Skip to main content

Space, Time and the Representation of Geographical Reality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of GIS

Part of the book series: Springer Geography ((SPRINGERGEOGR))

Abstract

Geographical information science is interesting from a philosophical point of view because the distinctions that its practitioners find themselves compelled to make have important resonances with distinctions that have been proposed in other contexts. An example is the dichotomy between object-based and field-based presentations of geographical data. This paper explores the relationships amongst a set of closely aligned distinctions which have appeared in the literature on both spatial and temporal reasoning in philosophy, cognitive science, geographical science, linguistics and other fields. Any systematic account of such distinctions must inform the construction of a workable ontology for spatio-temporal sciences such as geography.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Couclelis (1992) refers to the process of creating a vector model as that of ‘carving up the continuous landscape into discrete objects’. The continuous/discrete contrast is here aligned not with raster/vector so much as with reality/model, the model being understood to be vector-based.

  2. 2.

    Compare (Peuquet 1994), where the parallel is drawn between the raster/vector dichotomy and ‘objective’ versus ‘subjective’ views of space. Note that objective/subjective and absolute/relative form another pair of dichotomies which, though quite distinct, are closely enough related to be often confused.

  3. 3.

    Notwithstanding Gordon’s assertion that ‘the distinction between a material and a structure is never very clear’ (Gordon 1968). But Gordon’s otherwise excellent discussion shows little sensitivity to the mass/count distinction, e.g. between material (mass) and a piece of material (count), and between a structure (count) and what might be called ‘structured material’, characterised by the indefinite repetition of structural units. Greater sensitivity is shown by Vogel (1988): ‘Bone is made of several materials in an orderly array; but is bone therefore a structure or merely a composite material; or do we call bone generically a material but a particular bone, with shape, a structure?’

  4. 4.

    More generally, Bunt (1985) speaks of ‘phenomena that we perceive not as consisting of discrete elements, but as having a more or less homogeneous, continuous structure’.

  5. 5.

    See Johansson (1998) for a discussion of the notion of pattern as an important ontological category. Johansson’s patterns are not far removed from the notion of texture used here. Johansson hints at a distinction between a count interpretation of pattern as a bounded patterned unity and a mass interpretation as an indefinitely extensible texture, but he does not explicitly acknowledge the importance of the mass/count distinction here.

  6. 6.

    Muller (1998) advocates a thoroughgoing four-dimensionalism in which the objects of enquiry are chunks of spacetime with no preferential form of slicing assumed; but within this framework, he accords privileged status to the notion of a ‘temporal slice’. Note also that there is no discussion of how the mass/count distinction is manifested in the four-dimensional world.

  7. 7.

    Zemach (1970) distinguishes four possible ontological schemes by whether they treat their entities as persisting across space, over time, both, or neither, and claims that all four are used in everyday thinking, though not with the same frequency.

  8. 8.

    This latter is the point of view of the Event Calculus (Kowalski and Sergot 1986) which has been highly influential in the development of temporal reasoning schemes for Artificial Intelligence.

  9. 9.

    In the terminology of Peuquet (1984), this is ‘adjacent polygon’  data.

  10. 10.

    At a finer granularity it looks more discrete: the successive addition of new buildings, streets, etc. At a finer granularity still all these events consist of the continuous motion of matter.

References

  • Bunt H (1985) The formal representation of (quasi-)continuous concepts. In: Hobbs JR, Moore RC (eds) Formal theories of the commonsense world. Ablex Publishing Corporation, Norwood, NJ, pp 37–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman NR (1998) Rethinking levels of measurement for cartography. Cartogr Geogr Inf Sci 25(4):231–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Comrie B (1976) Aspect: an introduction to the study of verbal aspect and related problems. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Couclelis H (1992) People manipulate objects (but cultivate fields): beyond the raster-vector debate in GIS. In: Frank AU, Campari I, Formentini U (eds) Theories and methods of spatio-temporal reasoning in geographic space. Lecture notes in computer science, vol 639. Springer, Berlin, pp 65–77

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Galton A (1984) The logic of aspect: an axiomatic approach. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton A (2000) Qualitative spatial change. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton A (2011) Time flies but space doesn’t: limits to the spatialization of time. J Pragmat 43:695–703

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galton A (2018) Processes as patterns of occurrence. In: Stout R (ed) Process, action, and experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 41–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon JE (1968) The new science of strong materials. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes PJ (1985) Naive physics I: ontology for liquids. In: Hobbs JR, Moore RC (eds) Formal theories of the commonsense world. Ablex Publishing Corporation, Norwood, NJ, pp 71–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansson I (1998) Pattern as an ontological category. In: Guarino N (ed) Formal ontology in information systems. IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 86–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski RA, Sergot MJ (1986) A logic-based calculus of events. New Gener Comput 4:67–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy J, Hayes PJ (1969) Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. In: Melzer B, Michie D (eds) Machine intelligence, vol 4. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller P (1998) Eléments d’une théorie du mouvement pour la formalisation du raisonnement spatio-temporel de sens commun. Ph.D. thesis, Université Paul Sabatier, Toulouse III

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier FJ (ed) (1979) Mass terms: some philosophical problems. D. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Peuquet DJ (1984) A conceptual framework and comparison of spatial data models. Cartographica 21(4):66–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peuquet DJ (1994) It’s about time: a conceptual framework for the representation of temporal dynamics in geographis information systems. Ann Assoc Am Geogr 84(3):441–461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens SS (1946) On the theory of scales of measurement. Science 103(2684):677–680

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tedeschi P, Zaenen A (eds) (1981) Tense and aspect. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl HJ (1993) A theory of aspectuality: the interaction between temporal and atemporal structure, vol 64. Cambridge studies in linguistics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel S (1988) Life’s devices: the physical world of animals and plants. Princeon University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Worboys MF (1994) Unifying the spatial and temporal components of geographic information. In: Waugh TC, Healey RG (eds) Advances in geographic information systems: proceedings of the sixth international symposium on spatial data handling, Edinburgh, Taylor and Francis, London, pp 505–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Worboys MF (1995) GIS: a computing perspective. Taylor & Francis, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Zemach EM (1970) Four ontologies. J Philos 67:213–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antony Galton .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Galton, A. (2019). Space, Time and the Representation of Geographical Reality. In: Tambassi, T. (eds) The Philosophy of GIS. Springer Geography. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16829-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics