Skip to main content

Scientifically Defending Realism II: Maddy’s Piecemeal Realism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Science-Based Critique of Epistemological Naturalism in Quine’s Tradition
  • 145 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I discuss Maddy’s piecemeal realism, as she exemplifies it with regard to the debate on the ontological status of atoms that was provoked by Perrin’s seminal experiments in the early twentieth century. By considering the central experiments in some detail, by contrasting Maddy’s reading of these experiments with van Fraassen’s, and by reconstructing the arguments proposed by Perrin and Poincaré for the reality of the atom, I argue that the gap between empirical research on the one hand and scientific realism on the other cannot be closed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Wolff (2015) presents an anthropological challenge to the piecemeal approach of the Second Philosopher: she argues that, being the limited beings that we are, we cannot examine each question and position in detail and hence need general rules of Psillos’ kind to orient ourselves. This is certainly an interesting point. However, the Second Philosopher could respond to this objection simply by hiring the required number of scholars to work down the list on a case-by-case basis.

  2. 2.

    Poincaré’s views on the issue will be detailed below, Sect. 9.2.2. The main aspect of Perrin’s experiments that convinced Ostwald was that they simultaneously corroborate the molecular kinematic theory and clearly contradict its main rival, thermodynamics. See Ostwald (1912, p. 485).

  3. 3.

    Being a committed advocate of Perrin’s position, Nye by no means maintains a neutral perspective on the debate and, as will be shown below, sometimes distorts the views of Jean Perrin’s peers. However, when it comes to retelling the story of Perrin’s own experiments, which largely confirmed predictions by Albert Einstein, her account is still canonical for its attention to detail and careful analysis of the research context of the time. Among many others, her research is related by Gardner (1979), Egg (2014, p. 95), and by Maddy (2007, pp. 404–407).

  4. 4.

    Avogadro’s number specifies the number of molecules per mole, it is approximately 6.022 × 1023 per mole.

  5. 5.

    He also verified an Einsteinian prediction of the mean rotation energy of particles, which I have not discussed here, compare Nye (1972, pp. 129–130).

  6. 6.

    It is of course highly contested what phenomena count as observing: for instance, do microscopes count? However, this is not a problem that Maddy faces, as she explicitly does not put any epistemic weight on some event’s counting as a detection or observation, see below in this section. For an early critique of the distinction, see Maxwell (1962). In an earlier work, Maddy does use ‘seeing’, albeit in scare quotes, in her description of Perrin’s achievements: “atomic theory around the turn of the twentieth century was well-endowed with the five theoretical virtues, but it was not accepted as true until it had passed a further test. That further test was sometimes described in terms of ‘seeing’ or ‘observing’, other times in vaguer terms of ‘direct testing’ or ‘experimentally verifying’. I won’t attempt to analyze this notion; […]” (Maddy 1997, p. 142).

  7. 7.

    Prima facie, there may seem to be a third option for Maddy here. It consists in the claim that Perrin’s experiments made atoms observable sensu stricto. However, this would amount to reconceiving the question of the reality of the atom as a question for common-sense realism. Thus, this move would bypass rather than address the central issue of scientific realism, namely whether we can assert the reality of so-called theoretical, or unobservable entities. Furthermore, it does not seem convincing to conceive the achievement of Perrin’s experiments as making atoms observable in the strict sense. As Egg (2014, p. 95) points out, “a Brownian particle undergoes some 1021 collisions with molecules of the surrounding fluid per second.” Given the technology available by the time of Perrin’s experiments, this is just too fast to observe in any substantial sense of “observe”. None of this is to dispute that atoms have become observables now. I am only claiming that Perrin did not make atoms observable.

  8. 8.

    All translations from French to English are mine, unless otherwise stated. I am grateful to Christian Weibel for commenting on draft versions of the translations.

  9. 9.

    Compare Egg (2014).

  10. 10.

    For Poincaré’s views on ontology, see also Ladyman (2011).

  11. 11.

    Furthermore, Castro (2013, pp. 45f.) calls Poincaré’s conversion to atomism “philosophically bizarre” because it is either inconsistent with his philosophy of science or he had to abandon it. I hope to have shown that Castro is wrong to think that Poincaré faced this choice: his philosophy of science is much more versatile than this. Even more, I honestly don’t see why a substantial change in one’s philosophy of science should be termed bizarre, if it occurs in response to spectacular new developments in the sciences.

  12. 12.

    However, I wish to emphasize that, while my analysis differs from Maddy’s regarding the means with which the atoms debate was conducted, I entirely agree with her that the kind of realism championed by Perrin and his fellow scientists is clearly superior to the kind of abstract, holistic approach proposed by Psillos and Sankey. This can probably be explained with the interdisciplinary expertise of the scientists involved: several participants to the debate, including Perrin and Poincaré, were not only among the foremost scientists of their time, but also highly gifted philosophers. This allowed them to combine experimental findings with metaphysical theorizing in such a way as to make very compelling cases for their views. To appreciate the contrast to the contemporary scene, just imagine that Psillos would start experimenting in the CERN Hadron Collider to corroborate his realism, while leading physicists would start defending their realism in peer-reviewed philosophical journals.

References

  • Achinstein, Peter. 2002. Is There a Valid Experimental Argument for Scientific Realism? The Journal of Philosophy 99 (9): 470–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, Tyler. 2013. Cognition Through Understanding: Self-knowledge, Interlocution, Reasoning, Reflection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castro, Eduardo. 2013. Defending the Indispensability Argument: Atoms, Infinity and the Continuum. Journal for General Philosophy of Science/Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 44: 41–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, Alan. 2011. Drawing Philosophical Lessons from Perrin’s Experiments on Brownian Motion: A Response to van Fraassen. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62: 711–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egg, Matthias. 2014. Scientific Realism in Particle Physics. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, Albert. 1905. On the Movement of Small Particles Suspended in Stationary Liquids Required by the Molecular-Kinetic Theory of Heat. Annalen der Physik 17: 549–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, Michael R. 1979. Realism and Instrumentalism in 19th-Century Atomism. Philosophy of Science 46 (1): 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ivanova, Milena. 2013. Did Perrin’s Experiments Convert Poincaré to Scientific Realism? HoPos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 3: 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Conventionalism, Structuralism and Neo-Kantianism in Poincaré’s Philosophy of Science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 52: 114–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James. 2011. Structural Realism Versus Standard Scientific Realism: The Case of Phlogiston and Dephlogisticated Air. Synthese 180 (2): 87–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, Penelope. 1997. Naturalism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Second Philosophy. A Naturalistic Method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, Grover. 1962. The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III, ed. Herbert Feigl and Grover Maxwell, 21–28. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nye, Mary Jo. 1972. Molecular Reality. A Perspective on the Scientific Work of Jean Perrin. London: MacDonald.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostwald, Wilhelm. 1912. Outlines of General Chemistry, trans. W.W. Taylor. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrin, Jean. 1909. Mouvement brownien et réalité moléculaire. Annales de chimie et de physique 8 (18): 5–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1912. Les rapports de la matière et de l’éther. Journal de physique théorique et appliquée 2 (1): 347–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1913. Atomes. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, Henri. 1905. La valeur de la science. Paris: Ernest Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, Stathis. 1999. Scientific Realism. How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Moving Molecules Above the Scientific Horizon: On Perrin’s Case for Realism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science/Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 42 (2): 339–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, Bas. 2009. The Perils of Perrin, in the Hands of Philosophers. Philosophical Studies 143 (1): 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Johanna. 2015. Naturalistic Quietism or Scientific Realism? Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0873-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Reto Gubelmann .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gubelmann, R. (2019). Scientifically Defending Realism II: Maddy’s Piecemeal Realism. In: A Science-Based Critique of Epistemological Naturalism in Quine’s Tradition. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24524-5_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics