Skip to main content

The Real Problem of Consciousness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 561 Accesses

Abstract

Carruthers offers a new description of the problem of consciousness. Whilst the Real Problem of consciousness is the problem of explaining consciousness, it also includes worries about measuring consciousness. How do we know when we have measured consciousness? This problem is distinguished from traditional worries about the nature of consciousness stemming from Descartes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On reading this claim that the mind is a representational/computational device some readers may expect extensive discussion of a currently fashionable position known as “Bayesianism.” Bayesianism offers one possible formalism to Helmholtz’s early description of perception as being the output of unconscious inference. Roughly the formalism states that the posterior probability of a percept is proportional to the prior probability of the percept (the probability that the world is in the perceived state before being perceived) times the likelihood of the percept (the probability that the state of the world would cause the current sensory input). Advocates of this position hold that what we perceive is the state with the highest posterior probability. However, this approach fails to offer a testable alternative to the account considered here.

    If Bayesianism is taken as more than a mere description of input/output relations, i.e., as a claim about what computations are actually performed by the mind, we see it immediately runs afoul of the frame problem—i.e. the problem of determining what needs to be represented to perform a particular cognitive task and keeping those representations to a manageable load for a finite computational device (e.g. Dennett, 1987). Taken literally, any possible state of the world with a non-zero probability of causing a particular sensory input would have to be computed and almost all rejected before anything could be perceived.

    Worse, however, is the reliance on the “priors”, i.e. the probability that the world is in a particular state prior to being perceived. Such priors are purportedly “learned” through experiencing the world. Again, the frame problem is a problem here, there is an infinite number of states the world could be in with non-zero probabilities. Still, even if advocates could arbitrarily modify the formalism such that only states with a probability above some cut of score are actually represented, the value of the priors is too under-constrained to do any explanatory work. Whatever a subject perceives we can adjust the value of the prior in the formalism such that what they actually perceive turns out to be the state with the highest posterior probability. Without the ability to determine what priors are independently of the percept we are trying to explain, Bayesianism remains untestable.

  2. 2.

    Many thanks go to Gerard O’Brien for this very helpful phrasing.

  3. 3.

    I am using here the 1996 version of Cottingham’s translation from Latin, which also includes Cottingham’s own scholarship. I will occasionally add in parentheses some of Cottingham’s translation from the French version as this will aid our understanding.

  4. 4.

    As a rough guide 1 degree is approximately the angle subtended by a point either side of your thumb nail held at arm’s length.

  5. 5.

    Now of course in the normal case our eyes saccade constantly allowing us to build a much more detailed visual representation than is possible from staring at a fixation point. This makes the area of clear vision significantly larger than the 2–3 degrees observable in a fixation task. This doesn’t affect the central Dennettian claim that periphery is not clear and coloured in the way that we would typically assume. Nor do we typically reflect on how much moving our eyes is necessary for seeing the way we do.

References

  • Baddeley, A. (1992). Working memory. Science, 255(5044), 5556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, B., Yates, J., & Coleman, R. (1980). Perception of images moving at saccadic velocities during saccades and during fixation. Experimental Brain Research, 40(1), 71–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplovitz, G. P., Fendrich, R., & Hughes, H. C. (2008). Failures to see: Attentive blank stares revealed by change blindness. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(3), 877–886. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2007.08.006.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, G., & Schier, E. (2017). Why are we still being hornswoggled? Dissolving the hard problem of consciousness. Topoi, 36(1), 67–79. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9266-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2002). Consciousness and its place in nature. In D. J Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classic and contemporary readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1984). Matter and consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1993). Sensory qualities. Oxford: Clarendon Library of Logic and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). Cognitive wheels: The frame problem of A.I. In Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.), The robot’s dilemma. Albex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R., & Cottingham, J. (1996). René descartes: Meditations on first philosophy: With selections from the objections and replies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R., & Princess Elisabeth. (1643, 1644/2009). Correspondence between Descartes and Princess Elisabeth (J. Bennett, Trans.). EarlyModernTexts.com. Retrieved from http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/pdfs/descartes1643.pdf.

  • Flanagan, O. J. (1984). The science of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press and Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. J. (1992). Consciousness reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32I, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(4), 354–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2011). Perplexities of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, D. J., & Levin, D. T. (1997). Change blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1(7), 261–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Glenn Carruthers .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Carruthers, G. (2019). The Real Problem of Consciousness. In: The Feeling of Embodiment. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14167-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics