That Anselm’s God Exists and Gaunilo’s Island Does Not
- 67 Downloads
Abstract
Scholars were greatly indebted to Max Charlesworth for publishing in 1965 the Latin text of Anselm’s Proslogion, together with his own translation and commentary. The intense discussion this argument has received since then has, however, clarified a number of points about the logic of this argument. Its first premise is not a definition of God, and that identification is one of the conclusions of a three-stage argument. Also, the much-discussed issue of the relation of Chap. 3 to Chap. 2 has now been clarified: that the premise with which Anselm begins Chap. 3 is entailed by the conclusion of Chap. 2. For that reason, substituting a description of anything other than God for Anselm’s formula, such as Gaunilo’s Lost Island, entails that that thing both can and could not be thought not to exist. So, no such substitution is legitimate.
Keywords
Max Charlesworth Ontological argument Proslogion, translation of Karl Barth Peter GeachReferences
- Barth, K. (1931/1960) Anselm: Fides quaerens intellectum. (I. W. Robinson, Trans.). London: SCM Press. (Zurich: Evangelischer Verlag, A.G.).Google Scholar
- Campbell, R. (1976). From belief to understanding: A study of Aselm’s arguments for the existence of God. Canberra: ANU.Google Scholar
- Campbell, R. (2018). Rethinking Anselm’s arguments: A vindication of his proof of the existence of God. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Charlesworth, M. (1962). St. Anselm’s argument. Sophia, 1(2), 25–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Charlesworth, M. (1965). St. Anselm’s Proslogion. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Davies, B. (2004). Anselm and the ontological argument. In The Cambridge companion to Anselm. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Deane, S. N. (1962). St Anselm – Basic writings (2nd ed.). La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
- Eder, G., & Rambarter, E. (2015). Formal reconstructions of St. Anselm’s ontological argument. Synthese, 192, 2795–2825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Garrett, B. (2013). On behalf of Gaunilo. Analysis, 73(3), 481–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Geach, P. T. (1977). Review of Campbell (1976). Philosophy, 52(2), 234–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hopkins, J. (1978). On understanding and preunderstanding St. Anselm. The New Scholasticism, LII(2), 243–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hopkins, J. (1981). On an alleged definitive interpretation of Proslogion 2-4: A discussion of G. Schufreider’s An introduction to Anselm’s argument. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 19(1), 129–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hopkins, J. (1986). A new interpretative translation of Anselm’s Monologion and Proslogion. Minneapolis: A.J. Banning Press.Google Scholar
- La Croix, R. (1972). Proslogion II and III: A third interpretation of Anselm’s argument. Leiden: E.J. Brill.Google Scholar
- Logan, I. (2009). Reading Anselm’s Proslogion: The history and Anselm’s argument and its significance today. Farnham: Ashgate.Google Scholar
- Oppy, G. (1995). Ontological arguments and belief in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Oppy, G. (2011). On behalf of the fool. Analysis, 71(2), 304–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Plantinga, A. (1974). God, freedom, and evil. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans Publishing Company.Google Scholar
- Schufreider, G. (1978). An introduction to Anselm’s argument. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
- Smith, A. D. (2014). Anselm’s Other Argument. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Visser, S., & Williams, T. (2009). Anselm (Great medieval thinkers). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar