Skip to main content

No Justification for Weapons Research

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Morality of Weapons Research

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Ethics ((BRIEFSETHIC))

  • 204 Accesses

Abstract

If there can be no ahistorical justification for weapons research, then all attempts at justification must be historical : they must refer to the situations and circumstances in which weapons are actually used. In view of the general condition for all such justification, in terms of harm prevention, it must be the case that the harms caused by the use of the weapons produced must also prevent harm, and moreover, the harms caused must not be excessive and the harms prevented must at least be comparable to, and preferably much less than, those caused. But the problem here is that weapons designers cannot know what is going to happen in the future when it comes to the ways the weapons they design are used (if indeed they are ever used). If they cannot know what they must know in order for their work to be justified, then justification of weapons research will not in fact be possible. I am going to spend this chapter and the next making good this claim. If I am able to do so, then I will have shown that weapons research is never morally permissible : that is to say, in no circumstances and under no conditions is it ever morally acceptable to undertake weapons research. The case against weapons research will have been made.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For more details and many examples, see Brody (1988).

  2. 2.

    But is often not clear how to decide what to do even when it seems that the harm to be caused and the harms prevented are relatively clear. For instance, if medical treatment promises to prolong a someone’s life at the expense of the quality of that life, different people may make different judgements about how these prospective outcomes are ranked.

  3. 3.

    Brian Orend’s The Morality of War, Orend (2006), is a clear exposition of JWT which follows Walzer’s original formulation. Larry May (ed.) The Cambridge Handbook of The Just War, May 2018, is the most recent (at the time of writing) of a number of books published since Walzer (1977). In the foreword and in the introduction to this collection it is mentioned that there has been renewed interest in JWT in the present century and in particular so-called revisionist Just War Theorists have challenged some elements to the orthodoxy, for instance in regard to the moral equality of soldiers.

  4. 4.

    A distinction is now made between non-combatants, people who do not fight but nevertheless contribute to the war effort, for instance by working in armaments factories, and civilians who make no such direct contribution. The former are (sometimes) considered to be ‘legitimate’ targets. The British, Churchill in particular, claimed that bombing German cities was the only way to fight back and moreover it was an acceptable tactic because it would weaken the German people’s will to continue the war. It didn’t and it was no excuse .

  5. 5.

    I should stress that this is not the standard sense of the term, which is usually taken to mean that any measures can be used in war that are necessary for achieving objectives, provided that they do no violate international humanitarian law and that the objectives are legitimate. My usage drops the latter two qualifications.

  6. 6.

    And I assume one would think them more likely to do so than other kind of states.

  7. 7.

    Parliamentary democracy in England was certainly in place by 1832 with the Reform Act, but there were parliaments in England from 1265. England, and then Britain , waged many unjust wars of colonisation and conquest, right up until the First World War . Many more examples of democracies doing the same can be given.

  8. 8.

    This topic is raised in my detailed discussion of JWT in Forge (2012): see Chaps. 10, 11 and 13 of that book. In his foreword to May 2018, Jeff McMahan , having noted the changing character of warfare in the last two decades, suggests that much recent writing on JWT has been internal to the field, with philosophers addressing other philosophers, and not with the developments he mentions. This does not surprise me. And I note that this most recent collection on JWT has nothing at all to say about ad bellum proportionality, my topic in the next section of this chapter.

  9. 9.

    A theory about why states go to war which has it that states are only concerned with their own vital interests, such as Realism, would maintain that the calculation of costs vs benefits would be restricted to those of the state in question. They would be ‘selfish’ costs and benefits.

  10. 10.

    If all there was to the costs and benefits were harms caused and harms prevented, then ad bellum proportionality would reduce to a specific instance of JP.

  11. 11.

    These questions surely arise for anyone who would make some rational assessment about the decision to go to war, including those who are concerned exclusively with their own interests. Looking at the question from the Realist perspective, the problems are less difficult because it is only A’s costs and benefits that are at issue, and not those of anyone else.

  12. 12.

    This is reminiscent of Walzer’s notion of a supreme emergency, see Forge (2012, Chap. 13).

References

  • Brody, B. 1988. Life and Death Decision Making. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, E. 1946. Twenty Years of Crisis. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forge, J. 2009. Proportionality, Just War Theory and Weapons Innovation. Science and Engineering Ethics 15: 25–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forge, J. 2012. Designed to Kill: The Case Against Weapons Research. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gert, B. 2005. Morality: Its Nature and Justification. Revised Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. 2005. Proportionality and the Morality of War. Philosophy and Public Affairs 33: 34–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. 2011. Contingent Pacifism and the Moral Risks of Participating in War. Public Affairs Quarterly 2 (25): 95–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. 2010. Pacifism and Moral Theory. Diametros 23: 48–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orend, B. 2006. The Morality of War. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Forge .

Appendix: Pacifism and Weapons Research

Appendix: Pacifism and Weapons Research

JWT has been compared and contrasted, by Orend for instance, with Realism on the one hand and Pacifism on the other (Orend 2006: 4–5). The difference between the three in regard to war is (roughly) as follows: JWT holds that war is morally permissible under certain conditions, namely, those set out in the theory; Pacifism denies that war is ever morally permissible , while Realism maintains that morality has nothing to do with wars nor any other kind of relations between states (cf Carr 1946: 153). Pacifism and JWT resemble one another in applying a moral standard to war, but differ in that the former’s is stronger. For the Realist, war may be necessary or expedient, depending on whether it defends or promotes the vital interests of the state, nothing more. My own view is that Realism is the correct account of what wars are and why states go to war, whatever statespeople might say. I have given no argument in favour or against either of the other two theories as the correct normative account of war, and, moreover, as should be clear by now, my argument against weapons research does not presuppose either theory, in that it has no premise drawn from either of them. I have focused on JWT because it is more permissive in regard to war and hence one would suppose it would allow (some, or more) weapons research. We have seen that it does not. My argument against weapons research is therefore consistent with JWT , but does it give us any reason to prefer it to Pacifism, or conversely?

Pacifism and JWT evidently differ in terms of what roles they allow for armed forces and the weapons they wield: JWT allows that armies, etc., can go to war to resist aggression, but Pacifism in the traditional sense does not. This in itself, however, does not imply that Pacficists must maintain that states cannot have armed forces, it is just that they cannot use them to fight wars. This might seen spurious until we remember that weapons can be used to deter, to prevent others starting wars. A pacifist deterrent threat will be empty because war is not permissible, but that does not mean that it could not be efficacious. In this way we can see how Pacifism can be consistent with weapons research, namely with weapons research done with the intention of providing the means for deterrence . We have established that deterrence is a derivative function of a weapon and that there is no such thing as ‘purely deterring’ weapons, and hence any pacifist-sponsored weapons research would still have to produce the means to harm in order to obtain the means to deter. One might expect Pacifists to also maintain that threats to violence are impermissible and hence that deterrence is also not allowed. Nevertheless, it appears that Pacifism simpliciter and weapons research are strictly speaking incompatible, in the sense that the denial that war is ever morally permissible does not imply that weapons research is morally impermissible .

There are versions of Pacifism that do not deny that participation in all wars is morally wrong, something that Orend for one finds ‘strange ’ (Orend 2006: 244), with one such variety, known as contingent Pacifism, being of current interest (for example, May 2011; McMahan 2010) . It is worth saying a little more about this idea here. The point about contingent Pacifism is that its starting point or main premise is not that war is always forbidden. It is rather than wars are very bad indeed, and should only be undertaken if it is clear that they will prevent outcomes that would be very much worse than the war is. This is a stronger demand that there is just cause and that the proportionality condition is satisfied.Footnote 12 However, and here we do see some resemblance to my position, since one can never be sure that this demand is satisfied, in practice it entails a prohibition on all war, hence the Pacifist stance is contingent . If there were a complete cessation of weapons research, given that everyone were to accept that it is morally wrong, then this would eventually lead to world in which it would look as if everyone was a Pacifist because there would no longer be the means to fight wars, so no one could fight and there would be no more war. This not contingent Pacifism as such because the argument does not depend on any judgement about the rightness or wrongness of war. However, since the contingent Pacifist holds, in effect, that the ad bellum proportionality calculation cannot be carried through, then she and I share the same view on this issue.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Forge, J. (2019). No Justification for Weapons Research. In: The Morality of Weapons Research . SpringerBriefs in Ethics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16860-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics