Skip to main content

Reasonable Grounds

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Towards a Liberatory Epistemology

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

  • 174 Accesses

Abstract

A moral obligation to understand the social realty of the other requires a normative ground. This ground can be found by considering the concept of reasonableness, which appeals to norms in much broader and open-ended ways than methodological accounts of reason. To be reasonable is to apply the skills and formal elements of rationality in real life contexts—and to do so from a variety of perspectives instead of just one privileged perspective. With such a change in emphasis, impartiality becomes linked with open-mindedness and a willingness to correct for prejudice when considering the credibility of others. Being reasonable, then, is a contextually determined virtue that guides us toward the overcoming of ignorance and a genuine understanding of others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I have, for example, a dog that loves to roll in every nasty smell he finds in the woods. I truly do not understand the attractiveness of such an activity, although I recognize that he thoroughly enjoys it. My concept of smells-it-would-be-good-to-roll-in is much, much smaller than my dog’s.

  2. 2.

    See Spelman (2007, 123).

  3. 3.

    Elsewhere I have argued in defense of reason, albeit a reason decidedly different from the modern variety. See Heikes (2010).

  4. 4.

    This march occurred on Earth Day, April 22, 2017.

    Of course, as feminist philosophers of science will point out, scientists have probably overplayed their authoritative hand. Science is a lot less objective and a lot more culpable in oppressive practices than many in the field have liked to think.

  5. 5.

    For example, see Lynch (2012).

  6. 6.

    For more on these efforts see Toulmin (1991) and Kitcher (2016).

  7. 7.

    Quoted in Mills (1997, 25).

  8. 8.

    The question is how to signal this shift. One way of doing this is to simply alter the terms of the discussion, and philosophers who have done this include: Burbules, Kitcher, Rawls, Siegel, and Toulmin. These philosophers downplay “reason” in favor of discussions of “reasonableness.”

  9. 9.

    See Toulmin (2001, 24–28).

  10. 10.

    See Siegel (1997, 104–110).

  11. 11.

    For a critical take on Rawls’ use of the reasonable, see (Heikes 2018).

  12. 12.

    The most obvious example here is Mills (1997). For more on the inherent racism of modernism see West (2002).

  13. 13.

    While neither Mills nor Okin reject contract theory, both are critical of it with respect to issues of race and gender. See Mills (1997, 2000). Also see Okin (2005).

  14. 14.

    As Friedman notes, “no overt or covert gender bias is built into his [Rawls’] conception” (2000, 26).

  15. 15.

    See Friedman (2000, 22–23).

  16. 16.

    See Mills (2007, 14). Also see Antony (2002, 142).

  17. 17.

    Of course, not all calls for change are ones that need to be embraced. But they should at least be given a genuinely fair hearing.

  18. 18.

    As we look beyond what it is we actually do, we must consider more than just the axes of power relations. Reasonableness cuts across moral axes as well. These moral axes are identified by Charles Taylor as “our sense of respect for an obligation to others, … our understanding of what makes a life full… [and] the range of notions concerned with dignity” (Taylor 1989, 15). I address this point elsewhere, but sensitivity on each of these points is something we expect from the reasonable person. In other words, the person who is reasonable cannot be insensitive to the moral dimension of our lives.

  19. 19.

    Cf. Tanesini.

References

  • Alcoff, Linda Martín. 1995. “Is the Feminist Critique of Reason Rational?” Philosophical Topics 23 (2): 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Antony, Louise. 2002. “Quine as Feminist.” In A Mind of One’s Own, edited by Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt, 110–153. Cambridge, MA: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, Jason. 2011. “The Structure of Open-Mindedness.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (2): 191–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burbules, Nicholas C. 1991. “Rationality and Reasonableness.” Educational Theory 41 (2): 235–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burbules, Nicholas C. 1995. “Reasonable Doubt: Toward a Postmodern Defense of Reason as an Educational Aim.” In Critical Conversations in Philosophy of Education, edited by Wendy Kohli, 82–102. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, Lorraine. 1991. What Can She Know? Ithaca and New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalmiya, Vrinda. 2001. “Knowing People.” In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, edited by Matthias Steup, 221–234. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eze, Emmanuel. 2008. On Reason: Rationality in a World of Cultural Conflict and Racism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1982. “The Subject and Power.” Critical Inquiry 8 (4): 777–795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Marilyn. 1995. “Feminism and Modern Friendship: Dislocating the Community.” In Feminism & Community, edited by Penny Weiss and Marilyn Friedman, 187–208. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Marilyn. 2000. “John Rawls and the Political Coercion of Unreasonable People.” In The Idea of Political Liberalism: Essays on Rawls, edited by V. Davion and C. Wolf, 16–33. Lanham, Massachusetts: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heikes, Deborah K. 2010. Rationality and Feminist Philosophy. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heikes, Deborah K. 2018. “Rationality as an Epistemic Virtue.” In The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Feminism, edited by Pieranna Garavaso, 260–280. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1963. Lecture on Ethics. Translated by Louis Infield. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 2016. “Rationality for Dummies.” In What Reason Promises: Essays on Reason, Nature and History, edited by Susan Neiman, Peter Galison, and Wendy Doniger, 19–25. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, Michael Patrick. 2012. In Praise of Reason: Why Rationality Matters for Democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 1997. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 2000. “Race and the Social Contract Tradition.” Social Identities 6 (4): 441–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 2002. “Kant’s Untermenschen.” Paper, Thirty-six Annual University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Colloquium in Philosophy, Chapel Hill, NC, October 26–27: 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 2007. “White Ignorance.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 13–38. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, Robert. 1993. The Nature of Rationality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin, Susan Moller. 2005. “‘Forty Acres and a Mule for Women: Rawls and Feminism.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 4 (2): 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1953. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1985. “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 14 (3): 223–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, Phyllis. 2011. “The Marginalization of Feminist Philosophy.” In Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science: Power in Knowledge, edited by Heidi Grasswick, 3–24. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sibley, W.M. 1953. “The Rational Versus the Reasonable.” The Philosophical Review 62 (4): 554–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, Harvey. 1997. Rationality Redeemed? New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelman, Elizabeth. 2007. “Managing Ignorance.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 119–131. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 1991. “The Dream of an Exact Language.” In Dialogue and Technology: Art and Knowledge, edited by Bo Göranzon and Magnus Florin, 33–42. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 2001. Return to Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, Cornel. 2002. “A Geneology of Modern Racism.” In Race Critical Theories, edited by Philomena Essed and David Theo. Goldberg. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Deborah K. Heikes .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Heikes, D.K. (2019). Reasonable Grounds. In: Towards a Liberatory Epistemology. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16485-0_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics