Skip to main content

Do We Get to Know the Unknown?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ignorant Cognition

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 46))

  • 354 Accesses

Abstract

Ignorance: a word is still sufficient to describe one of the most troublesome problems of contemporary epistemology—without even mentioning its growing popularity outside the academic environment. The recent developments of the schools of thought called “epistemologies of ignorance” and “agnotology” have insisted on the necessity of a contextualization of ignorance, specifically, on the need to investigate the epistemological backgrounds that generate it and the analysis of information-sharing mechanisms that contribute to spread it in particular environments. In the words of Proctor and Schiebinger (2008, [p. i]) their goal is “to come to grips with how ignorance has been understood, created, and ignored, linking these ideas also to allied creations of secrecy, uncertainty, confusion, silence, absence, and impotence—especially as these pertain to scientific activities”.

We live on a placid island of ignorance

in the midst of black seas of infinity,

and it was not meant that we should voyage far.

Howard Phillips Lovecraft, The Call of Cthulhu, 1926

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Ignorance, in many forms, is a recurring hot topic in today’s news. Indeed, whenever words such as “fake news,” “misinformation,” “uneducated opinions” are mentioned by politicians, journalists, and lawmakers, the multifaceted concept of ignorance is taken into account and put under the spotlight. Moreover, uninformed or uneducated citizens are the unwilling center of many social and political phenomena that had concerned the so-called “occidental liberal democracies” in the last decades (amongst the others: the rise of populist parties, the spread of conspiracy theories, the diffusion of anti-scientific theories movements, etc.; cf. (Inglehart and Norris 2016; Lupia 2016)). In fact, it goes without saying that the more knowledgeable the citizens are, the better the democratic process will work, and the contrary, mutatis mutandis, is also true. So, the crisis that journalism faces worldwide (McChesney 2003; Blumler 2010) (caused, mostly but not only, by the rising importance of unconventional media, above all of social network sites), is double-tied to the changing relationship between powerful forces and voting crowds in the occidental democracies (Levy and Nielsen 2010). Notwithstanding the importance of this subject, to avoid straying from the path of a theoretical investigation, in this book I will not directly deal with the increasing relevance of the topic of “ignorance” outside the academic environments. I will, though, examine some aspects of the phenomenon of “fake news” in the last two chapters of the book, in which I discuss the impact that ignorance has on the social cognition of the agent, especially in particular information-based contexts.

  2. 2.

    The so-called “Epistemologies of Ignorance” and “Agnotology” are schools of thoughts initiated in the last few decades by authors in different disciplines (mainly sociology, social philosophy, psychology, and anthropology) who aimed at investigating the impact of ignorance in current and past societies (Proctor and Schiebinger 2008; Sullivan and Tuana 2007; Davies and McGoey 2012; Townley 2011).

  3. 3.

    The only academic works that examine ignorance without an explicit reference to its moral implications are the epistemological ones that aim at finding the definition for it between an array of possibilities—in particular (Peels 2010, 2011, 2017; Le Morvan 2010, 2011). Nonetheless, even if the authors of these accounts do not explicitly consider the moral implications of ignorance in their main argument, the examples that they take into consideration are almost always morally loaded—e.g. (Peels 2011, pp. 350–351; Le Morvan 2010, p. 36).

  4. 4.

    The eco-cognitive perspective has been introduced by Magnani (2009) and will be further discussed in Part 1, Chap. 2.

  5. 5.

    In this work the term “fugitive” or “fugitivity” when connected to the concept of ignorance refers to the apparent inability of the cognitive agent to grasp the existence or depth of her own ignorance. The fugitive nature of ignorance is mainly connected to the “Ignorance’s Concealment-Detection Problem,” which I illustrate in the second chapter. In few words, it states: “A trouser-wearing theory of ignorance would indeed have something helpful to say, among other things, about how ignorance is both inapparent enough to escape personal detection and yet recognizable enough from an external point of view to permit subsequent correction, and about the factors implicated in this transition from personal concealment to external detection.”

  6. 6.

    A barely comprehensive list of authors and currents which should be referred to when speaking of the transversal interest of philosophers for ignorance are, of course, Socrates and Plato (in particular The Republic—cf. (Adam 1963), Protagoras—cf. (Taylor 2009), Sophist—cf. (Bernadete 1986), Meno—cf. (Scott 2006), Apology—cf. (Burnet 1977)), classical and modern Skeptics, Nicola De Cusa and his treatise De Docta Ignorantia—cf. (Hopkins 1981), the Kantian noumenon or the “thing in itself”, and John Rawls’ “veil of ignorance”.

  7. 7.

    Significantly, one of the excerpts of Proctor’s book reports an internal memo of Brown & Williamson Tobacco Company of 1969 that says “Doubt is our product.” In that volume, Proctor and Schiebinger (2008) denounces the generation of useful ignorance by powerful companies that tried to reach their goals by distributing unvalidated data and hiding relevant information, as an act of both social injustice and a reproachable epistemic behavior.

  8. 8.

    Smithson (1988) mainly distinguishes ignorance in error and irrelevance, to further dividing them, error in distortion (as confusion and inaccuracy) and incompleteness (as uncertaintyvagueness, probability and ambiguity—and absence) and irrelevance in untopicality, taboo, and undecidability.

  9. 9.

    Tuana (2006) distinguishes ignorance in Knowing that we do not, but not caring to know, We do not even know that we do not know, They do not want us to know, Willful ignorance, Ignorance produced by the construction of epistemically disadvantaged identities, and Loving Ignorance.

  10. 10.

    Haas and Vogt (2015) distinguish four main forms of ignorance: Preferred Ignorance, Investigative Ignorance, Presumed Knowledge, and Complete Ignorance.

  11. 11.

    In this context I prefer to avoid further commenting Peels/Le Morvan’s debate for the little importance that the distinction they discuss makes in the investigation of the cognitive traits of ignorance, or how ignorance represents a pregnant cognitive state for the human agent.

  12. 12.

    Specifically, the central argumentation of Stoljar (2006) volume Ignorance and Imagination: The Epistemic Origin of the Problem of Consciousness regards how our ignorance concerning “non-conscious facts” increases scholars’ puzzlement about consciousness; Gross (2010) presents case studies of ecological design where the inclusion of surprise and the relative conscious acknowledgement of ignorance benefit the design and negotiation processes; at last, Firestein (2012) sees ignorance as the main fuel of scientific progress. The last book basically argues that scientists constantly aim at diminishing humanity’s ignorance but, at the same time, by answering some important questions, they uncover other problems and issues, which naturally emerge from the newly achieved knowledge and doubts regarding it.

  13. 13.

    Throughout the book I use the gendered pronouns “she” and “her” when referring to the real agent and her features. With this choice I do not mean to refer just to the female population of human agents, but I use female pronouns as an alternative to the longer, even if more accurate, ones, namely “he or she” and “his or her.”

References

  • Adam, J.: The Republic of Plato, vol. 2, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1963). intro. D. A. Rees

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernadete, S.: Plato’s Sophist. Chicago University Press, Chicago (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumler, J.G.: Foreword: the two-legged crisis of journalism. J. Stud. 11(4), 439–441 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L., Cox, R.: Faultless ignorance: strengths and limitations of epistemic definitions of confabulation. Conscious. Cogn. 18(4), 952–965 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnet, J.: Euthyphro; Apology of Socrates; Crito. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, W., McGoey, L.: Rationalities of ignorance: on financial crisis and the ambivalence of neo-liberal epistemology. Econ. Soc. 41(1), 64–83 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Firestein, S.: Ignorance. How It Drives Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, M.: Ignorance and Surprise. Science, Society, and Ecological Design. The MIT Press, Cambridge Massachusetts (2010)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haas, J., Vogt, K.M.: Ignorance and investigation. In: Gross, M., McGoey, L. (eds.) Routledge International Handbook of Ignorance Studies, pp. 17–24. Routledge, Abingdon (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D.: Situated knowledges: the science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Fem. Stud. 14(3), 575–599 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogrefe, G.-J., Wimmer, H., Perner, J.: Ignorance versus false belief: A developmental lag in attribution of epistemic states. Child Dev. 57(3), 567–582 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, J.E.: Nicolas of Cusa on Learned Ignorance: A Translation and an Appraisal of De docta ignorantia. The Arthur J. Banning Press, Cambridge (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Inglehart, R.F., Norris, P.: Trump, brexit, and the rise of populism: Economic have-nots and cultural backlash. In: Rage against the Machine: Populist Politics in the U.S., Europe and Latin America, pp. 1–52. American Political Science Association, Philadelphia (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W.: The Principles of Psychology, vol. 1. Holt, New York (1890)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J.: Should some knowledge be forbidden? the case of cognitive differences research. Philos. Sci. 83(5), 779–790 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P.: Knowledge, ignorance and true belief. Theoria 77(1), 32–41 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P.: On ignorance: a reply to Peels. Philosphia 39(2), 335–344 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D.A.L., Nielsen, R.K.: The Changing Business of Journalism and Its Implications for Democracy. Reuters Institute for the Study of Journalism, Oxford (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lupia, A.: Uninformed Why People Seem to Know So Little about Politics and What We Can Do about It. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, K.: What is the role of the self in self-deception? Philos. Stud. 173(2), 505–523 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L.: Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Springer, Heidelberg (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • McChesney, R.W.: The problem of journalism: a political economic contribution to an explanation of the crisis in contemporary us journalism. J. Stud. 4(3), 299–329 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R.: What is ignorance? Philosophia 38(1), 57–67 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R.: Ignorance is lack of true belief: a rejoinder to LeMorvan. Philosphia 39(2), 345–355 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R.: The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, M.F.: Tensions in agnotology: normativity in the studies of commercially driven ignorance. Soc. Stud. Sci. 45(2), 345–355 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, R.N., Schiebinger, L.: Agnotology. The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance. Stanford University Press, Stanford (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N.: Ignorance On the Wider Implications of Deficient Knowledge. Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh (2009)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D.E.: Plato’s Meno. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithson, M.: Ignorance and Uncertainty. Emerging Paradigms. Springer, New York (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D.: Ignorance and Imagination: The Epistemic Origin of the Problem of Consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, S., Tuana, N.: Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. SUNY Press, New York (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C.C.W.: Plato’s Protagoras. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Townley, C.: A Defense of Ignorance: Its Value for Knowers and Roles in Feminist and Social Epistemologies. Lexington Books, UK (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, N.: The speculum of ignorance: the women’s health movement and epistemologies of ignorance. Hypatia 21(3), 1–19 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J.: Epistemic bubbles. In: Artemov, S., Barringer, H., Garcez, A., Lamb, L., Woods, J. (eds.) We Will Show Them: Essay in Honour of Dov Gabbay (Volume II), pp. 731–774. College Pubblications, London (2005)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Selene Arfini .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Arfini, S. (2019). Do We Get to Know the Unknown?. In: Ignorant Cognition. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14362-6_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics