Skip to main content

On Leaving as Little to Chance as Possible

  • Chapter
Book cover Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift
  • 366 Accesses

Abstract

Randomness was one of Mario Bunge’s earliest philosophical interests, and remains as one of his most persistent. Bunge’s view of the nature of randomness has been largely consistent over many decades, despite some evolution. For a long time now, he has seen chance as a purely ontological matter of contingency, something that does not result from either psychological uncertainty or epistemological indeterminacy, and that disappears once the die is cast. He considers the Bayesian school of probability and statistics to be pseudoscientific. Bunge upholds a fairly conventional view that chance is not any part of the purely mathematical theory of probability, and a thoroughly unconventional view that ontologically contingent processes are deterministic, though not classically so. This chapter examines Bunge’s views on probability by investigating what any of the following have to do with each other: chance or randomness, likelihood, the mathematical theory of probability, determinism, independence, belief, psychological uncertainty, and epistemological indeterminacy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In his Foundations of Physics, Bunge says “Kolmogoroff himself did employ a misleading terminology but it is as supernumerary as the observer and the ideal experiment in [quantum mechanics]... random samplings will occur in informal inferences and in applications of [the calculus of probability] not in its foundations.” (Bunge 1967, p. 90)

  2. 2.

    Those who insist that equiprobability is all that is needed have two options: explain why the probabilities should be equal; or offer no explanation. The former is the same as explaining why the respective events should be considered equivalent, while the latter is the same as assigning their equivalence arbitrarily. Thus, there is no escaping the concept of equal (or else proportional) likelihood, whether arising naturally or assigned arbitrarily.

  3. 3.

    The concept of likelihood (of events) in classical probability is not the same as the technical concept of likelihood (of model parameters) introduced by Fisher and as used in modern statistics, both Bayesian and non-Bayesian (see e.g. Reid 2013).

  4. 4.

    That is, stopped at a time drawn from a probability distribution whose values are proportional to the radii of the circles of latitude crossed at the corresponding times, and so to the surface areas between corresponding differentially (infinitesimally) separated lines of latitude.

  5. 5.

    Transition probabilities are instead modelled using sequences of random variables indexed by a set used to represent time values. This extends the basic theory to the theory of stochastic processes (see Sect. 34.6).

  6. 6.

    In purely mathematical problems, there is no reason for the conditional probability P(A | B) to be read as “the probability of A, given that B has occurred”. Instead it should be read as “the probability of B, given that A is the case”; or in other words, the probability of A renormalized to B as the sample space.

  7. 7.

    Bunge says something similar in e.g. volume 5 of his Treatise, where he held that “A sequence of events can be said to be random if every event in it has a definite probability; otherwise the sequence is either chaotic or causal. This is not the standard definition of randomness—but then there is no standard definition.” (Bunge 1983, pp. 365–366)

  8. 8.

    This is a change from the view Bunge expressed in volume 3 of his Treatise, where he said “Randomness, being a special case of stochasticity, is a type of order” (Bunge 1977, p. 209).

  9. 9.

    A series is a sum of (finitely or infinitely many) terms, a sequence (or string) is a list of them.

  10. 10.

    There is though a formula that allows computation of any particular digit of the binary or hexadecimal expansion of π. It has been proven that there is no formula of its type for expansions in any base that is not a power of 2 (Borwein et al. 2004; Bailey and Borwein 2014).

  11. 11.

    In Chasing Reality, Bunge says there are three: event, probability space, and probability measure (Bunge 2006, p. 100). By “probability space” Bunge refers to the σ-algebra (field) of measurable subsets.

  12. 12.

    In Evaluating Philosophies, Bunge says “objective indeterminacy implies subjective uncertainty—though not conversely” (Bunge 2012, p. 108). Yet the former implication is also false. It is so easy and common to be certain about outcomes which are not fixed in advance that the corresponding vocabulary is part of everyday life, to include overconfidence, hubris, and counting chickens before they are hatched.

  13. 13.

    Bunge has it instead as a random individual who tests positive for HIV, but this complicates the problem over his subsequent discussions, because positive tests have a probability of being false.

  14. 14.

    Bunge may have eventually realized this, as later he objected for different reasons:

    ...what is the use of this exercise? None, because what we need to know is the mechanisms of infection and immunity, and this is a matter for scientific research, not for logic. And if these mechanisms turn out to be causal rather than stochastic, we will not need the probability calculus either. We may call this objection the argument from barrenness. (Bunge 2010, p. 25)

  15. 15.

    Bunge has mentioned this problem by name (Bunge 2012, p. 107), but without the second step that makes it interesting. He has also often commented on what sounds like it should be an equivalent problem, phrased in terms of three of the Apostles. It is inequivalent because the contestant does not make any selection, let alone two, only the “host” does. The paradox can be resolved similarly though. Bunge holds that problem to be effectively the same as the Monty Hall problem, and that in both cases no chance is involved and it makes no sense to talk about the probability of winning (e.g. Bunge 2003, pp. 229–230).

  16. 16.

    At one time Bunge explicitly claimed it possible to go from non-probabilistic premises to probabilistic ones using the method of arbitrary functions (Bunge 1969, p. 445), but that was incorrect and in his writings since then he has consistently asserted the contrary.

  17. 17.

    Bunge has also objected to the propensity label, preferring to call his own version the objectivist or realist interpretation (Bunge 2006, p. 103).

  18. 18.

    “Propensity methods” is sometimes used as a description for propensity score matching methods as invented by Rubin, but they are not a reconceptualization of statistics in propensity terms, and include a Bayesian aspect. See Rubin (2007).

  19. 19.

    Likelihoods as used in the technical statistical sense do not obey the laws of probability (see e.g. Cox and Mayo 2010).

References

  • Bailey, D. H., & Borwein, J. (2014). Pi Day is upon us again and we still do not know if Pi is normal. American Mathematical Monthly, 121(3), 191–206. https://doi.org/10.4169/amer.math.monthly.121.03.191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayer, D., & Diaconis, P. (1992). Trailing the dovetail shuffle to its lair. Annals of Applied Probability, 2(2), 294–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J. (2006). The case for objective Bayesian analysis. Bayesian Analysis, 1(3), 385–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borwein, J. M., Galway, W. F., & Borwein, D. (2004). Finding and excluding b-ary Machin-type BBP formulae. Canadian Journal of Mathematics, 56, 1339–1342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1951). What is chance? Science & Society, 15(3), 209–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1967). Foundations of physics (Springer tracts in natural philosophy, Vol. 10). New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1969). Corrections to foundations of physics: Correct and incorrect. Synthese, 19, 443–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1977). Ontology I: The furniture of the world (Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 3). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979). Ontology II: A world of systems (Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 4). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1981). Four concepts of probability. Applied Mathematical Modelling, 5, 306–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1983). Epistemology & methodology I: Exploring the world (Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 5). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1985). Epistemology & methodology III: Philosophy of science and technology—Part I—formal and physical sciences (Treatise on basic philosophy, Vol. 7). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Emergence and convergence: Qualitative novelty and the Unity of knowledge. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2006). Chasing reality: Strife over realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2008). Bayesianism: Science or pseudoscience? International Review of Victimology, 15, 165–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2010). Matter and mind: A philosophical inquiry (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, Vol. 287). Dordrecht/Heidelberg/London/New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2012). Evaluating philosophies (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, Vol. 295). Dordrecht/Heidelberg/New York/London: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2013). Medical philosophy: Conceptual issues in medicine. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carriquiry, A. L., & Pawlovich, M. (2004). From empirical Bayes to full Bayes: Methods for analyzing traffic safety data. Iowa Department of Transportation, Office of Traffic and Safety. https://www.iowadot.gov/crashanalysis/pdfs/eb_fb_comparison_whitepaper_october2004.pdf. Accessed 13 June 2018.

  • Cox, D. R. (2006). Frequentist and Bayesian statistics: A critique (keynote address). In Statistical problems in particle physics, astrophysics and cosmology: Proceedings, PHYSTAT05, Oxford, UK, 12–15 September 2005, World Scientific, Singapore, pp. 3–6. https://doi.org/10.1142/9781860948985_0001.

  • Cox, D. R., & Brandwood, L. (1959). On a discriminatory problem connected with the works of Plato. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series B (Methodological), 21(1), 195–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, D. R., & Mayo, D. (2010). Objectivity and conditionality in frequentist inference. In D. Mayo & A. Spanos (Eds.), Error and inference: Recent exchanges on experimental reasoning, reliability and the objectivity and rationality of science (pp. 276–304). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://www.phil.vt.edu/dmayo/personal_website/ch%207%20cox%20%26%20mayo.pdf. Accessed 11 Feb 2018.

  • Diaconis, P., Holmes, S., & Montgomery, R. (2007). Dynamical bias in the coin toss. SIAM Review, 49(2), 211–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Efron, B. (2013). A 250-year argument: Belief, behavior, and the bootstrap. Bulletin (New Series) of the American Mathematical Society, 50(1), 129–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauer, E. (1997). Observational before—after studies in road safety: Estimating the effect of highway and traffic engineering measures on road safety. Amsterdam: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (1985). Why propensities cannot be probabilities. The Philosophical Review, 94(4), 557–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2005). Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Medicine. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschenmann, P. (1973). Concepts of randomness. In M. Bunge (Ed.), Exact philosophy: Problems, tools, and goals (pp. 129–148). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933/1956). Foundations of the theory of probability (Second English Edition) (N. Morrison, Trans.). New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P. S. (1814). Théorie Analytique des Probabilités (2nd ed.). Paris: Courcier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, R. (2003). QED: How to spot the pattern in a game of chance. The Telegraph, 17 July. https://www.telegraph.co.uk/technology/3310656/QED-How-to-spot-the-pattern-in-a-game-of-chance.html. Accessed 18 June 2018.

  • Persaud, B., & Lyon, C. (2007). Empirical Bayes before–after safety studies: Lessons learned from two decades of experience and future directions. Accident Analysis and Prevention, 39, 546–555. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.aap.2006.09.009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrone, S., Rizzelli, S., Rousseau, J., & Scricciolo, C. (2014). Empirical Bayes methods in classical and Bayesian inference. Metron, 72, 201–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, N. (2013). Aspects of likelihood inference. Bernoulli, 19(4), 1404–1418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, N., & Cox, D. R. (2015). On some principles of statistical inference. International Statistical Review, 83(2), 293–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. M. (2007). The design versus the analysis of observational studies for causal effects: Parallels with the design of randomized trials. Statistics in Medicine, 26, 20–36. https://doi.org/10.1002/sim.2739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G., & Vovk, V. (2006). The sources of Kolmogorov’s Grundbegriffe. Statistical Science, 21(1), 70–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tervo, D. G. R., Proskurin, M., Manakov, M., Kabra, M., Vollmer, A., Branson, K., & Karpova, A. Y. (2014). Behavioral variability through stochastic choice and its gating by anterior cingulate cortex. Cell, 159(1), 21–32. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2014.08.037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volchan, S. B. (2002). What is a random sequence? American Mathematical Monthly, 109(1), 46–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • vos Savant, M. (1990). Game show problem. http://marilynvossavant.com/game-show-problem/. Accessed 11 Feb 2018.

Download references

Acknowledgement

I thank Michael Matthews and Paul McColl for their respective contributions in shepherding the manuscript through its various stages.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kary, M. (2019). On Leaving as Little to Chance as Possible. In: Matthews, M.R. (eds) Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16673-1_34

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics