Skip to main content

Moving Stories: Agency, Emotion and Practical Rationality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Value of Emotions for Knowledge
  • 707 Accesses

Abstract

What is it to be an agent? One influential line of thought, endorsed by G. E. M. Anscombe and David Velleman, among others, holds that agency depends on practical rationality—the ability to act for reasons, rather than being merely moved by causes. Over the past 25 years, Velleman has argued compellingly for a distinctive view of agency and the practical rationality with which he associates it. On Velleman’s conception, being an agent consists in having the capacity to be motivated by a drive to act for reasons. Your bodily movements qualify as genuine actions insofar as they are motivated in part by your desire to behave in a way that makes sense to yourself. However, there are at least two distinct ways of spelling out what this drive towards self-intelligibility consists in, both present in Velleman’s work. It might consist in a drive towards intelligibility in causal-psychological terms: roughly, a drive to maximize the rational coherence of your psychological states. Alternatively, it might consist in a drive towards narrative intelligibility: a drive to make your ongoing activity conform to a recognizable narrative structure, where that structure is understood emotionally. Velleman originally saw these options as basically equivalent, but later came to prioritize the drive towards causal-psychological intelligibility over that towards narrative intelligibility. I argue that this gets things the wrong way round—we should instead understand our capacities to render ourselves intelligible in causal-psychological terms as built upon a bedrock of emotionally suffused narrative understanding. In doing so, we resolve several problems for Velleman’s view, and pave the way for an embodied, embedded and affective account of practical rationality and agency. According to the picture that emerges, practical rationality is essential to agency, narrative understanding is essential to practical rationality, and the rhythms and structures patterning the ebb and flow of our emotional lives are essential to narrative understanding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On Velleman’s understanding this way of drawing the act/happening distinction coincides with Anscombe’s epistemic strategy as outlined in the introduction. As we will see, for Velleman the reason-governed way in which the past shapes the future in agency is a function of the distinctive epistemic relation in which an agent stands to her acts.

  2. 2.

    See e.g. Velleman (2006b, 2009, 2014).

  3. 3.

    Velleman (2009) appears to have changed his mind on this score, claiming that the drive towards narrative self-understanding is an optional supplement to the drive towards causal-psychological self-understanding for practical reasoners, ‘at least to some extent’ (p. 204). Below I argue that this is a mistake—it is more plausible to construe causal-psychological understanding as built on a foundation of narrative understanding.

  4. 4.

    The degree of compatibility between Velleman’s views on practical rationality and selfhood and the narrative theories cited above is a delicate issue. A key tenet of Velleman’s work on personhood is that ‘self’ is a multi-purpose reflective pronoun, rather than the designator of a single entity or topic of enquiry (Velleman 2006a). In this chapter our concern is with the mode of reflexive self-understanding that Velleman argues is constitutive of agency. But Velleman is at best agnostic about the relationship between the self-understanding constitutive of agency (understood, roughly, in terms of a drive to act in ways that make sense to ourselves) and the kinds of self-conception with which narrative theorists are frequently concerned (e.g. conceiving of oneself as a loving spouse, committed parent, or hopeless loser). See e.g. Velleman (2001a, 2007, 2009).

  5. 5.

    Note that an agent might be motivated by this drive without having the concept of acting for reasons. It suffices that the drive in fact propels the agent to act reasonably, whether or not the agent understands themselves in these terms (Velleman 1992, pp. 120–121; 2001b, pp. 26–32).

  6. 6.

    In the interests of simplicity I’m writing as if we can legitimately pull apart the explanatory projects of characterizing the constitutive structure of some phenomenon and spelling out how that phenomenon does or could arise in nature. But note that many will be inclined to resist this separation, holding that empirical inquiry and data are our best guides to metaphysical structure. Such folks should be especially sceptical of Velleman’s intellectualism about practical reason.

  7. 7.

    One question that a fully developed version of the present proposal should address concerns the origins of the practices of intersubjective understanding that scaffold development. Given the design specifications above, a suitably developmentally plastic creature will acquire a drive to act intelligibly by the standards of whatever practices of intersubjective understanding are present in its community—hence sophisticated folk-psychological understanding can emerge from primitive narrative understanding. But how do sophisticated practices of intersubjective understanding come to exist in the scaffolding environment in the first place? A naturalistic story here must show how folk-psychological practices like our own can bootstrap themselves into existence from humbler beginnings given the existence of a community of creatures with the psychological structure described above. Sterelny (2003, 2012) and Zawidzki (2013) in particular have provided plausible, empirically informed suggestions about how such bootstrapping could occur.

References

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1957. Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L.F. 2017. The Theory of Constructed Emotion: An Active Inference Account of Interoception and Categorization. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 12 (1): 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. 1999. Identification, Decision, and Treating as a Reason. In Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency, 185–206. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davenport, J. J. (2012). Narrative Identity, Autonomy, and Mortality: From Frankfurt and MacIntyre to Kierkegaard. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1963. Actions, Reasons and Causes. Journal of Philosophy 60 (23): 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D., and N. Humphrey. 1998. Speaking for Our Selves. In Brainchildren: Essays on Designing Minds, 185–206. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1975. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. 1998. Vehicles, Contents, Conceptual Structure and Externalism. Analysis 58 (1): 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. The Shared Circuits Model (SCM): How Control, Mirroring, and Simulation Can Enable Imitation, Deliberation, and Mindreading. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1): 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. 2008. Folk-Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jongepier, F. (2016). Towards a Constitutive Account of Implicit Narrativity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (1): 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, Peter. 2007. On the Distance Between Literary Narratives and Real-Life Narratives. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60: 117–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R.S. 1991. Emotion and Adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M.D. 2005. Bridging Emotion Theory and Neurobiology Through Dynamic Systems Modeling. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (2): 169–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. 1996. Is ‘Self-knowledge’ an Empirical Problem? Renegotiating the Space of Philosophical Explanation. Journal of Philosophy 93 (10): 483–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. The Regulative Dimension of Folk Psychology. In Folk Psychology Reassessed, ed. D.D. Hutto and M. Ratcliffe, 137–156. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. 1981. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M. 2001. Mindreading, Mindshaping, and Evolution. Biology and Philosophy 16: 597–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2004. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Ethics Without Principles. In Philosophy and Social Hope, 185–206. London, UK: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudd, A. 2012. Self, Value and Narrative: A Kierkegaardian Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. 1996. The Constitution of Selves. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (2014). Staying Alive: Personal Identity, Practical Concerns, and the Unity of a Life. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. 2008. Affective Intentionality and the Feeling Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (4): 429–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2003. Thought in a Hostile World. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Evolved Apprentice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, P. (2010). What’s Missing in Episodic Self-Experience? Journal of Consciousness Studies 17(1–1): 119–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. 1999. The Self and the SESMET. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (4): 483–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Against Narrativity. Ratio 17 (4): 428–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. The Subject of Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. 1985. Self-Interpreting Animals. In Philosophical Papers I: Human Agency and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. David. 1989. Practical Reflection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. What Happens When Someone Acts? Mind 101 (403): 461–481; Reprinted in Velleman (2014), pp. 100–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. Identification and Identity. In The Contours of Agency: Themes from the Philosophy of Harry Frankfurt, ed. S. Buss and L. Overton. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; Reprinted in Velleman (2006a), pp. 330–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Introduction. In The Possibility of Practical Reason; Reprinted in Velleman (2014), pp. 11–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Narrative Explanation. Philosophical Review 112 (1): 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Self as Narrator. In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, ed. J. Anderson and J. Christman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Reprinted in Velleman (2006a), pp. 203–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a. Self to Self: Selected Essays. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. The Centered Self; Velleman (2006a), pp. 253–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Reply to Catriona MacKenzie. Philosophical Explorations 10 (3): 283–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. How We Get Along. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The Possibility of Practical Reason, 2nd ed. Ann Arbor, MI: Maize Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. 1982. Free Agency. In Free Will, ed. G. Watson, 205–220. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. 2008. The Function of Folk Psychology: Mind Reading or Mind Shaping? Philosophical Explorations 11 (3): 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Mindshaping: A New Framework for Understanding Human Social Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dave Ward .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ward, D. (2019). Moving Stories: Agency, Emotion and Practical Rationality. In: Candiotto, L. (eds) The Value of Emotions for Knowledge. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15667-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics