Skip to main content

Troubles Ahead

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 226 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 409))

Abstract

In this chapter I look at the original DTM from a critical perspective. Firstly, I closely analyze the way directives produce meanings of words. Secondly, I look at the consequences of the holistic nature of the DTM. Next, I expand on the pragmatic aspect of the theory and try to imagine how the process of gathering directives should look like. In the following subsection I inspect the reasons and consequences of the non-referential status of the DTM. In Sect. 3.6 I discuss Alfred Tarski’s counterexample which discouraged Ajdukiewicz from developing the theory further. Section 3.7 brings to light some of the non-obvious assumptions on syntax which are present in the DTM. The chapter closes with the examination of the most problematic aspect of the original theory – the fact it was originally restricted only to “closed” and “connected” languages. I explain Ajdukiewicz’s reasons for this restriction and prepare ground for its elimination.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As pointed out in Machery (2009), there are at least two significantly different traditions of understanding concepts: the first understands them as categorization devices, the second as building blocks of judgements. Given the role categorization plays in empirical directives, they should probably be understood as a combination of the two.

  2. 2.

    See Chap. 4 for a discussion on a similar problem in Sellars’ theory.

  3. 3.

    Note that, although we should not conflate these cases – the analyticity of sentences that figure in the directives and the analyticity of the whole directives – both of them are bad news for the theory as they both lead to the problem mentioned by Fodor and Lepore. It is just that we should consider them separately.

  4. 4.

    See Maynes (2012) for a critical discussion on this common view.

  5. 5.

    See Cappelen (2014) and Machery (2017) for a rundown of the arguments of both sides.

  6. 6.

    For thinking that the choice of logic could be dictated by empirical facts, Łukasiewicz was criticized by Ajdukiewicz, who believed it to be a practical decision.

  7. 7.

    Whether this explanation would have been acceptable from the ideological point of view of Marxist materialism is another question.

  8. 8.

    This was probably the influence of two traditions: the phenomenological tradition of Husserl and the positivist tradition of the Vienna Circle, especially Rudolf Carnap’s Logische Aufbau Der Welt (1928).

  9. 9.

    This is somewhat justified by the expression “data of experience” used in Ajdukiewicz (1935/1978).

  10. 10.

    A number of examples similar to this were suggested by John Perry (2001).

  11. 11.

    Davidson raises this point while discussing the problem of ascribing beliefs to animals, but his point is equally applicable to the DTM.

  12. 12.

    As opposed to the trivial sense in which we could just say that they differ because they are comprised of different letters.

  13. 13.

    As we pointed out in Sect. 3.4.3, he does say that meaning directives are analytic, but there is nothing to suggest that the same could be said about sentences covered by the directives.

  14. 14.

    It is hard not to notice that all of these considerations are very reminiscent of problems encountered in other theories, such as Quine’s theory of language (indeterminacy of translation) and Davidson’s theory of language (principle of charity). I discuss both connections at length in Chaps. 4 and 5.

  15. 15.

    To the point that he tried to reduce semantics to syntax, which was a valiant but probably futile effort. This is interesting to mention in the context of the DTM as it could be argued that Ajdukiewicz’s theory manages to do something very close to the unattainable Carnapian ideal by adding a dash of pragmatics to the mix.

  16. 16.

    The expression used in the Polish version of the paper is even more evocative, as it can be best translated as “dormant”.

  17. 17.

    The term was introduced in Carnap (1945) and discussed in detail in Carnap (1950b).

  18. 18.

    Which, admittedly, is nothing new in the philosophy of language, as Quine could easily have been accused of the same confusion.

  19. 19.

    Anticipating both Davidson’s conceptual themes and Wittgenstein’s world pictures, although, as pointed out by Giedymin, he could have been inspired by a single mention of “world pictures” found in Poincaré.

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1931/1978). On the meaning of expressions. In K. Ajdukiewicz (Ed.), The scientific world-perspective and other essays. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1934/1978). Language and meaning. In K. Ajdukiewicz (Ed.), The scientific world-perspective and other essays. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1935/1978). The scientific world-perspective. In K. Ajdukiewicz (Ed.), The scientific world-perspective and other essays. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1964/1978). The problem of empiricism and the concept of meaning. In K. Ajdukiewicz (Ed.), The scientific world-perspective and other essays. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1995). My philosophical ideas. In V. Sinisi & J. Woleński (Eds.), The heritage of Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz (Poznań studies in the philosophy of sciences and the humanities, Vol. 40). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1998). Conceptual role semantics. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy (pp. 242–256). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buszkowski, W. (2010). O równoznaczności wyrażeń w ujęciu Ajdukiewicza. In J. Grad, J. Sójka, & A. Zaporowski (Eds.), Nauka −Kultura −. Społeczeństwo. Księga jubileuszowa dedykowana Profesor Krystynie Zamiarze. Poznań: Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu im. Adama Mickiewicza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2014). Philosophy without intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). Der Logische Aufbau Der Welt. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1934). Logische Syntax der Sprache. Wien: Verlag von Julius Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1945). The two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5(4), 513–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950a). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 40–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950b). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciecierski, T., & Wilkin, P. (2009). Sidestepping the holes of holism. In V. A. Munz, K. Puhl, & J. Wang (Eds.), Language and world. Preproceedings of the 32nd International Wittgenstein Symposium (pp. 84–86).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982). Rational animals. Dialectica, 36(4), 317–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege. Philosophy of language. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1976). What is a theory of meaning? (II). In Evans & McDowell (Eds.), Truth and meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism. A shopper’s guide. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892/1980). On sense and reference. In P. Geach, & M. Black (Eds., and Trans.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (3rd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1957). Mental acts: Their content and their objects. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanusek, J. (2012a). Argument Tarskiego i teorie znaczenia Kazimierza Ajdukiewicza. Diametros, 32, 160–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanusek, J. (2012b). On a non-referential theory of meaning for simple names based on Ajdukiewicz’s theory of meaning. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 21, 253–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, W. (2001). Formal features of compositionality. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 10, 7–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackman, H. (2017). Meaning holism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/meaning-holism/

  • Jedynak, A. (2003). Ajdukiewicz. Warszawa: Wiedza Powszechna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblich, H. (2013). Is there room for armchair theorizing in epistemology? In M. C. Haug (Ed.), Philosophical methodology: The armchair or the laboratory? (pp. 195–216). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy within its proper bounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maciaszek, J. (2015). Składalność znaczeń w teorii dyrektywalnej. Przegląd Filozoficzny. Nowa Seria., 1(93), 27–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1988). Believing the axioms I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 53(2), 481–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynes, J. (2012). Linguistic intuition and calibration. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35, 443–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowaczyk, A. (2000). Ajdukiewicza teoria znaczenia z perspektywy lat. Filozofia Nauki, 2(30), 101–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowaczyk, A. (2015). Jak czytać Ajdukiewicza. Przegląd Filozoficzny. Nowa Seria, 1(93), 9–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olech, A. (2015). Ajdukiewicz and Husserl on the issue of the meaning of expressions. Studia Semiotyczne − English Supplement, XXIV, 130–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (1997). Is compositionality compatible with holism? Mind & Language, 12(1), 11–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1997). Holism. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 227–247). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Reference and reflexivity. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1960). The runabout inference ticket. Analysis, 21, 38–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind language and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1950). Identity, ostension, and hypostasis. Journal of Philosophy, 47(22), 621–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1953). Two dogmas of empiricism. In W. V. Quine (Ed.), From a logical point of view (pp. 20–46). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1978). Literal meaning. Erkenntnis, 1, 207–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 253–329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2009). Reference, inference and the semantics of pejoratives. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), The philosophy of David Kaplan (pp. 137–158). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1998). Does ontology rest on a mistake? Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 72(1), 229–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Grabarczyk, P. (2019). Troubles Ahead. In: Directival Theory of Meaning. Synthese Library, vol 409. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18783-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics