Skip to main content

Duality Theory: Hybrids

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Heyting Algebras

Part of the book series: Trends in Logic ((TREN,volume 50))

Abstract

This chapter covers the duality theory for closure algebras and Heyting algebras. The notion of a hybrid of topology and order is introduced, and the fundamental properties of hybrids are studied. It is proved that the category of hybrids and hybrid maps is dually equivalent to the category of closure algebras and closure algebra homomorphisms, while the category of strict hybrids and hybrid maps is dually equivalent to the category of Heyting algebras and Heyting homomorphisms. The notion of a Grzegorczyk algebra is introduced, and several characterizations of these algebras are given using the duality theory. From these characterizations it follows that the category of skeletal closure algebras is a subcategory of the category of Grzegorczyk algebras. Finally, it is proved that the variety of Grzegorczyk algebras is generated by its finite members, and some consequences of this result are derived.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Editorial note: For the definition of the exponential (Vietoris) topology, see Definition 1.3.4.

  2. 2.

    Editorial note: Following the policy for omission of parentheses explained in the Preface, in contexts involving \({\mathbf {\mathsf{{C}}}}\), parentheses will sometimes be omitted after \(R\) and \(R^{-1}\) for readability.

  3. 3.

    Editorial note: The morphisms of the category \(\mathsf {HYB}\) will be introduced in Definition 3.3.1.

  4. 4.

    Editorial note: The existence of such a maximal chain follows from Proposition 1.4.10.

  5. 5.

    Editorial note: See, e.g., Example D on p. 26 of [18].

  6. 6.

    Editorial note: Since (X, R) is a chain, the family \(\{R(x) : x\in \mathrm {Gap}(X,R)\}\) is a ring of sets.

  7. 7.

    Editorial note: See, e.g., Corollary 3.1.14 of  R. Engelking, General Topology, 2nd ed. (Heldermann-Verlag), 1989.

  8. 8.

    Editorial note: This is a nonstandard use of the term ‘Dedekind complete’, which usually means that each nonempty subset bounded above has a supremum (resp. bounded below has an infimum).

  9. 9.

    Editorial note: A subset \(Z\) of \(X\) is upward (resp. downard) directed if for all \(x,y\in Z\), there is \(z\in Z\) such that \(xRz\) and \(yRz\) (resp. \(zRx\) and \(zRy\)).

  10. 10.

    Editorial note: See Proposition 5.9 on p. 33 of [3].

  11. 11.

    Editorial note: This result is now known as Esakia’s lemma ; see, e.g., p. 350 of A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic (Clarendon Press), 1997. Note that the lemma does not require that \(R\) be reflexive or transitive.

  12. 12.

    Editorial note: It is straightforward to see that \((X_i,\Omega _i,R_i)^*=(B(X_i),R_i^{-1})\) is indeed a closure algebra.

  13. 13.

    Editorial note: Indeed, it is easy to see that f being surjective implies that \(f^{-1}\) is injective. For the converse, given \(y\in Y\), we have that \(\{y\}\) is the intersection of the downward directed family of clopens \(A_i\) containing y. Since each \(A_i\) is nonempty, and \(f^{-1}\) is injective, \(f^{-1}(A_i)\) is nonempty. Thus, by compactness, the intersection of the \(f^{-1}(A_i)\) is nonempty, so \(f^{-1}(\{y\})\) is nonempty. This shows that f is surjective.

    To see that \(f^{-1}\) being surjective implies that f is injective, use the fact that distinct points are distinguished by clopens. For the converse, suppose A is a clopen subset of X. Then f(A) is closed in Y, so f(A) is the intersection of clopens \(B_i\) such that \(f(A)\subseteq B_i\). Thus, \(f^{-1}(f(A))=\bigcap \{f^{-1}(B_i)\mid i\in I\}\), and since f is injective, \(A=f^{-1}(f(A))\), so \(A=\bigcap \{f^{-1}(B_i)\mid i\in I\}\). Using compactness, it follows that there is one clopen B such that \(A=f^{-1}(B)\).

    Note that Lemmas 3.3.13(3) and 3.3.14(3) are inter-derivable using the Duality Theorem (the proof of which does not require these lemmas).

  14. 14.

    Editorial note: That \((\cdot )_*\) is a well-defined contravariant functor follows from Lemmas 3.3.11 and 3.3.13 (and the easily verifiable facts that it preserves identity and composition), and that \((\cdot )^*\) is a well-defined contravariant functor follows from Lemma 3.3.14 (and the same easily verifiable facts). That \((\cdot )_*\) satisfies part (a) of the definition of coequivalence (Definition (2)) follows from Lemma 3.3.15. That \((\cdot )_*\) satisfies part (b) is a consequence of Lemmas 3.3.13 and 3.3.14

  15. 15.

    Editorial note: It is easy to see that \((X_0,\Omega _0)\) is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff space.

  16. 16.

    Editorial note: Zorn’s lemma states that a partially ordered set in which every chain has an upper bound has a maximal element (see, e.g., [11]).

  17. 17.

    Editorial note: The proof is similar to that of the analogous part of Lemma 3.3.13(3).

  18. 18.

    Editorial note: Since \((X/E, \Omega _E)\) is compact and distinct points are separated by clopens, it follows that \((X/E, \Omega _E)\) is zero-dimensional. See, e.g., p. 69 of P. Johnstone, Stone Spaces (Cambridge University Press), 1982.

  19. 19.

    Editorial note: The Gödel translation  T is defined as follows: if p is a propositional variable, let \(T(p)=\Box p\), and for arbitrary formulae p, q, let \(T(p\vee q)=T(p)\vee T(q)\), \(T(p\wedge q)=T(p)\wedge T(q)\), \(T(p\rightarrow q)=\Box (T(p)\rightarrow T(q))\), and \(T(\lnot p)=\Box \lnot T(p)\).

  20. 20.

    Editorial note: The superintuitionistic fragment of \(\sigma \) is the superintuitionistic logic \({\{p\mid T(p)\in \sigma \}}\).

  21. 21.

    Editorial note: For a proof, see Corollary 9.64 (and Exercise 9.21) in A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic (Clarendon Press), 1997.

  22. 22.

    Editorial note: S5 is obtained by adding to S4 the axiom \(\Diamond p\rightarrow \Box \Diamond p\).

  23. 23.

    Editorial note: This result is now known as the Blok–Esakia Theorem; see p. 325 of A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic (Clarendon Press), 1997.

  24. 24.

    Editorial note: Lemma  3.5.11 is an algebraic formulation of Theorem 3.5.2 provided that the rule (R3) is reformulated in terms of \(\Diamond \).

  25. 25.

    Editorial note: Julia Ilin pointed out a gap in Esakia’s original proof, so we have replaced it by an algebraic version of the proof from pp. 158–9 of G. Boolos, The Logic of Provability (Cambridge University Press), 1993.

  26. 26.

    Editorial note: A logic is finitely approximable  if it is characterized (in the sense of Sect. 2.3.3) by a class of finite algebras.

References

  1. Birkhoff, G. (1967). Lattice theory (Vol. 3), American mathematical society colloquium publications Providence: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Blok, W.J. (1976) Varieties of interior algebras. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cohn, P. M. (1965). Universal algebra. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Esakia, L. L. (1974). Topological Kripke models. Soviet Mathematics Doklady, 15, 147–151.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Esakia, L. L. (1979). On the theory of modal and superintuitionistic systems (Russian). Logical inference (pp. 147–172). Moscow: Nauka.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Esakia, L. L. (1981). Diagonal constructions, Löb’s formula, and Cantor’s scattered spaces (Russian). Studies in logic and semantics (pp. 128–143). Tbilis: Metsniereba.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Esakia, L. L. (1984). On the variety of Grzegorczyk algebras. Selecta Sovietica Mathematica, 3, 343–366.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Grzegorczyk, A. (1967). Some relational systems and the associated topological spaces. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 60, 223–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Halmos, P. R. (1962). Algebraic logic. New York: Chelsea Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jónsson, B., & Tarski, A. (1951). Boolean algebras with operators. I. American Journal of Mathematics, 73, 891–939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Makinson, D. C. (1969). On the number of ultrafilters of an infinite Boolean algebra. Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 15, 121–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Maksimova, L. L. (1979). Interpolation theorems in modal logics and amalgamable varieties of topological Boolean algebras. Algebra and Logic, 18, 348–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Maksimova, L. L., & Rybakov, V. V. (1974). The lattice of normal modal logics. Algebra and Logic, 13, 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Mostowski, A., & Tarski, A. (1939). Boolesche ringe mit geordneter basis. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 32, 69–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Nachbin, L. (1965) Topology and order. Translated from the Portuguese by Lulu Bechtolsheim. Van Nostrand Mathematical Studies (Vol. 4). Princeton: D. Van Nostrand Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Priestley, H. A. (1972). Ordered topological spaces and the representation of distributive lattices. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 3(24), 507–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Segerberg, K. (1971) An essay in classical modal logic. Vols. 1, 2, 3. Filosofiska Studier (Vol. 13). Uppsala: Filosofiska Föreningen och Filosofiska Institutionen vid Uppsala Universitet.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Sikorski, R. (1960). Boolean algebras (Vol. 25). Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete, N. F. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Wolk, E. S. (1968). The topology of a partially well ordered set. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 62, 255–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Esakia, L. (2019). Duality Theory: Hybrids. In: Bezhanishvili, G., Holliday, W. (eds) Heyting Algebras. Trends in Logic, vol 50. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-12096-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics