Skip to main content

The Scientific Implications of Epistemology: Weyl and Husserl

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Weyl and the Problem of Space

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 49))

Abstract

The title of this article refers to the subtitle of the section “Subject and Object” of the major work of Hermann Weyl. We can immediately remark the surprising order of the terms: should we not expect from a man of science that he preferably discuss the epistemological implications of science? Using epistemology as the vector of scientific thought, Weyl examines how, under the pressure of an issue inherent in science, the classical philosophical doctrine of the subjectivity of sensible qualities eventually rooted out any trace of intuition in the now purely symbolic representation of the objective world. The precedence of epistemology over physics could be justified by this conceptual revolution initiated by special relativity: physics is now geometry in action. Through gradual improvement geometrical concepts have become more and more involved in phenomena taking place in physical space-time: geometry is not only ontologically rooted in the real through its ability to produce semantic universals (curvatures, manifolds, groups, connections, etc.), but, besides, it is actively involved in its becoming by the fact that its symmetry principles have a constitutive action. In short, while mathematics is still in Galileo’s physics only a language appropriate to the study of nature, a remarkable ontological extension of the founding project of mathematical physics led to a deep upheaval of its sense: the means of knowledge cannot be separated from the knowledge of the objects themselves.

Translated from French by Pascale Pelletier, revised by the author.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    H.Weyl, Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1949), Section 17. Hereafter referred to as PMNS.

  2. 2.

    H. Weyl, Space-Time-Matter, trans. H. Brose (New York: Dover, 1952), p. 2. Hereafter referred to as STM.

  3. 3.

    The generalization of Weyl’s diagram to scientific knowledge in general is suggested by J.Ortega y Gasset, L’Evolution de la théorie déductive, transl. J.P. Borel (Paris: Gallimard, 1970), p. 26. Between the two regions, there is indeed a correspondence, guaranteed by experiments, but not a similarity.

  4. 4.

    A.S. Eddington, The Nature of the Physical World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1928), pp. 343–344.

  5. 5.

    H. Minkowski, ‘Space and Time’, The Principle of Relativity, transl. W. Perrett and G.B. Jeffery (New York: Dover, 1952), p. 76.

  6. 6.

    E. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, trans. D.Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970), p. 295.

  7. 7.

    H. Weyl, « Über den Symbolismus der Mathematik und mathematischen Physik », Studium Generale, 6 (1953), p. 219–228.

  8. 8.

    See for instance R. Thom, Paraboles et catastrophes, Paris, Flammarion, 1983, p. 35.

  9. 9.

    Crisis, §34, p. 131.

  10. 10.

    Ibid. §44, p. 156.

  11. 11.

    Ibid. §9b, p. 31.

  12. 12.

    Ibid. p. 32.

  13. 13.

    A good example of redundancy is the Euclidean manner to “unfold” non-Euclidean geometry in a gravitational field by renouncing the absolute rigidity of the bodies moving in it.

  14. 14.

    H.Weyl, Das Kontinuum (Leipzig: Veit, 1918), Ch.2 §6.

  15. 15.

    E. Husserl, Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology, Book I, transl. F.Kersten (The Hague: M.Nijhoff, 1982), §82, p. 196.

  16. 16.

    Ibid. §24, p. 44.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Kerszberg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kerszberg, P. (2019). The Scientific Implications of Epistemology: Weyl and Husserl. In: Bernard, J., Lobo, C. (eds) Weyl and the Problem of Space. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 49. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-11527-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics