Skip to main content

Scientific Realism Meets Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophers Look at Quantum Mechanics

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 406))

Abstract

I examine the epistemological debate on scientific realism in the context of quantum mechanics (QM), focusing on the empirical underdetermination of different formulations (and interpretations) of QM. This underdetermination is unsurprising in the light of the realism debate, since much of the interpretational, metaphysical work on QM transcends those epistemic commitments of realism that cohere well with the history of science. I sketch a way of demarcating empirically idle metaphysics of QM from the empirically well-confirmed aspects of the theory in a way that withholds realist commitment to what quantum state |Ψ> represents. I argue that such commitment is not required for fulfilling the ultimate realist motivation: accounting for the empirical success of QM in a way that is in tune with a broader understanding of how theoretical science progresses and latches onto reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The realist intuition about quantum mechanics is driven by countless novel predictions and explanatory achievements with respect to various distinct phenomena regarding atomic spectra, the periodic structure of elements, and the band structure of the semiconductors, to name a few.

  2. 2.

    There are some notable exceptions, of course, such as Cordero (2001), Cushing (1994), Barrett (2003), Belousek (2005), and van Fraassen (1991).

  3. 3.

    This lack of consensus is equally true amongst philosophers of physics and physicists themselves. For one snapshot, see Schlosshauer et al. (2013).

  4. 4.

    See, e.g., Esfeld et al. (2017), Esfeld (2014), and Bhogal and Perry (2015), on the role played by Humean metaphysics of laws as a backgrop to Bohmian QM.

  5. 5.

    Note that none of this speaks against the rationality, meaningfulness, or purposefulness of these metaphysical ideas. The point is purely epistemological.

  6. 6.

    Peter Lewis (2016: 182) aptly summarises the state of play at the end of his book length review of quantum metaphysics: “Very little can be concluded unconditionally on the basis of quantum mechanics . . . The best we can say is that not everything in our received classical worldview can be right.”

  7. 7.

    I do not endorse a structuralist reading of the Fresnel-Maxwell theory-shift either (Saatsi 2015a, b).

  8. 8.

    Ehrenfest’s theorem shows how quantum mechanical expectation values of momentum and position operators obey an equation that structurally corresponds to Newton’s equations.

  9. 9.

    French (2014) furthermore takes the continuity and enrichment of the theories’ symmetry features to signal the need to shift from (merely) epistemic structural realism (ESR) to ontological structural realism (OSR):

    But if ESR is going to [incorporate the kinds of structures that matter in QM, such as the structures encoding permutation symmetry], then it will have to take on the metaphysical consequences of this symmetry and those, I argue, lead us to abandon the notion of object, hidden or otherwise. In other words, if structural realism is to broaden its grasp and seize the kinds of structures that modern physics actually presents to us, then it is going to have to shift from ESR to OSR. (p. 19)

    As far as the scientific realism debate in general philosophy of science is concerned, this shift is in tension with the epistemological motivations that led to the idea of structural realism in the first place. The degree of epistemic humility that Worrall recommended by placing the realist’s commitment to mere structure (as opposed to ‘nature’) is quite drastic from the point of view of ‘standard’ realism. If we take this degree of humility to be epistemically well motivated in the first place, and if we think that the distinction between structure and nature can be sensibly drawn, then we should see it as indicating scientists’ unreliability in theorising about the nature of light and the nature of all other things (ultimately) quantum mechanical. But this level of scepticism about scientists’ reliability to theorise about the fundamental nature of the world would also, it seems, speak against the philosopher’s reliability to figure out whether the structural features of our best theories correspond to a structuralist ontology or otherwise (see also Saatsi 2007).

  10. 10.

    Ontic structural realism is a clear exception to this, but for the reasons given (cf. footnote 10) I will here focus on structural realism merely as a form of epistemic humility.

  11. 11.

    Musgrave (1992) argues that a realist can appeal to general metaphysical criteria to eliminate all but one competing interpretation. In the light of the anti-metaphysical trend in the contemporary realism debate such general metaphysical criteria for theory-choice are difficult to motivate as a reliable source of justification, however.

  12. 12.

    This is of course not to say that such work cannot become responsible for such successes, but this potential has no bearing on our current epistemic commitments.

  13. 13.

    As Schaffer (2017, p. 2) explains:

    With causal explanation, there is the structure of cause (such as the rock striking the window), law (laws of nature), and effect (such as the shattering of the window). Metaphysical explanation has a parallel structure, involving ground (the more fundamental source), principle (metaphysical principles of grounding), and grounded (the less fundamental result). One finds a similar structure with logical explanation, involving premise, inference rule, and conclusion.

  14. 14.

    Wallace (2019) argues against philosophers’ commonplace idea that collapse (or ‘projection’) postulate is central to ‘orthodox’ or ‘standard’ QM that physicists employ in practical applications.

References

  • Allori, V. (2013). Primitive ontology and the structure of fundamental physical theories. In D. Z. Albert & A. Ney (Eds.), The wave function: Essays in the metaphysics of quantum mechanics (pp. 58–75). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. A. (2003). Are our best physical theories (probably and/or approximately) true. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1206–1218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. A. (2008). Approximate truth and descriptive nesting. Erkenntnis, 68(2), 213–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belousek, D. W. (2005). Underdetermination, realism, and theory appraisal: An epistemological reflection on quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 35(4), 669–695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H., & Perry, Z. (2015). What the humean should say about entanglement: What the humean should say about entanglement. Noûs, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1990). Science and necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2016). Fiction as a vehicle for truth: Moving beyond the ontic conception. The Monist, 99(3), 260–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H., Elby, A., & Weingard, R. (1996). Cause and effect in the pilotwave interpretation of quantum mechanics. In J. T. Cushing et al. (Eds.), Bohmian mechanics and quantum theory: An appraisal (pp. 309–319). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 29, 391–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2015). Indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordero, A. (2001). Realism and underdetermination: Some clues from the practices-up. Philosophy of Science, 68, S301–S312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing, J. T. (1994). Quantum mechanics: Historical contingency and the Copenhagen hegemony. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egg, M. (2012). Causal warrant for realism about particle physics. Journal of General Philosophy of Science, 43(2), 259–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egg, M. (2016). Expanding our grasp: Causal knowledge and the problem of unconceived alternatives. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 115–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2009). Metaphysics of scientific realism. London: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2014). The primitive ontology of quantum physics: Guidelines for an assessment of the proposals. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 47, 99–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Lam, V., & Hubert, M. (2017). The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68, 133–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Saatsi, J. (2018). Symmetries and explanatory dependencies in physics. In A. Reutlinger & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Explanation beyond causation: Philosophical perspectives on non-causal explanations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Votsis, I. (2011). Everything you always wanted to know about structural realism but were afraid to ask. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 1(2), 227–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1982). Experimentation and scientific realism. Philosophical Topics, 13, 71–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2015). How quantum theory helps us explain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, 1–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansson, L., & Saatsi, J. (2018). Explanatory abstractions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. Advance Access. axy026.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Everything must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landsman, N. P. (2007). Between classical and quantum. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: Philosophy of physics (pp. 417–554). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2016). Quantum ontology: A guide to the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. W. (2007). Completeness, supervenience and ontology. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical, 40(12), 3151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2010). Can the world be only wavefunction? In S. Saunders, J. Barrett, A. Kent, & D. Wallace (Eds.), Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, & reality (pp. 121–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2007). Spin: All is not what it seems. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38(3), 529–557.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1992). Realism about what. Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 691–697.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1996). Realism, truth and objectivity. In R. Cohen, R. Hilpinen, & Q. Renzong (Eds.), Realism and anti-realism in the philosophy of science (pp. 19–44). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A., & Albert, D. Z. (2013). The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norsen, T. (2014). The pilot-wave perspective on spin. American Journal of Physics, 82, 337–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical papers: Volume 2, mind, language and reality (Vol. Volume 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosaler, J. (2016). Interpretation neutrality in the classical domain of quantum theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 53, 54–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2007). Living in harmony: Nominalism and the explanationist argument for realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(1), 19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2015a). Historical inductions, old and new. Synthese. First Online: doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0855-5.

  • Saatsi, J. (2015b). Replacing recipe realism. Synthese, 194(9), 3233–3244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2016). What is theoretical progress of science. Synthese, First Online.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2017a). Dynamical systems theory and explanatory indispensability. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 892–904.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2017b). Explanation and explanationism in science and metaphysics. In M. Slater & Z. Yudell (Eds.), Metaphysics and the philosophy of science: New essays (pp. 162–191). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., & Wallace, D. (Eds.). (2010). Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, & reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2017). The ground between the gaps. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17(11), 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M. (2007). Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M., Kofler, J., & Zeilinger, A. (2013). A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(3), 222–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2015). “Atoms exist” is probably true, and other facts that should not comfort scientific realists. Journal of Philosophy, 112(8), 397–416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timothy, W. (2016). Modal science. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(4–5), 453–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidman, L. (2014). Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1991). Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist View. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2012a). Decoherence and its role in the modern measurement problem. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 370(1975), 4576–4593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2012b). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory according to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2019). What is orthodox quantum mechanics? This volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003a). Experimentation, causal inference, and instrumental realism. In H. Radder (Ed.), The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation (pp. 87–118). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003b). Making things happen: A causal theory of explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Support from Arts and Humanities Research Council (as part of Scientific Realism and the Quantum project) is gratefully acknowledged. I received helpful feedback on presentations in Leeds, San Sebastian, NYU Abu Dhabi. Special thanks to Fabio Ceravolo, Kevin Coffey, Steven French, Simon Newey, Kohei Morita for helpful discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juha Saatsi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Saatsi, J. (2019). Scientific Realism Meets Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. In: Cordero, A. (eds) Philosophers Look at Quantum Mechanics. Synthese Library, vol 406. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15659-6_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics