

    Hart (1994), pp. 193–200.

  52. 52.

    For discussion on Hart’s views on the legal character of international law see Richard Collins’ chapter in this book.

  53. 53.

    Hart (1994), pp. 289, 297; McCormick (1978), pp. 278–279; Rodriguez-Blanco (2007).

  54. 54.

    Winch (1990), pp. 71–88. See also: MacIntyre (1971).

  55. 55.

    Winch (1990), ch 2.

  56. 56.

    Winch (1990), pp. 42–61.

  57. 57.

    Hart (1994), pp. 9–10 and 89.

  58. 58.

    McCormick (1978), p. 284.

  59. 59.

    Hart (1994), p. 89.

  60. 60.

    Rodriguez-Blanco (2007), pp. 456–460.

  61. 61.

    Hart (1994), p. 57.

  62. 62.

    Hart (1994), p. 86.

  63. 63.

    McCormick (1978), pp. 284–292. See also: Hart (1994), pp. 255–259; Hart (1982), pp. 255–261.

  64. 64.

    Hart (1994), p. 94.

  65. 65.

    Hart (1983), pp. 339–342; Hart (1994), pp. 292–293.

  66. 66.

    Hart (1994), p. 256.

  67. 67.

    Hart (1994), pp. 112–117; Hart (1982), pp. 262–268.

  68. 68.

    Rodriguez-Blanco (2007).

  69. 69.

    Finnis (2011c).

  70. 70.

    MacIntyre (1971), pp. 217–222.

  71. 71.

    Hart (1982), p. 262.

  72. 72.

    Anscombe (1981), Finnis (2011a), pp. 245–252; Finnis (2000), pp. 1607–1611; Rodriguez-Blanco (2014), ch 8.

  73. 73.

    Hart (1982), p. 265.

  74. 74.

    Hart (1994), p. 193.

  75. 75.

    Hart (1994), pp. 193–200.

  76. 76.

    Hart (1994), p. 192.

  77. 77.

    Hart (1994), p. 193.

  78. 78.

    Hart (1994), p. 192.

  79. 79.

    Hart (1958), pp. 622–623; Hart (1994), pp. 188–191.

  80. 80.

    Finnis (2011c), p. 256; Finnis (2011d), pp. 262–265; MacIntyre (1998c), pp. 241–243; Simon (1980), pp. 23–31.

  81. 81.

    Finnis (2011b), p. 112.

  82. 82.

    Finnis (2011a), pp. 141–156.

  83. 83.

    MacIntyre (1997), pp. 98–99.

  84. 84.

    MacIntyre (1998a), p. 123.

  85. 85.

    MacIntyre (1998a), p. 123.

  86. 86.

    MacIntyre (2007), pp. 187–191.

  87. 87.

    Dupré (1993), p. 687.

  88. 88.

    MacIntyre (2007), pp. 190–191; MacIntyre (1990), pp. 61–63.

  89. 89.

    MacIntyre (2007), pp. 194–195.

  90. 90.

    MacIntyre (2007), p. 190; MacIntyre (1978), pp. 28–30.

  91. 91.

    MacIntyre (2007), pp. 204–225; MacIntyre (2016), pp. 231–242.

  92. 92.

    MacIntyre (1999).

  93. 93.

    MacIntyre (1998c) and MacIntyre (1999), pp. 113–146.

  94. 94.

    MacIntyre (1988), pp. 198–202; MacIntyre (1999), pp. 109–111.

  95. 95.

    MacIntyre (2009), p. 23. See also: MacIntyre (1990), pp. 133–137; MacIntyre (2016), pp. 88–89.

  96. 96.

    Finnis (2011a), ch IX; Simon (1980), pp. 31–50.

  97. 97.

    Finnis (2011a), pp. 354–362; Finnis (2000).

  98. 98.

    Retter (2015), pp. 9–19.

  99. 99.

    O’Connell (2014), p. 97; Uhlmann (1998), pp. 122–127.

  100. 100.

    O’Connell (2014), pp. 90–93 and p. 98.

  101. 101.

    Criddle and Fox-Decent (2009) and Benvenisti (2013).

  102. 102.

    Aristotle (2009), I:2, 1252b27-31; Finnis (2011a), pp. 149–150; Tasioulas (1996), pp. 116–123; Simon (1993), pp. 63–68.

  103. 103.

    Weil (1983), pp. 418–419; Tasioulas (1996).

  104. 104.

    Retter (2011), pp. 561–566; Domingo (2012).

  105. 105.

    Schmidt (2016), p. 278.

  106. 106.

    Twining (2010), p. 504. See also: Held et al. (1999), Twining (2004), Tamahana (2008), pp. 386–390; Domingo (2010), pp. 55–57.

  107. 107.

    Santos (1987), pp. 297–298.

  108. 108.

    MacIntyre (1999), p. 160; MacIntyre (2009), p. 24.

  109. 109.

    MacIntyre (1999), pp. 124–126 and 158–159.

  110. 110.

    See e.g. Sztucki (1974), p. 64; Shelton (2015), p. 34; Guan (2017), pp. 469–470.

  111. 111.

    Tasioulas (1996), p. 120; Retter (2011), pp. 569–571.

  112. 112.

    Orakhelashvili (2006); Retter (2011), pp. 566–568.

  113. 113.

    Lauterpacht (1970), p. 358.

  114. 114.

    D’Amato (1990), Shelton (2015), pp. 34–48; Guan (2017).

  115. 115.

    Verdross (1966), Radbruch (2006), Rommen (1959). See also: O’Connell (2014), p. 88.

  116. 116.

    O’Connell (2014), pp. 79 and 93–97.

  117. 117.

    MacIntyre (2006, 2009).

  118. 118.

    O’Connell (2014), pp. 80–81 and 93–97.

  119. 119.

    See e.g. Weil (1983), pp. 424–429, 440–441; Saul (2014), Shelton (2015) and Guan (2017).

  120. 120.

    MacIntyre (2009), pp. 22–27; MacIntyre (1998b), pp. 142–144; MacIntyre (1990), pp. 133–137; MacIntyre (1988), pp. 193–196; Simon (1991).

  121. 121.

    Weil (1983), p. 426.

  122. 122.

    Simon (1980), pp. 47–60; MacIntyre (1998c), pp. 240–241; MacIntyre (2009), pp. 12–15; Finnis (2011a), pp. 144–147 and 154–156.

  123. 123.

    Twining (2011), p. 368. See also: Griffiths (1986), Cotterrell (1998), Berman (2007), pp. 1159–1164; Tamahana (2008), pp. 375–390; Twining (2010) and Michaels (2013).

  124. 124.

    By ‘appropriately’ I refer to principles of procedural morality for governance by law: Fuller (1977), Finnis (2011a), pp. 270–276.

  125. 125.

    Aristotle (2009), I:2, 1252b27-31; Finnis (2011a), pp. 147–156; Domingo (2010), pp. 102–106; Domingo (2012); Simon (1993), pp. 63–68.

  126. 126.

    Twining (2010), pp. 482–484.

  127. 127.

    See e.g. Fischer-Lescano and Teubner (2004) and Barzilai (2008).

  128. 128.

    Aquinas (1947), I–II, Q.94; Rommen (1998), pp. 195–203; MacIntyre (1984, 1998b), pp. 142–144.

  129. 129.

    O’Connell (2014), p. 88.

  130. 130.

    See e.g. Reynolds v. United States 98 U.S. 145 (1879), p. 166.

  131. 131.

    See e.g. Standen (2009).

  132. 132.

    See e.g. TransLex Principles, Principle No. IV.7.1.

  133. 133.

    See e.g. UN Global Compact, Principle 4; Responsible Business Alliance Code of Conduct, A.1.

  134. 134.

    See e.g. Bell (2013), pp. 187 and 190–193; Kastner (2012).

  135. 135.

    Weil (1983), p. 441.

  136. 136.

    Schmidt (2016), p. 283.

  137. 137.

    See e.g. Koskenniemi (2005a), pp. 324–325; Koskenniemi (2005b), p. 197; Bianchi (2008), Shelton (2015) and Guan (2017).

  138. 138.

    D’Aspremont (2015).

References

  • Anscombe GEM (1981) On the source of the authority of the state. In: Anscombe GEM (ed) Ethics, religion and politics: collected philosophical papers, vol III. Basil Blackwell, Oxford, pp 130–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas T (1947) Summa theologiae (trans: Fathers of the English Dominican Province). Benziger Brothers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (2009) The politics (trans Ernest B). Revised edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzilai G (2008) Beyond relativism: where is political power in legal pluralism? Theor Enquiries Law 9:395–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell C (2013) Of jus post bellum and lex pacificatoria: what’s in a name? In: Stahn C, Easterday J, Iverson J (eds) Jus post bellum: mapping the normative foundations. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 181–206

    Google Scholar 

  • Benvenisti E (2013) Sovereigns as trustees of humanity: on the accountability of states to foreign stakeholders. Am J Int Law 107(2):295–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman PS (2007) Global legal pluralism. South Calif Law Rev 80:1155–1237

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi A (2008) Human rights and the magic of jus cogens. Eur J Int Law 19(3):491–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brierly JL (1963) In: Waldock SH (ed) The law of nations: an introduction to the international law of peace, 6th edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Byers M (1997) Conceptualising the relationship between jus cogens and erga omnes rules. Nordic J Int Law 66(2):211–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cotterrell R (1998) Law and community: a new relationship? Curr Leg Probl 51:367–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Criddle E, Fox-Decent E (2009) A fiduciary theory of jus cogens. Yale J Int Law 34(2):331–387

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Amato A (1990) It’s a bird, it’s a plane, it’s jus cogens! Conn J Int Law 6(1):1–6

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Aspremont J (2015) Jus cogens as a social construct without pedigree. Neth Yearb Int Law 46:85–114

    Google Scholar 

  • De Wet E (2013) Jus cogens and obligations erga omnes. In: Shelton D (ed) The Oxford handbook of international human rights law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 541–561

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Domingo R (2010) The new global law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Domingo R (2012) The new global human community. Chic J Int Law 12(2):563–587

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré L (1993) The common good and the open society. Rev Polit 55(4):687–712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2000) On the incoherence of legal positivism. Notre Dame Law Rev 75(5):1597–1611

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011a) Natural law and natural rights, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011b) Reason, authority, and friendship. In: Finnis J (ed) Reason in action: collected essays, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 104–124

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011c) On Hart’s ways: law as reasons and as fact. In: Finnis J (ed) Philosophy of law: collected essays, vol IV. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 230–256

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011d) Hart as a political philosopher. In: Finnis J (ed) Philosophy of law: collected essays, vol IV. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 257–279

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer-Lescano A, Teubner G (2004) Regime-collisions: the vain search for legal unity in the fragmentation of global law. Mich J Int Law 25(4):999–1046

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller L (1977) The morality of law, Revised edn. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths J (1986) What is legal pluralism? J Legal Pluralism Unofficial Law 24:1–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guan S (2017) Jus cogens: to revise a narrative. Minn J Int Law 26(2):461–499

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall S (2001) The persistent spectre: natural law, international order and the limits of legal positivism. Eur J Int Law 12(2):269–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna M (2018) The substantive/procedural distinction: law’s solution to the problem of Jus cogens in a world of sovereign states. German Law J 19(1):22–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and morality. Harv Law Rev 71(4):593–628

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1982) Commands and authoritative reasons. In: Hart HLA (ed) Essays on Bentham: jurisprudence and political theory. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 243–268

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1983) Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law. In: Hart HLA (ed) Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 309–342

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1994) The concept of law, 2nd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Held D, McGrew A, Goldblatt D, Perraton J (1999) Global transformations: politics, economics, culture. Polity Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • ILC (1966) Report of the International Law Commission on the work of its eighteenth session. Yearb Int Law Comm I, Part II:172–363

    Google Scholar 

  • ILC (2006) Report of the International Law Commission on fragmentation of International Law: difficulties arising from the diversification and expansion of international law. UN Doc. A/CN.4/L.682

    Google Scholar 

  • Janis M (1988) The nature of jus cogens. Conn J Int Law 3:359–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1996) The metaphysics of morals (trans: Gregor M). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastner P (2012) Towards internalized legal obligations to address justice and accountability? A novel perspective on the legal framework of peace negotiations. Crim Law Forum 23:193–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1949) General theory of law and state (trans: Wedberg A). Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1952) Principles of international law. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1967) The pure theory of law, 2nd edn (trans: Knight M). University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolb R (2015) Peremptory international law – jus cogens: a general inventory. Hart, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi M (2005a) From apology to utopia: the structure of international legal argument. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi M (2005b) International law in Europe: between tradition and renewal. Eur J Int Law 16(1):113–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauterpacht H (1970) International law: being the collected papers of Hersch Lauterpacht: volume 1—the general works. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lesaffer R (2009) European legal history: a cultural and political perspective. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lev A (2011) The transformation of international law in the 19th century. In: Orakhelashvili A (ed) Research handbook on the theory and history of international law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 111–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Lujpen W (1967) Phenomenology of natural law. Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • MacGibbon IC (1954) The scope of acquiescence in international law. Br Yearb Int Law 31:143–186

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1971) The idea of a social science. In: MacIntyre A (ed) Against the self-images of the age: essays on ideology and philosophy. Duckworth, London, pp 211–229

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1978) Objectivity in morality and objectivity in science. In: Engelhardt HT, Callahan D (eds) Moral, science and sociality. Hastings Center, New York, pp 21–39

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1984) Does applied ethics rest on a mistake? Monist 67(4):498–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1988) Whose justice? Which rationality? University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN)

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1990) Three rival versions of moral enquiry. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1997) Natural law reconsidered. Int Philos Q 37(1):95–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1998a) Practical rationalities as forms of social structure. In: Knight K (ed) The MacIntyre reader. Polity Press, Oxford, pp 120–135

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1998b) Plain persons and moral philosophies: rules, virtues and goods. In: Knight K (ed) The MacIntyre reader. Polity Press, Oxford, pp 136–152

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1998c) Politics, philosophy and the common good. In: Knight K (ed) The MacIntyre reader. Polity Press, Oxford, pp 235–252

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1999) Dependent rational animals: why human beings need the virtues. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (2006) First principles, final ends, and contemporary philosophical issues. In: MacIntyre A (ed) The tasks of philosophy: selected essays, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 143–178

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (2007) After virtue, 3rd edn. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN)

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (2009) Intractable moral disagreements. In: Cunningham L (ed) Intractable disputes about the natural law: Alasdair MacIntyre and critics. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN), pp 1–52

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (2016) Ethics in the conflicts of modernity: an essay on desire, practical reasoning, and narrative. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick N (1978) Legal reasoning and legal theory. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels R (2013) Globalization and law. Law beyond the state. In: Banakar R, Travers M (eds) Law and social theory. Hart, Oxford, pp 287–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum A (1954) A concise history of the law of nations, Revised edn. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell ME (2014) Jus cogens: international law’s higher ethical norms. In: Childress DE (ed) The role of ethics in international law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 78–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Orakhelashvili A (2006) Peremptory norms in international law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Radbruch G (2006) Statutory lawlessness and supra-statutory law (1946). Oxf J Leg Stud 26(1):1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Retter M (2011) Jus cogens: towards an international common good? Transnational Legal Theory 2(4):537–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Retter M (2015) Internal goods to legal practice: reclaiming Fuller with MacIntyre. UCL J Law Jurisprudence 4(1):1–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigaux F (1998) Hans Kelsen on international law. Eur J Int Law 9(2):325–343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Blanco V (2007) Peter Winch and H.L.A. Hart: two concepts of the internal point of view. Can J Law Jurisprudence 20(2):453–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Blanco V (2014) Law and authority under the guise of the good. Hart, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommen H (1959) Natural law in decisions of the Federal Supreme Court and of the constitutional courts in Germany. Natural Law Forum 4(1):1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommen H (1998) The natural law: a study in legal and social history and philosophy. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos B d S (1987) Law: a map of misreading. Toward a postmodern conception of law. J Law Soc 14(3):279–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santos B d S (2002) Toward a new legal common sense: law, globalization and emancipation, 2nd edn. Butterworths, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul M (2014) Identifying jus cogens norms: the interaction of scholars and international judges. Asian J Int Law 5(1):26–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt D (2016) Peremptory law, global order, and the normative boundaries of a pluralistic world. Int Theory 8(2):262–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw M (2008) International law, 6th edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shelton D (2015) Sherlock Holmes and the mystery of Jus cogens. Neth Yearb Int Law 34(1):23–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon Y (1980) A general theory of authority. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN)

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon Y (1991) Practical knowledge (trans: Mulvaney R). Fordham University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon Y (1993) Philosophy of democratic government. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN)

    Google Scholar 

  • Standen J (2009) The manly sports: the problematic use of criminal law to regulate sports violence. J Crim Law Criminol 99(3):619–642

    Google Scholar 

  • Sztucki J (1974) Jus cogens and the Vienna convention on the law of treaties: a critical appraisal. Springer, Vienna

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tamahana B (2008) Understanding legal pluralism: past to present, local to global. Sydney Law Rev 30:375–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (1996) In defence of relative normativity: communitarian values and the Nicaragua case. Oxf J Leg Stud 16(1):85–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (2016) Custom, jus cogens, and human rights. In: Bradley C (ed) Custom’s future: international law in a changing world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 95–116

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Triepel H (1899) Völkerrecht und landesrecht. C.L. Hirschfeld, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2000) Globalisation and legal theory. Northwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2004) Diffusion of law: a global perspective. J Legal Pluralism 34(4):1–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2009) General jurisprudence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2010) Normative and legal pluralism: a global perspective. Duke J Comp Int Law 20:473–518

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (2011) Responding to globalization. Osgoode Hall Law J 49(2):353–373

    Google Scholar 

  • Uhlmann E (1998) State community interests, Jus cogens and protection of the global environment: developing criteria for peremptory norms. Georgetown Int Environ Law Rev 11:101–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Verdross A (1966) Jus Dispositivum and jus cogens in international law. Am J Int Law 60:55–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherall T (2015) Jus cogens and sovereign immunity: reconciling divergence in contemporary jurisprudence. Georgetown J Int Law 46:1151–1212

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil P (1983) Towards relative normativity in international law. Am J Int Law 77(3):413–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winch P (1990) The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy, 2nd edn. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark D. Retter .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Retter, M.D. (2019). Before and After Legal Positivity: Peremptory Norms from Global and Transnational Social Practice. In: Siliquini-Cinelli, L. (eds) Legal Positivism in a Global and Transnational Age. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 131. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24705-8_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24705-8_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-24704-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-24705-8

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics