Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 104))

  • 172 Accesses

Abstract

This final chapter elucidates Patočka’s absolute emphasis on intersubjectivity, his “localizing” infinity into the relation between “subjects.” After paying attention to Patočka’s early ideas on the relation of a finite being to infinite life, I turn to his late thought focusing on the third movement of existence as identified with the movement of transcendence. I accentuate Patočka’s idea of self-transcendence toward the other, by which “the kingdom of God” is among us: the movement of self-transcendence is the movement of love. This idea allows for thinking the finite-infinite relation as the relation between finite being who by de-limiting themselves live in infinity. I indicate why we should not expel love from the first two movements of existence. Finally, I localize Patočka’s concept of the finite-infinity relation in the context of related reflections of Feuerbach, Kierkegaard, and Nietzsche.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This chapter is based on a paper “Approaching the Absolute in Jan Patočka’s Phenomenology,” Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 79(3), 2017, 499–515.

  2. 2.

    Karfík himself, if I understand him correctly, answers this question negatively. Cf. his “Post scriptum” to the Czech translation of the just mentioned chapter (Karfík 2016: 171).

  3. 3.

    Regarding this issue, cf. Hagedorn (2011, 2014 and 2015), Evink 2015, de Warren (2015), Kočí (2016, 2017).

  4. 4.

    A comprehensive analysis of the concept of transcendence in Patočka’s philosophy is offered by Frei (2014). Cf. also San (2012).

  5. 5.

    Regarding the importance of life in Patočka’s early phenomenology, see Chaps 2 and 4 above.

  6. 6.

    Karfík also cites a telling letter from 1933 in which Patočka speaks of a sharp difference between Husserl, who “makes philosophy in the absolute,” and Heidegger, who “disclaims any approach to the absolute” (Karfík 2008: 27, n. 8).

  7. 7.

    In one of his very last studies, Patočka formulates following observation which is implicit, I would argue, already in his early phenomenology: “Landgrebe grasped perceptively that the free act in which the epoché is rooted cannot … be integrated into the overall conception of subjectivity as it appears in the view of the transcendental spectator, and showed a profound reason for it, in that freedom is essentially linked to the future-oriented extasis of temporality while insight, contemplation, and theoretical interest are by their very nature rooted in the past oriented ‘already’ which pertains to what is finished, to that into which a free being is set” (Patočka 1989d: 311).

  8. 8.

    According to Karfík, Patočka’s philosophy of history is an attempt to relive a philosophical project that has its origins in the German Enlightenment and that was realized most fully by Hegel. Yet, whereas Hegel’s realization is based on the ontology of the in-finite, absolute subject, Patočka actualizes it on the basis of Heidegger’s ontology. Cf. Karfík (2016): 168.

  9. 9.

    See, e.g., these formulations: “That the third basic relation … is also a temporal one follows from its relation to the future, to nonbeing, to death” (Patočka 1989a: 266). “The accent on the future requires, on the contrary, that the already existent cease to be regarded as the decisive instance of possibilities, that the possibility of not-being come to the fore and sharpen our eyes to that to which alone we can, and must, give ourselves up” (Patočka 2016b: 164).

  10. 10.

    The two studies on time have been interpreted by Kouba (2015).

  11. 11.

    Cf. Hagedorn (2015: esp. 34–36).

  12. 12.

    In the Czech original, Patočka uses the collocation život věčný which should be translated into English, due to its obvious Christian connotations, as “eternal life.”

  13. 13.

    Ivan Chvatík believes that, to overcome the present crisis of the world, Patočka seeks a third conversion after the first conversion from myth to philosophy and the second made by Christianity; cf. Chvatík (2011: esp. 272–277).

  14. 14.

    As is probably clear, I disagree with Hagedorn as well as Patočka’s idea that “human life is ‘unfree’ as long as it clings to something in the world, as long as it is preoccupied with beings” (Hagedorn 2015: 36).

  15. 15.

    Interestingly, devaluating the mythical way of life, Patočka uses the same analogy speaking of prehistorical living as living in “ontological metaphor.” Cf. above, Chap. 11.

  16. 16.

    Of course, in loving others, one can also be polemical toward them, but it does not make polemos the principle of action, and much less that of love.

  17. 17.

    Obviously, Patočka comes close to Levinas’ idea that “the individual and the personal are necessary for Infinity to be able to be produced as infinite” (Levinas 1979: 218). This similarity, however, cannot be analysed here in more detail.

  18. 18.

    In fact, Patočka’s image of “the ocean of being” sounds like an echo of Feuerbach’s “vivifying and refreshing waves of the ocean of the world.”

  19. 19.

    In the 1950s, when interpreting faith, Patočka connects it with the “conception in which the future takes priority” and identifies it with “the belief that no decision is ultimate and irrevocable” (Patočka 2015e: 9). Regarding the concept of faith, cf. Hagedorn (2015: esp. 34–36), and Kočí (2016: esp. 113–114).

  20. 20.

    Especially because some of the fundamental thoughts of Heidegger’s Being and Time, utilized by Patočka, are based on the reconsideration of Kierkegaard’s thought, and Patočka’s own concept of the movements of existence can be connected with that of Kierkegaard, as already pointed out by Kohák (1989: 284).

  21. 21.

    Regarding sacrifice, see e.g. this formulation: “I love those who do not first seek behind the stars for a reason to go under and be a sacrifice, who instead sacrifice themselves for the earth, so that the earth may one day become the overman’s” (Nietzsche 2006: 8).

References

  • Chvatík, Ivan. 2011. The Responsibility of the “Shaken”. In Jan Patočka and the Heritage of Phenomenology, ed. Erika Abrams and Ivan Chvatík, 263–279. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Warren, Nicolas. 2015. The Gift of Eternity. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology, Religion, War and the Crisis of Modernity. A Special Issue Dedicated to the Philosophy of Jan Patočka, ed. James Dodd and Ludger Hagedorn, vol. XIV, 161–180. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evink, Eddo. 2015. The Gift of Life. Jan Patočka and the Christian Heritage. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology, Religion, War and the Crisis of Modernity. A Special Issue Dedicated to the Philosophy of Jan Patočka, ed. James Dodd and Ludger Hagedorn, vol. XIV, 47–63. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1972. Principles of the Philosophy of the Future. In The Fiery Brook: Selected Writings, Trans. Zawar Hanfi. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frei, Jan. 2014. Problém transcendence u Jana Patočky. Faculty of Arts, Charles University in Prague (Dissertation).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagedorn, Ludger. 2011. Beyond Myth and Enlightenment: On Religion in Patočka’s Thought. In Jan Patočka and the Heritage of Phenomenology, ed. Erica Abrams and Ivan Chvatík, 245–262. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Kenosis: Die philosophische Anverwandlung eines christlichen Motivs bei Jan Patočka. In Figuren der Transzendenz: Transformationen eines phänomenologischen Grundbegriffs, ed. Michal Staudigl and Christian Sternad, 349–366. Würzburg: Köningshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. ‘Christianity Unthought’ – A Reconsideration of Myth, Faith, and Historicity. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology, Religion, War and the Crisis of Modernity. A Special Issue Dedicated to the Philosophy of Jan Patočka, ed. James Dodd and Ludger Hagedorn, vol. XIV, 31–46. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karfík, Filip. 2008. Unendlichwerden durch die Endlichkeit. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Jan Patočka a problém filosofie dějin. Reflexe 50 (2016): 145–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kočí, Martin. 2016. Christianity after Christianity. A Theological Appropriation of Jan Patočka’s Thought in the Context of the Theological Turn in Continental Philosophy, Katholieke Universiteit Leuven (Dissertation).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Sacrifice for Nothing: The Movement of Kenosis in Jan Patočka’s Thought. Modern Theology 33 (4,. 2017): 594–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohák, Erazim. 1989. Jan Patočka. Philosophy and Selected Writings. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kouba, P. 2015. Time in ‘Negative Platonism’. In The Phenomenological Critique of Mathematisation and the Question of Responsibility, ed. Lubica Učník, Ivan Chvatík, and Anita Williams, 79–88. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1979. Totality and Infinity. Trans. A. Lingis. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2006. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. A Book for All and None. Trans. Adrian del Caro. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patočka, Jan. 1989a. The “natural” world and phenomenology. In Philosophy and selected writings, ed. Erazim Kohák, 239–273. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989d. Cartesianism and Phenomenology. In Philosophy and Selected Writings, ed. Erazim Kohák, 285–326. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Der Subjektivismus der Husserlschen und die Möglichkeit einer ‘asubjektiven’ Phänomenologie. In Die Bewegung der menschlichen Existenz, ed. Klaus Nellen, Jiri Nemec, and Ilja Srubar. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. O dvojím pojetí smyslu filosofie. In Péče o duši I, ed. Ivan Chvatík and Pavel Kouba, 68–84. Praha: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Body, Community, Language, World. Trans. Erazim Kohák, ed. James Dodd. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002c. In Studie o času I, ed. I.I.I. Péče o duši, Ivan Chvatík, and Pavel Kouba, 612–643. Praha: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002d. Studie o času II. In Péče o duši III, ed. Ivan Chvatík and Pavel Kouba, 644–651. Praha: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Kolem Masarykovy filosofie náboženství. In Češi, ed. Karel Palek and Ivan Chvatík, 366–422. Praha: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. Some Comments Concerning the Extramundane and Mundane Position of Philosophy. In Living in Problematicity, ed. Eric Manton, 18–28. Prague: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007e. Life in Balance, Life in Amplitude. In Living in Problematicity, ed. Eric Manton, 32–42. Prague: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Pojem evidence a jeho význam pro noetiku. In Fenomenologické spisy I, ed. Ivan Chvatík and Jan Frei, 14–125. Praha: Oikúmené.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015c. On the Prehistory of the Science of Movement. World, Earth, Heaven and the Movement of Human Life. In Dis-Orientations. Philosophy, Literature and the Lost Ground of Modernity, ed. Marcia Sa Cavalcante Schuback and Tora Lane, 65–73. London: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015d. On Masaryk’s Philosophy of Religion. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology, Religion, War and the Crisis of Modernity. A Special Issue Dedicated to the Philosophy of Jan Patočka, vol. XIV, 95–135. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015e. Time, Myth, Faith. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology, Religion, War and the Crisis of Modernity. A Special Issue Dedicated to the Philosophy of Jan Patočka, vol. XIV, 3–12. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a. The Natural World as a Philosophical Problem. In The Natural World as a Philosophical Problem, Trans. Erica Abrams, 1–114. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. “The Natural World” Remeditated Thirty-Three Years Later. In The Natural World as a Philosophical Problem, Trans. Erica Abrams, 115–180. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rezek, Petr. 2010. Třetí životní pohyb u Jana Patočky jako problém intersubjektivity. In Jan Patočka a věc fenomenologie, ed. Petr Rezek, 108–125. Praha: Galerie Ztichlá Klika.

    Google Scholar 

  • San, Emre. 2012. La transcendance comme problème phénoménologique. Lecture de Merleau-Ponty et Patočka. Paris: Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ritter, M. (2019). Omnia Vincit Amor. In: Into the World: The Movement of Patočka's Phenomenology. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 104. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-23657-1_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics