Skip to main content
  • 143 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter introduces the theme of the book, epistemological naturalism, explains central concepts and gives an overview on the book’s contents. In particular, I introduce my understanding of epistemological naturalism as consisting of two elements, namely naturalized epistemology and justificatory monism. Briefly, naturalized epistemology is the project of pursuing epistemology in a strictly scientific manner. Justificatory monism claims that there is only one fundamental way to justify any claim whatsoever, namely through empirical-scientific evidence. Furthermore, I discuss basic Quinean terminology, as Quine’s work is a central point of orientation throughout the book.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My distinction between epistemic and epistemological matters distinguishes the actual practice of justifying claims and attaining knowledge from reflecting and theorizing about this practice. Epistemic questions are questions regarding the justification of a given claim or position; they are internal to the game of giving and asking for reasons. For example, to maintain that the epistemic standing of the claim that god exists is weak is to maintain that the claim has little warrant, or justification. In contrast, epistemological questions are questions about this game; they are answered with reflections and theories about central concepts or principles of the game. By drawing this distinction, I do by no means dispute that many epistemic debates evolve into epistemological debates.

  2. 2.

    I take it that what Glock (2003, pp. 27–28) calls metaphilosophical naturalism largely coincides with methodological naturalism: he (ibid.) considers Quine’s methodological monism as an instance of metaphilosophical naturalism.

  3. 3.

    I use the term ‘justificatory monism’ instead of Quine’s term ‘naturalism’ for two reasons. First, ‘naturalism’ is—mostly due to Quine’s influence—currently used in so many different ways that it has lost any distinctive meaning. Second, I hope that the term ‘justificatory monism’ serves to highlight the aspects of Quine’s naturalism that I am focusing on.

  4. 4.

    Hence, I disagree with Keil (2003, p. 277), who maintains that “it was far from clear what he [Quine, RG] did ban under the name of prior [i.e. first, RG] philosophy”, and also that “[t]here are not many philosophers left at whom Quine’s criticism of philosophical apriorism could be aimed.” Quine’s justificatory monism excludes any position according to which reflection on the correct explication of empirical-scientific justification is not itself bound by this conception. Such positions are still held by a significant part of contemporary philosophers of science.

  5. 5.

    Further passages where Maddy implicitly relies on empiricist justificatory monism are: Maddy (2007, p. 262), where she makes clear that it is not conceivable that any other evidence than empirical evidence could play a role in developmental psychology; Maddy (2007, p. 279), where she acknowledges, in striking analogy to Quine, that even the laws of logic can be revised in light of empirical evidence; Maddy (2007, p. 410), where she agrees with Mark Lange that interpretations of physical theories that allow for new empirical predictions thereby qualify as scientific theories, instead of being philosophical speculation; Finally, Maddy (2007, p. 88) distinguishes her position from Carnap’s by rejecting the very idea that there is any realm of inquiry beyond the empirical one: “what she [the Second Philosopher, RG] wants, of course, is a defense based on empirical study of human language use. In contrast, Carnap explicitly distinguishes his pursuit of ‘the logic of science’ from the empirical study of language”.

References

  • Føllesdal, Dagfinn. 1973. Indeterminacy of Translation and Under-Determination of the Theory of Nature. Dialectica 27: 289–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, Hans-Johann. 2003. Quine and Davidson on Language, Thought and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Can Animals Judge? Dialectica 64: 11–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, Paul. 2014. Naturalism and the Linguistic Turn. In Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications, ed. Bana Bashour and Hans D. Muller, 37–43. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998 [1987]. Kritik der Reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, Geert. 2003. “Science Itself Teaches”. A Fresh Look at Quine’s Naturalistic Metaphilosophy. Grazer Philosophische Studien 66: 253–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, Penelope. 2007. Second Philosophy. A Naturalistic Method. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. A Second Philosophy of Logic. In The Metaphysics of Logic, ed. Penelope Rush. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 93–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, David. 2015. Naturalism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/naturalism/. Accessed 5 August 2017.

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 2002. The Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism. In Naturalism Defeated? Essays on Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism, ed. James Beilby, 1–12. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1969. Epistemology Naturalized. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, 69–90. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. The Roots of Reference. La Salle: Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Five Milestones of Empiricism. In Theories and Things, 67–72. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Pursuit of Truth, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, Alex. 1996. A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47: 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Naturalistic Epistemology for Eliminative Materialists. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59: 335–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Disenchanted Naturalism. In Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications, 17–36. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Reto Gubelmann .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gubelmann, R. (2019). Introduction. In: A Science-Based Critique of Epistemological Naturalism in Quine’s Tradition. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24524-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics