Skip to main content

Proliferating Virtues: A Clear and Present Danger?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Virtue Ethics: Retrospect and Prospect

Abstract

The needless proliferation of virtues is a possible pitfall of the explosion of work in virtue ethics. I discuss two positions on proliferation and offer my own. Russell (Practical intelligence and the virtues. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009) takes the first approach, arguing that virtue ethical right action is impossible unless we adopt a finite and specifiable list of the virtues. I argue against this. Hursthouse (Working virtue: virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2007) offers a second perspective, looking first to standard Aristotelian virtues, and adding virtues only when the standard list fails to capture something of moral importance. Like Hursthouse (Working virtue: virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2007), I believe that questions arising from applied ethics present the real challenge to the adequacy of traditional lists of virtues. These challenges are becoming increasingly urgent. Technologies are not only shaping our conceptions of ourselves, the human good, and virtues, but also, through germline gene editing, have the potential to change human nature. My position takes its cue from Hursthouse (Working virtue: virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2007) but goes beyond her by arguing for an “anthropological turn” in virtue ethics. The anthropological turn examines forms of life, especially those influenced by technology and science, and how they affect articulations of the human good and the virtues needed to attain it. Any new virtues, I argue, should be identified through study of how dispositions conducive to human good arise organically within forms of life. In this way, virtues remain grounded in what is good for humans, yet the anthropological turn recognizes that what counts as human good is now in flux because of science and technology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My discussion of Russell draws on Snow (2018).

  2. 2.

    Russell (2014, 217, n. 26) seems to recognize this point, but is skeptical of its force: «It is likely that Aristotle thought the virtues should cover all of the “key areas” of life (e.g., one’s finances, emotions like fear and confidence, etc.), but it is far from obvious either that Aristotle’s catalog does cover all such areas or that he thought it did. It is even less obvious how to identify such “key areas,” how to individuate them, and how to know when they have all been identified.» I think that Aristotle’s virtues give us more guidance about identifying key areas of life than Russell allows, and that, with sufficient reflection, we can amplify Aristotle’s account and identify key areas and the virtues that pertain to them. For example, Kamtekar (2004, 481) offers the following in connection with the situationism debate: «It seems open, then, to an Aristotelian to admit as new domains for practical attention those features of situations that social psychology identifies as particularly consequential for action: in the domain of group effects, there might be a virtue of taking appropriate account of the judgments of others; in the domain of time, a virtue of appropriate punctuality, and so on.» Kamtekar does not here accede to the situationist critique of virtue ethics, but instead, suggests using social psychological studies as tools for the identification of new virtues that arise in various domains—group effects and time—that can cross situation-types. For example, if I have the virtue of taking appropriate account of the judgments of others, I might resist acquiescing in the judgment of my child’s friends that he should be allowed to stay out until midnight on a school night, but assent to the judgment of his teachers that he should improve in his science classes.

  3. 3.

    I think it is quite probable that many ordinary people know many of the virtues on Aristotle’s list, though not under the description of Aristotelian virtue. (For Aristotle’s list of the virtues, see the Nicomachean Ethics, Book IV.) For example, many people who have religious upbringings are aware of the vice of gluttony, which is opposed to temperance. Considerations of temperance also come into play in connection with health and well-being. An interesting question is whether a person can be considered virtuous if she performs a temperate action though not understanding it as an Aristotelian virtue. As suggested in the text, I believe she can be. See also Snow (2018, forthcoming).

  4. 4.

    I am grateful to Candace Vogler for this example.

  5. 5.

    How important and how long-term the relationship had to be for a text break-up to count as seriously disrespectful was left unspecified.

  6. 6.

    Vallor (2016, 210–211) seems to agree. See her condemnation of a human subculture that has a habit of torturing robots—deriving pleasure from the robots’ screams, writhing, and pleas for mercy. Vallor concludes that it is clearly unethical for humans to be cruel in this way, and to derive pleasure from sounds and other physical signs mimicking human reactions to torture, even if no actual pain is caused.

  7. 7.

    In interesting comments on another version of this essay, Nick Austin, S. J., attributes a new virtue, “studiositas,” to Aquinas. Austin contends that studiositas is a form of disciplined attentiveness, which is the positive correlate of Augustine’s “vain curiosity” or “lust of the eyes,” and is needed for the monastic life of study and prayer. Austin remarks that this virtue has relevance for our uses of technologies of connectivity. See Austin (2017).

  8. 8.

    In taking the ‘anthropological turn’ I follow philosophers MacIntyre (1984), Flanagan (2017, Chap. 1), and the anthropologist Laidlaw (2014).

  9. 9.

    See also Robertson (Forthcoming).

  10. 10.

    I hope it is clear from the text that I am not proposing a situationist approach to the articulation of new virtues or the reconceptualization of familiar ones. The manner of developing virtues here proposed does not identify virtues as mere behavioral regularities that are indexed to objectively describable features of situations. Instead, my argument is that reflection on variegated experiences occurring in interactions with technology and other spheres of life can enable us to recognize and develop specific articulations of virtues that take root within those domains. The issue of the generality or specificity of virtue is key to avoiding the situationist trap. Unlike Badhwar (1996) and Adams (2006), I believe that virtues can evolve within specific domains, yet be general enough to be meaningfully relevant across domains. So, for example, I believe there is a single virtue of courage—overcoming fear in the face of a threat—that can be exercised in different physical contexts, such as on the battlefield, or facing cancer treatments, as well as in moral contexts, such as standing up to bullies. Similarly, the virtue of “techcheck” is a single virtue, as described in the text, which can range over various domains of life in which technological interactions of different kinds are salient. In his comments Austin (2017) argues that what I am calling “techcheck” is not really a new virtue, but instead, a new form of temperance—the regulation of our appetites in order to find the right balance or use of technologies of connectivity.

  11. 11.

    I owe this example to a student in the class I mentioned earlier.

  12. 12.

    The twelve technomoral virtues are: honesty, self-control, humility, justice, courage, empathy, care, civility, flexibility, perspective, magnanimity, and technomoral wisdom.

  13. 13.

    A longer version of this essay was presented as the Inaugural Research Series Lecture at the Margaret Beaufort Institute, Cambridge University, October 27, 2017. I am grateful to the audience for their questions and to Nick Austin, S. J., for helpful commentary. Work on this essay was supported by the John Templeton Foundation. The views expressed are my own.

References

  • Aach, John, Jeantine Lunshof, Eswar Iyer, and George M. Church. 2017. Addressing the Ethical Issues Raised by Synthetic Human Entities with Embryo-like Features. eLife 6: e20674. Accessed 20 Mar 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, Robert M. 2006. A Theory of Virtue: Excellence in Being for the Good. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano, Mark. 2013. Character as Moral Fiction. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, Nick, S.J. 2017. Personal Email Communication, Oct 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badhwar, Neera. 1996. The Limited Unity of Virtue. Noûs 30 (3): 306–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Das, Ramon. 2003. Virtue Ethics and Right Action. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81: 324–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 1998. Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics. Noûs 32: 504–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 2002. Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior, 2002. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doudna, Jennifer A., and Samuel H. Sternberg. 2017. A Crack in Creation: Gene Editing and the Unthinkable Power to Control Evolution. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 2017. The Geography of Morals: Varieties of Moral Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 1999. Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99: 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. Human Gene Editing Receives Science Panel’s Support. http://nytimes.com. Aug 4. Accessed 3 Aug 2017.

  • https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gastrulation. Accessed 19 Sept 2017.

  • https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Germ_layer. Accessed 19 Sept 2017.

  • https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nunchi. Accessed 17 Sept 2017.

  • https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Primitive_streakWikipedia. Accessed 19 Sept 2017.

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2007. Environmental Virtue Ethics. In Working Virtue: Virtue Ethics and Contemporary Moral Problems, edited by Rebecca L. Walter and Philip J. Ivanhoe, 155–171. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Robert N. 2003. Virtue and Right. Ethics 113: 810–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar, Rachana. 2004. Situationism and Virtue Ethics on the Content of our Character. Ethics 114: 458–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawall, Jason. 2002. Virtue Theory and Ideal Observers. Philosophical Studies 109: 197–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawall, Jason. forthcoming. Book Review, Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting. Ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, Kristján. 2008. An Aristotelian Critique of Situationism. Philosophy 83: 55–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lahti, Emilia. 2017. https://www.emilialahti.com/what-is-sisu. Accessed 17 Sept 2017.

  • Laidlaw, James. 2014. The Subject of Virtue: An Anthropology of Ethics and Freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lear, Jonathan. 2006. Radical Hope: Ethics in the Face of Cultural Devastation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levefor, G. Tyler, Blaine J. Fowers, Soyeon Ahn, Samantha F. Lang, and Laura M. Cohen. 2017. To What Degree do Situational Influences Explain Spontaneous Helping Behavior? A Meta-Analysis. European Review of Social Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/10463283.2017.1367529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louden, Robert. 1984. On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics. American Philosophical Quarterly 21: 227–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair C. 1984. After Virtue: A Study if Moral Theory, 2nd ed. Notre Dame, IN: The University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merritt, Maria. 2000. Virtue Ethics and Situationist Personality Psychology. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3: 365–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1988. Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1): 32–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, Seth. forthcoming. Nunchi, Ritual, and Early Confucian Ethics. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel C. 2009. Practical Intelligence and the Virtues. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel C. 2014. Phronesis and the Virtues (NE VI. 12–13). In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, edited by Ronald Polansky, 203–220. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharges, John. 2017. http://www.capetownmagazine.com/whats-the-deal-with/ubuntu/125_22_17348. Accessed 17 Sept 2017.

  • Snow, Nancy E. 2018. Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics. In The Oxford Handbook of Virtue Ethics, edited by Nancy E. Snow, 321–342. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snow, Nancy E. Under review. The Perils of Magnificence. In Neglected Virtues, edited by Glen Pettigrove and Christine Swanton. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, Gopal. 2013. The Situationist Critique of Virtue Ethics. In The Cambridge Companion to Virtue Ethics, edited by Daniel C. Russell, 290–314. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Allen. 2010. Radical Hope for Living Well in a Warmer World. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 23: 43–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallor, Shannon. 2016. Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williston, Byron. 2015. The Anthropocene Project: Virtue in the Age of Climate Change. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmer, Carl. 2017. A New Form of Stem-Cell Engineering Raises Ethical Questions. https://www.nytimes.com/2017/03/21/science/embryonic-stem-cells-synthetic-embryos-sheefs.html. Accessed 11 July 2018.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nancy E. Snow .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Snow, N.E. (2019). Proliferating Virtues: A Clear and Present Danger?. In: Grimi, E. (eds) Virtue Ethics: Retrospect and Prospect. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15860-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics