Skip to main content

Mindful Performance

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Extended Theory of Cognitive Creativity

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 23))

Abstract

In this chapter I explore several variations of mindfulness in performance, and I focus specifically on variations of self-awareness in these practices. I take an enactivist approach, clarifying first why enactivism is not a form of behaviorism. I argue that phenomenologically inspired enactivist conceptions of perception and action are neither mindless, in a naïve behavioristic way, nor overly cognitivist, but do involve aspects of mindfulness that support embodied performance. I’ll look at examples from athletics, dance and musical performance. Finally, I’ll consider the status of self in mindful practices that are sometimes described as attaining mindless or selfless states.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On a slightly different reading Zahavi (2018) takes me-ness and mineness to involve forms of reflective awareness which are only occasional, or as he says, ‘rare’. To be precise, Zahavi is right that we are not aware of the experience “as my own” if we take the ‘as’ to signify a conceptual grasp. I suggest we understand the ‘as’ to be a soft (non-conceptual) or bracketed ‘as’.

  2. 2.

    The Buddhist scholar John Donne (2011, 74) points to more detailed descriptions in the Buddhist literature. “For practitioners to experience a non-dual state, however, there must be some form of knowing or experiencing that is not structured by subject–object duality. This form of knowing is ‘reflexive awareness’ (Skt. Svasa mvitti, Tib. rang rig), and it does not receive a robust theoretical treatment until the works of Dharmakírti and his major commentators (seventh to ninth centuries). Once a clear account of reflexive awareness is in place, Buddhist authors now have the tools to speak of truly non-dual meditative states, namely, those in which the meditator experiences consciousness in its true form as utterly devoid of subject–object structuring. And this is precisely the type of practice that emerges historically as Mahámudrá in India by the end of the first millennium (C.E.).”

References

  • Aizawa, K. (2014). The enactivist revolution. Avant, 5(2), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ataria, Y., Dor-Ziderman, Y., & Berkovich-Ohana, A. (2015). How does it feel to lack a sense of boundaries? A case study of a long-term mindfulness meditator. Consciousness and Cognition, 37, 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beilock, S. (2010). Choke: What the secrets of the brain reveal about getting it right when you have to. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowman, Q. (2004). Cognition and the body: Perspectives from music education. In L. Bresler (Ed.), Knowing bodies, moving minds: Toward embodied teaching and learning (pp. 29–50). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Breivik, G. (2007). Skillful coping in everyday life and in sport: A critical examination of the views of Heidegger and Dreyfus. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 34(2), 116–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breivik, G. (2013). Zombie-like or superconscious? A phenomenological and conceptual analysis of consciousness in elite sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 40(1), 85–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. (2015). Putting pressure on theories of choking: Towards an expanded perspective on breakdown in skilled performance. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(2), 253–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D.J. (2016). Cognition in skilled action: Meshed control and the varieties of skill experience. Mind & Language, 31(1): 37–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J., Gallagher, S., & McNeill, D. (2002). Gesture following deafferentation: A phenomenologically informed experimental study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(1), 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. (2004). Interactional expertise as a third kind of knowledge. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(2), 125–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1922). Human nature and conduct. New York: Henry Holt & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dor-Ziderman, Y., Berkovich-Ohana, A., Glicksohn, J., & Goldstein, A. (2013). Mindfulness-induced selflessness: A MEG neurophenomenological study. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dor-Ziderman, Y., Ataria, Y., Fulder, S., Goldstein, A., & Berkovich-Ohana, A. (2016). Self-specific processing in the meditating brain: A MEG neurophenomenology study. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2016(1), niw019. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niw019.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation: Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise. In Proceedings and addresses of the american philosophical association (pp. 47–65). Newark: American Philosophical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (1985). From Socrates to expert systems: The limits of calculative rationality. In C. Mitcham, & A. Huning (Eds.), Philosophy and technology ii: Information technology and computers in theory and practice (pp. 111–130). Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunne, J. (2011). Toward an understanding of non-dual mindfulness. Contemporary Buddhism, 12(1), 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen, J.W. (2010). Mindless coping in competitive sport: Some implications and consequences. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 4(1), 66–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ford, P., Hodges, N.J., & Williams, A.M. (2005). Online attentional-focus manipulations in a soccer dribbling task: Implications for the proceduralization of motor skills. Journal of Motor Behavior, 37, 386–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francesconi, D., & Gallagher, S. (2018). Embodied cognition and sports pedagogy. In M. Cappucio (Ed.), Handbook of embodied cognition and sport psychology (pp. 249–272). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005a). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005b). Dynamic models of body schematic processes. In H. De Preester, & V. Knockaert (Eds.), Body image and body schema (pp. 233–250). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2016). The practice of thinking: Between Dreyfus and McDowell. In T. Breyer (Ed.), The phenomenology of thinking (pp. 134–146). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017b). Self-defense: Deflecting deflationary and eliminativist critiques of the sense of ownership. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 1612. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01612.

  • Gallagher, S., & Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. (2018). Self- and other-awareness in joint expert performance. In E. Fridland, & C. Pavese (Eds.), Routledge handbook on skill and expertise. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varela, F. (2003). Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Supplementary Volume, 29. 93–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2012). The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2014). Phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. At http://plato.stanford.edu/

  • Gallagher, S., Cole, J., & McNeill, D. (2001). The language-thought-hand system. In C. Cave, I. Guaitella, & S. Santi (Eds.), Oralité et gestualité: Interactions et comportements multimodaux dans la communication (pp. 420–24). Paris: L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, F., & Moore, Z.E. (2012). Mindfulness and acceptance models in sport psychology: A decade of basic and applied scientific advancements. Canadian Psychology, 53(4), 309–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glowinski, D., Mancini, M., Cowie, R., Camurri, A., Chiorri, C., & Doherty, C. (2013). The movements made by performers in a skilled quartet: a distinctive pattern, and the function that it serves. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 841. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gnecco, G., Badino, L., Camurri, A., D’Ausilio, A., Fadiga, L., Glowinski, D., …, Volpe, G. (2013). Towards automated analysis of joint music performance in the orchestra. In International conference on arts and technology (pp. 120–127). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gregucci, A., Pappaianni, E., Siugzdaite, R., Theuninck, A., & Job, R. (2015). Mindful emotion regulation: Exploring the neurocognitive mechanisms behind mindfulness. BioMed Research International, 2015(June), 670724. https://doi.org/10.1155/2015/670724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guillot, M. (2017). I me mine: On a confusion concerning the subjective character of experience. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(1), 23–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirstein, W. (2015). Consciousness despite network underconnectivity in autism: Another case of consciousness without prefrontal activity? In R.J. Gennaro (Ed.), Disturbed consciousness: New essays on psychopathology and theories of consciousness (pp. 249–264). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Høffding, S. (2015). A phenomenology of expert musicianship. Ph.D. dissertation, Department of Philosophy, University of Copenhagen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2014). Affordances and the musically extended mind. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 1003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2007). Pre-reflective self-consciousness: on being bodily in the world. Janus Head, 9(2), 493–519

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, A., Slagter, H.A. Dunne, J.D., & Davidson, R.J. (2008). Attention regulation and monitoring in meditation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 163–169. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2008.01.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maravita, A., & Iriki, A. (2004). Tools for the body (schema). Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(2), 79–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007). What myth? Inquiry, 50(4), 338–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). The structure of behavior. (trans. Fisher, A.L.). Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2010). Does bodily awareness interfere with highly skilled movement? Inquiry, 53(2), 105–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B.G. (2015). Thinking in the zone: The expert mind in action. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(S1), 126–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery, J., & Chambers, M. (2009). Mastering swimming. Champaign: Human Kinetics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A., & Malinowski, P. (2009). Meditation, mindfulness and cognitive flexibility. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(1), 176–186. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2008.12.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Repp, B.H., & Su, Y.H. (2013). Sensorimotor synchronization: A review of recent research (2006–2012). Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 20(3), 403–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salice, A., Høffding, S., & Gallagher, S. (2017). Putting plural self-awareness into practice: The phenomenology of expert musicianship. Topoi, 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9451-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2011). Embodied cognition. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2014). Book review: Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Mind, 123(489), 213–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S.L., Carlson, L.E., Astin, J.A., & Freedman, B. (2006). Mechanisms of mindfulness. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 62(3), 373–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2000). Kinetic tactile-kinesthetic bodies: Ontogenetical foundations of apprenticeship learning. Human Studies, 23, 343–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2002). How music works: Beyond the immanent and the arbitrary. In Action, criticism, and theory (act) for music education 1:2. (http://mas.siue.edu/ACT/index.html). 14.

  • Shusterman, R. (2008). Body consciousness: A philosophy of mindfulness and somaesthetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soliman, T.M., & Glenberg, A.M. (2014). The embodiment of culture. In L, Shapiro (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition (pp. 207–220). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., McIlwain, D., Christensen, W., & Geeves, A. (2011). Applying intelligence to the reflexes: Embodied skills and habits between dreyfus and descartes. Journal of the British Society Phenomenology, 42(1), 78–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. (1998). Throwing like a girl. In D. Welton (Ed.), Body and flesh: A philosophical reader (pp. 259–273). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2018). Consciousness, self-consciousness, selfhood: a reply to some critics. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 9(3), 703–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeidan, F., Johnson, S.K., Diamond, B.J., David, Z., & Goolkasian, P. (2010). Mindfulness meditation improves cognition: Evidence of brief mental training. Consciousness and Cognition, 19(2), 597–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research on this paper was supported by the author’s Anneliese Maier Research Award from the Humboldt Foundation, and by an Australian Research Council (ARC) grant, Minds in Skilled Performance. DP170102987.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shaun Gallagher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, S. (2020). Mindful Performance. In: Pennisi, A., Falzone, A. (eds) The Extended Theory of Cognitive Creativity. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22090-7_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22090-7_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-22089-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-22090-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics