Skip to main content

Philosophical Considerations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Praxis of Indirect Reports

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 21))

  • 156 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter aims at discussing the logic of indirect reporting, focusing on Frege’s general semantic theory and Davidson’s Paratactic Theory. Moreover, this chapter talks about Mikhail Bakhtin’s idea of ‘voice’ where indirect reports are considered as hybrid constructions. The epistemology of indirect reports reveals that there is always a conflict in the knowledge/belief dimension. Indirect reports embrace both knowledge and belief whereby the reporter can present his/her intuition during the report. On this account, when the reporting speaker trespasses on his/her knowledge base and resorts to his/her belief system (subjectivity is observed), a knowledge/belief conflict occurs. In this chapter, the process underlying indirect reports and the ‘photosynthetic model’ are elaborated. Seeing indirect reports as a process rather than an end product put emphasis on the refinery and coping processes where the reporter can change the illocutionary force of the utterance to create a specific implicature. Based on the ‘photosynthetic model’, it is argued that the sociocognitive features underlying the report can alter the force of the utterances, where indirect reports are influenced by different sociocognitive trajectories that make it very difficult to definitely predict what would be the end product and the consequence of indirect reporting. Finally, evidentiality, ‘de re/de dicto’ distinction, and ‘de se’ beliefs are dealt with. This chapter concludes that the practice of indirect reporting is a complicated process where the end product and the consequences are not completely predictable. Therefore, the practice of indirect reporting is highly under the influence of the peculiarities of the context (either social or cognitive, or both).

Ordinary language is a part of the human organism and no less complicated than it is. It is humanly impossible to get the logic of language out of it directly. Language disguises thought. And in just such a way that it is impossible to draw any conclusions from the external form of the costume, the disguise, about the form of the disguised thought; because the costume’s external form is made for purposes quite distinct from that of making known the form of the body. The implicit adjustments for understanding ordinary language are immensely complicated.

(Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus, cited in Von Kutschera, 2012, p. 217)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In line with Wittgenstein (1997, Section 23), “language game” is meant to bring into prominence the fact that the speaking of language is part of an activity, or a form of life.

  2. 2.

    Clift and Holt (2007) acknowledge the importance of philosophy in indirect reporting, referring to Mikhail Bakhtin’s notion of ‘polyphony’ as an instantiation of the idea of indirect reporting.

  3. 3.

    Jakobson’s (1971) concept of ‘speech within speech’ also refers to the combination of voices.

  4. 4.

    Bakhtin argues that “a hybrid construction is an utterance that belongs, by its grammatical (syntactic) and compositional markers, to a single speaker, but that actually contains mixed within it two utterances, two speech manners, two styles, two ‘languages’, two semantic and axiological belief systems” (1981, p. 304).

  5. 5.

    In line with Seymour (2016, p. 373), “the reporter chooses to represent the saying in the subjective perspective of the agent or from his own objective perspective.”

  6. 6.

    In this regard, Austin (1962) distinguishes between locutionary and illocutionary acts. In ‘John said: p’, John performs the action (locutionary act) but in ‘John said that p’, John is being described as uttering something (illocutionary act). In this case, as reported by Davis (2016, p. 308), “[i]llocutionary saying is much like asserting, but asserting is stronger.”

  7. 7.

    Considering indirect reports as speech acts, the reporter not only conveys someone else’s utterances but also ‘promises’ that the report is genuine and faithful.

  8. 8.

    One should bear in mind that by ‘relevant’, I do not mean ‘effusiveness’. I simply want to show that the information can be negative or positive. However, this positivity or negativity has been the most relevant information regarding a sociocognitive filter.

  9. 9.

    As reported by Nicholson (2016, p. 112), “[t]he philosophical perspective associated with learning practical knowledge and skills is known as Pragmatism.” The author continues that “Pragmatism comes from the Greek word pragma, meaning ‘action.’ Pragmatic is also defined as ‘practical.’ Three American philosophers (Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey) conclude that education should focus on learning how to solve practical problems.”

  10. 10.

    Not all species produce the same product in the process of photosynthesis. There are many varieties of anoxygenic photosynthesis observed among certain types of bacteria. These bacteria consume carbon dioxide but do not release oxygen.

  11. 11.

    ZPD can be equalled with scaffolding, arguing that individuals can reach their true potential by the aid of the peers.

  12. 12.

    Ifantidou (2001, p. 149) argues that these two are the same by stating that “the parentheticals we have been considering above, e.g. I think, we all agree, Bill says, have the same function as hearsay adverbials: they mark the proposition that falls within their scope as being interpretively rather than descriptively used.” The author further adds that “parentheticals such as Bill says, the newspaper reported yesterday, which we might call ‘hearsay parentheticals’, are exactly like hearsay adverbials in that they specifically indicate that the views being interpreted are not the speaker’s own” (Ifantidou, 2001, p. 149). Therefore, according to Ifantidou, the two sentences ‘John is, allegedly, a spy’ and ‘John is, you say, a spy’ are considered parallel to each other.

  13. 13.

    The ‘out-of-court statement’ or ‘hearsay’ is not unlike what Capone (2016) argues as ‘samesaying’. Donald Davidson has been a strong influence on Capone’s in the development of the concept of samesaying (refer to Davidson [1968] for further study). The term ‘hearsay’ is at the heart of ‘samesaying’ since the latter refers to the fact that “the report and the speech to be reported have some broad content in common” (Capone, 2016, p. 24). Thus, in order to perform a ‘hearsay’ function, one of the samesayers (the reporting speaker) should use the words of someone else (the original speaker). In order to fully grasp the practice of ‘samesaying’, one should understand the ‘hearsay’ function.

  14. 14.

    As reported by Ifantidou (2001, p. 201), the use of parentheticals “indicates that the views being interpreted are the speaker’s own.”

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1979 [1961]). Philosophical papers. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. (1973). Problems of Dostoevsky’s poetics (R.W. Rotsel, Trans.) Ann Arbor, MI: Ardis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. (1981). The dialogic imagination. In M. Holquist (C. Emerson, & M. Holquist, Trans.). Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, C. (2011). Contextualism. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 53–70). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Björklund, M. (2011). Mikhail Bakhtin. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 38–52). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, D. (1994). Evidence and modality. In R. Asher & J. Simpson (Eds.), The encyclopedia of language and linguistics (pp. 1183–1186). Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, L. (2013). The communicative mind: A linguistic exploration of conceptual integration and meaning construction. Newcastle, UK: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). The social practice of indirect reports. Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2016). The pragmatics of indirect reports: Socio-philosophical considerations. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2018). On the social praxis of indirect reporting. In A. Capone, M. Garcia-Carpintero, & A. Falzone (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics in the world languages (pp. 3–20). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, A., & Lepore, E. (2005). Insensitive semantics: A defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1991). Implicature, explicature and truth-theoretic semantics. In S. Davis (Ed.), Pragmatics: A reader (pp. 33–51). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chafe, W. L., & Nichols, J. (1986). Evidentiality in English conversation and academic writing. In W. L. Chafe & J. Nichols (Eds.), Evidentiality: The linguistic coding of epistemology (pp. 261–272). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, D. (2007). The basics: Semiotics. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1976). Knowledge and belief: ‘De dicto’ and ‘de re’. Philosophical Studies, 29(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clift, R., & Holt, E. (2007). Introduction. In E. Holt & R. Clift (Eds.), Reporting talk: Reported speech in interaction (pp. 1–15). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulmas, F. (1986). Reported speech: Some general issues. In F. Coulmas (Ed.), Direct and indirect reports: Trends in linguistics, studies, and monographs (pp. 1–28). Berlin, Germany: Mouton De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Couzen, H. D. (1981). The critical circle. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, N. (2006). Designerly ways of knowing. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1968). On saying that. Synthese, 19, 130–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1979). Quotation. Theory and Decision, 11, 27–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. (2016). A theory of saying reports. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics: Interdisciplinary studies (pp. 291–332). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure, F. (1983 [1916]). Course in general linguistics (R. Harris, Trans.). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1908). What does pragmatism mean by practical? The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 5(4), 85–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift. Eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle, Germany: Verlag Louis Nebert. [English translation: Begriffsschrift, A formula Language, Modeled upon that for Arithmetic. In J. van Heijenoort (Ed.), From Frege to Gödel, A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931 (pp. 1–82). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.]

    Google Scholar 

  • Garvey, T. G. (2000). The value of opacity: A Bakhtinian analysis of Habermas’s discourse ethics. Philosophy & Rhetoric, 33(4), 370–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gignac, A. (2016). Enunciation, personification, and intertextuality. In B. J. Oropeza & S. Moyise (Eds.), In exploring intertextuality: Diverse strategies for new testament interpretation of texts (pp. 176–186). Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1978). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics (Vol. 9, pp. 113–128). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2014). Do not block the way of inquiry. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy, 50(3), 319–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harnish, R. M. (2007). Frege on direct quotation. Essays in Philosophy, 8(1), 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (2003). Remembering, imagining, and the first person. Manuscript. California: University of Southern California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2012). The pragmatic maxim: Essays on Peirce and pragmatism. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2016). Pragmatism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/pragmatism/.

  • Ifantidou, E. (2001). Evidentials and relevance. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson, R. (1971). Shifters, verbal categories and the Russian verb. In R. Jakobson (Ed.), Selected writings (Vol. II: Word and language, pp. 130–147). The Hague, The Netherlands: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1922[1907]). Pragmatism: A new name for some old ways of thinking. Cambridge: MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasser, J. (2011). How settled are settled beliefs in “the fixation of belief”? Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy, 47(2), 226–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, G. J., McDonald, S., & Wickman, P. O. (2012). Science learning and epistemology. In B. Fraser, K. Tobin, & C. McRobbie (Eds.), Second international handbook of science education (Vol. 24, pp. 281–291). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kiefer, F. (2016). Indirect and direct reports in Hungarian. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics: Interdisciplinary studies (pp. 77–92). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Krashen, S. (1981). Second language acquisition and second language learning. Oxford, UK: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, J. (1980). Desire in language: A semiotic approach to literature and art. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (2012). Pragmatism and inquiry. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (2016). How infallible but corrigible full belief is possible. In H. Arló-Costa, V. F. Hendricks, & J. van Benthem (Eds.), Readings in formal epistemology: Sourcebook (pp. 247–268). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liszka, J. J. (1996). A general introduction to the semeiotic of Charles S. Peirce. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (Ed.). (2003). Donald Davidson. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, E. (2009). Presupposing acquaintance: A unified semantics for de dicto, de re and de se belief reports. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32(5), 429–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mithun, M. (1986). Evidential diachrony in northern Iroquoian. In W. Chafe & J. Nichols (Eds.), Evidentiality: The linguistic coding of epistemology (pp. 89–112). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, C. W. (1971). Writings on the general theory of signs. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. W. (2016). Philosophy of education in action: An inquiry-based approach. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nikulin, D. V. (2006). On dialogue. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, F. (1986). Mood and modality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1982). What do quotation marks name? Frege’s theories of quotation and that-clauses. Philosophical Studies, 42, 315–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1973). The syntax and semantics of quotation. In S. Anderson & P. Kiparsky (Eds.), A festschrift for Morris Halle (pp. 410–418). New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1897). Fallibilism, continuity, and evolution. CP, 1, 141–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931[1958]). Collected writings (8 vols). (C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, & A. W. Burks, Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Récanati, F. (2001). What is said. Synthese, 128, 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rojo, L. M., & Pujol, A. G. (2011). Michel Foucault. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 85–103). Amsterdam, The Netherlands: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sambre, P. (2013). Fleshing out embodied language and intersubjectivity: An exploration of Merleau-Ponty’s legacy to cognitive linguistics. Cognitive Semiotics, 4(1), 189–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sbisà, M. (2011). John L. Austin. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 26–37). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schirato, T. (2011). Deconstruction. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 71–78). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, W. (2010). Narratology: An introduction. Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, M. (1994). Indirect discourse and quotation. Philosophical Studies, 74, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, M. (2016). Indirect discourse and quotation. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. L. Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics (pp. 355–376). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, M. (2006). Empiricism. In F. English (Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational leadership and administration (pp. 338–339). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stojnic, U., & Lepore, E. (2018). Semantics and what is said. In A. Capone, M. Garcia-Carpintero, & A. Falzone (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics in the world languages (pp. 21–38). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, K. A. (2002). De re and de dicto: Against the conventional wisdom. Noûs, 36, 225–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Craen, P. (2011). Hermeneutics. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman, & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (Vol. 10, pp. 125–130). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Von Kutschera, F. (2012). Philosophy of language (Vol. 71). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, G., & Birner, B. (1993). The semantics and pragmatics of and everything. Journal of Pragmatics, 19, 205–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weigand, E. (2010). Dialogue: The mixed game. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, H. (2016). Speaking for another. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics: Interdisciplinary studies (pp. 405–434). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1997). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky, A. M. (1971). In a manner of speaking. Linguistic Inquiry, 2(2), 223–233.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Morady Moghaddam, M. (2019). Philosophical Considerations. In: The Praxis of Indirect Reports. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14269-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14269-8_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-14268-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-14269-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics