Skip to main content

Crossing Boundaries: Why Physics Can Help Understand Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mechanistic Explanations in Physics and Beyond

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 11))

Abstract

Socio-economic systems can often successfully be treated as complex systems in the statistical physics sense. This means that the complexity resides in the emerging dynamical behaviour, not in a complicated composition. In order to understand why physics can help to understand socio-economic phenomena with complex behaviour in this sense, I argue that it is necessary to adopt a structural perspective. Accordingly, one has to modify the notion of mechanistic explanations, partly by broadening it. One crucial tool for finding mechanistic explanations in such a structural sense, are minimal models, i.e. models that abstract from micro details in a drastic way. I will show why mechanistic explanations using minimal models for complex dynamical behaviour naturally lead to a structural notion of mechanisms. Among other things I will deal with two diverging views. One of these is that the application of physics-based models to socio-economic phenomena is (mostly) unwarranted to begin with. The other diverging view is that, while the use is in fact warranted, the resulting explanation of socio-economic phenomena is either non-causal or, if causal, not in a mechanistic sense.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a more detailed discussion of this difference, see Kuhlmann (2011).

  2. 2.

    Thebault et al. (2018) make this point only for one specific approach but apparently see it as a more general issue. See Gallegati et al. (2006) for a more general discussion.

  3. 3.

    Mantegna and Stanley (2000) is arguably still the best-known introduction to econophysics.

  4. 4.

    See Beinhocker’s (2007) book The Origin of Wealth: Evolution, Complexity, and the Radical Remaking of Economics for a comprehensive up-to-date survey of the debate, which addresses a wider audience and stresses many aspects that are interesting for my investigation of econophysics. Note that Beinhocker talks about ‘complexity economics’ in contrast to ‘traditional economics’.

  5. 5.

    The classification ‘stable’ means that the sum of two independent identically distributed random variables of the Lévy type results in a distribution with the same shape. See Bouchaud and Potters (2000: sect. 1.5.3) for details. The Gaussian distribution is a more common example of a stable distribution.

  6. 6.

    Also, see Mandelbrot (1963).

  7. 7.

    See Mandelbrot and Hudson (2004) for a very readable introduction to Mandelbrot’s contributions from an ex post perspective.

  8. 8.

    This model itself builds upon the simpler and less detailed stock-market model by Bouchaud and Cont (1998).

  9. 9.

    The model itself was put forward by Ernst Ising (1925). Only in 1944 Lars Onsager famously supplied an exact computation of the thermodynamical properties of the two-dimensional Ising model at the critical point.

  10. 10.

    Among them some take Bouchaud and Cont (1998) as their starting point, such as Johansen et al. (2000). Others, like Bornholdt (2001), build upon Chowdhury and Stauffer (1999) – and thereby ultimately upon Bouchaud and Cont (1998), too.

  11. 11.

    See Hesse (1963) and Bartha (2010) for two extensive philosophical studies on analogies.

  12. 12.

    See Binney et al. (1992) for a detailed exposition and Batterman (2002), Morrison (2014) as well as Jovanovic and Schinckus (2016: 58) for accessible introductions together with philosophical/conceptual discussions.

  13. 13.

    Note that Knuuttila and Loettgers look at socio-economic applications in general and not specifically at econophysics. In fact, they don’t even mention the term ‘econophysics’. However, they study the work of some of the founders of econophysics, such as Stanley and Stauffer, and, in any case, their considerations seem equally relevant for econophysics.

  14. 14.

    JPW are primarily concerned with one particular example, namely the financial market model of Johansen et al. (2000) (henceforth “JLS”). It is similar to the example I introduced above, at least for the purposes of the current discussion. They focus on the question to which extent this model does in fact treat crashes and critical phase transitions as analogous.

  15. 15.

    See Batterman (2002) and Batterman and Rice (2014).

  16. 16.

    See Woodward (2002: sect. 4.3) for a very illuminative discussion.

  17. 17.

    See Weisberg (2013) for a comprehensive discussion of scientific models, Gibbard and Varian (1978) for a classical paper specifically on economic models, and Wimsatt (1987) on the function of “false models,” which is particularly relevant to complex systems.

  18. 18.

    Cartwright’s (1983: ch. 8) so-called ‘simulacrum account of explanation’, which is also non-law-based, is arguably the approach where models and explanations stand in the closest connection with each other.

  19. 19.

    Batterman (2005) has a similar point, when he argues that highly idealized and oversimplified models can sometimes be better for the explanation of the dominant phenomenon, e.g. a phase transition, than a detailed model in terms of micro-constituents.

Literature

  • Bartha, P. 2010. By Parallel Reasoning: The Construction and Evaluation of Analogical Arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. 2002. The Devil in the Details. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Critical phenomena and breaking drops: Infinite idealizations in physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36: 225–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W., and C.C. Rice. 2014. Minimal Model Explanations. Philosophy of Science 81 (3): 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beinhocker, E.D. 2007. The Origin of Wealth: Evolution, Complexity, and the Radical Remaking of Economics. London: Random House Business Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binney, J.J., N.J. Dowrick, A.J. Fisher, and M.E.J. Newman. 1992. The Theory of Critical Phenomena: An Introduction to the Renormalization Group. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bornholdt, S. 2001. Expectation bubbles in a Spin Model of Markets: Intermittency from Frustration Across Scales. International Journal of Modern Physics C 12: 667–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchaud, J.-P., and R. Cont. 1998. A Langevin Approach to Stock Market Fluctuations and Crashes. European Physical Journal B 6: 543–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchaud, J.-P., and M. Potters. 2000. Theory of Financial Risks: From Statistical Physics to Risk Management. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chowdhury, D., and D. Stauffer. 1999. A Generalized Spin Model of Financial Markets. European Physical Journal B 8: 477–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallegati, M., S. Keen, T. Lux, and P. Ormerod. 2006. Worrying Trends in Econophysics. Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and Its Applications 370: 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A., and H.R. Varian. 1978. Economic Models. The Journal of Philosophy 75: 664–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S.S. 1996. Mechanisms and the Nature of Causation. Erkenntnis 44: 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Rethinking Mechanistic Explanation. Philosophy of Science 69: S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 2017. The New Mechanical Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. 1963. Models and Analogies in Science. London: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P.M., and J. Williamson. 2012. What Is a Mechanism? Thinking About Mechanisms Across the Sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2: 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ising, E. 1925. Beiträge zur Theorie des Ferromagnetismus. Zeitschrift für Physik 31: 253–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jhun, J., Palacios, P., and J. Weatherall. 2017. Market Crashes as Critical Phenomena? Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Econophysics. Synthese (online first).

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansen, A., O. Ledoit, and D. Sornette. 2000. Crashes as critical points. International Journal of Theoretical and Applied Finance 3: 219–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jovanovic, F., and C. Schinckus. 2016. Econophysics and Financial Economics: An Emerging Dialogue. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., and A. Loettgers. 2016. Model Templates Within and Between Disciplines: From Magnets to Gases – And Socio-economic Systems. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 6: 377–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhlmann, M. 2011. Mechanisms in Dynamically Complex Systems. In Causality in the Sciences, ed. P. McKay Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson, 880–906. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Explaining Financial Markets in Terms of Complex Systems. Philosophy of Science 81: S1117–S1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C.F. Craver. 2000. Thinking About Mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbrot, B. 1960. The Pareto-Levy Law and the Distribution of Income. International Economic Review 1: 79–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. The Variation of Certain Speculative Prices. Journal of Business 36 (4): 394–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbrot, B., and R.L. Hudson. 2004. The Misbehavior of Markets: A Fractal View of Risk, Ruin and Reward. London: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mantegna, R.N., and H. Eugene Stanley. 2000. An Introduction to Econophysics: Correlations and Complexity in Finance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. 1999. Learning from Models. In Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. M.S. Morgan and M. Morrison, 347–388. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. 1999. Models as autonomous agents. In Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. M.S. Morgan and M. Morrison, 38–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Complex Systems and Renormalization Group Explanations. Philosophy of Science 81: 1144–1156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. E. J. 2005. Power Laws, Pareto Distributions and Zipf’s Law. Contemporary Physics 46: 323–351, citations from third online version: http://aps.arxiv.org/abs/cond-mat/0412004v3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roehner, B.M. 2002. Patterns of Speculation: A Study in Observational Econophysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schinckus, C. 2016. 1996-2016: Two Decades of Econophysics: Between Methodological Diversification and Conceptual Coherence, Special Topics issue ‘Discussion & Debate: Can Economics be a Physical Science?’. The European Physical Journal 225: 3299–3311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thebault, K.P.Y., S. Bradley, and A. Reutlinger. 2018. Modelling inequality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69: 691–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. 2013. Simulation and Similarity: Using Models to Understand the World. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W.C. 1987. False Models as Means to Truer Theories. In Neutral Models as a Biological Strategy, ed. M.H. Nitecki and A. Hoffman, 23–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 2002. Making Things Happen – A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Meinard Kuhlmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kuhlmann, M. (2019). Crossing Boundaries: Why Physics Can Help Understand Economics. In: Falkenburg, B., Schiemann, G. (eds) Mechanistic Explanations in Physics and Beyond. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 11. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10707-9_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics