Skip to main content

The Principles-Theory Variant of Proportionality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Borrowing Justification for Proportionality

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 72))

  • 270 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter tackles issues surrounding the meaning of proportionality. It advances what the principles-theory variant of the test is and how the Supreme Federal Court of Brazil (STF) has made use of this variant propounded by Alexy. Accordingly, Sect.  1 differentiates two types of controversies that have surrounded the concept of proportionality and the studies on its migration. Section 2 shows that from the case law of the Federal Constitutional Court of Germany (BVerfG), Alexy derived a particular conception of proportionality, which he embedded in an encompassing theory that postulates the conceptual necessity of the test and thus makes a strong case for its universality. This variant of proportionality is grounded in three premises: the optimization thesis, the wide-scope conception of rights, and the thesis of argumentative representation. Section 3 details a set of decisions in which the STF or one of its Justices or panels have recourse to the principles-theory variant of proportionality or its sub-tests. Section 4 meets critiques often addressed to the use Brazilian Justices have made of the test: that the STF performs an inaccurate imitation of proportionality analysis, mistakes the concept of proportionality for something else, and resorts to no adjudicative method whatsoever. Finally, I start to affirmatively answer the question of whether there can be a place for the principles-theory variant proportionality in the Brazilian law, regardless of the absence of a corresponding clause in the Federal Constitution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Dworkin (1986), pp. 43–48, distinguishing ‘semantic disagreements’ from ‘genuine disagreements’ in law.

  2. 2.

    See Balmer (2008), p. 784, on the proportionality of crime with punishment. C.f. Schlink (2012), pp. 719–722, suggesting that the separation between proportionality in issues of punishment and proportionality in constitutional adjudication is not so sharp.

  3. 3.

    Law (2004), pp. 693–694.

  4. 4.

    Bomhoff (2010), pp. 110, 138.

  5. 5.

    Ibid., p. 109; Bomhoff (2008a), p. 555.

  6. 6.

    Law (2004), p. 697.

  7. 7.

    Ibid., p. 698.

  8. 8.

    Kumm (2004), p. 579; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 265; Urbina (2012), p. 49; Klatt (2012), p. 8; Klatt and Meister (2012a), p. 7; Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 67.

  9. 9.

    Kumm (2012), p. 13.

  10. 10.

    See Möller (2014), p. 32; Barak (2012a, b), p. 131; Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 67.

  11. 11.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 72.

  12. 12.

    Cohn (2010), p. 607; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), p. 371.

  13. 13.

    Bomhoff (2013), pp. 190–191.

  14. 14.

    Kumm (2004), p. 593.

  15. 15.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), p. 371.

  16. 16.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 90.

  17. 17.

    Law (2004), p. 694; Kumm (2004), p. 576.

  18. 18.

    Barak (2012a, b), p. 131.

  19. 19.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 75.

  20. 20.

    Ibid., pp. 75–76.

  21. 21.

    Alexy (1992), p. 149.

  22. 22.

    Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 67.

  23. 23.

    See Porat (2014), p. 401 ff., for an overview of the debates concerning balancing in U.S. constitutional law.

  24. 24.

    Reznik (2000), pp. 242–282.

  25. 25.

    Schauer (2010), pp. 36–37.

  26. 26.

    See Möller (2012a), pp. 17–20, on the particularities of the U.S. model of rights; and Schauer (2010), p. 37, saying that ‘the typical proportionality inquiry is structured …, and it is this structure of burdens and presumptions that explains why it is a mistake to treat a proportionality inquiry as equivalent to an open-ended decision on the balance of all reasons and all facts’.

  27. 27.

    Frantz (1961), p. 1424; Aleinikoff (1987), p. 943; Huscroft et al. (2014), p. 1.

  28. 28.

    Frantz (1961), p. 1424.

  29. 29.

    Bomhoff (2008b), p. 122.

  30. 30.

    Möller (2012a), pp. 17–18.

  31. 31.

    Bomhoff (2013), pp. 190–234. Not all comparatists notice this difference, which has led to some erroneous conclusions. To illustrate that, we can mention Aleinikoff (1987), who is commonly deemed as referring to balancing in the German sense (the final step of the proportionality test), when in fact he deals with the U.S. Supreme Court’s approach only.

  32. 32.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), p. 399.

  33. 33.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 265.

  34. 34.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), p. 399.

  35. 35.

    Bomhoff (2008b), p. 122.

  36. 36.

    Ibid., p. 124.

  37. 37.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), p. 402. See Porat (2014), pp. 413–415, classifying the role of balancing in European-based systems as ‘strong,’ and in the U.S. as ‘weak’.

  38. 38.

    See Sweet and Mathews (2010), pp. 117–140; Sullivan and Frase (2009), pp. 53–66. C.f. Pildes (1993), p. 711; (1998), p. 725, arguing for the presence of proportionality in the U.S. law.

  39. 39.

    Huscroft et al. (2014), p. 1.

  40. 40.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 265.

  41. 41.

    Yowell (2014), p. 111.

  42. 42.

    Lochner v. New York, Judgment of 1905, 198 U.S. 45.

  43. 43.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Pharmacy Case, 7 BVerfGE 377, Judgment of 6 November 1958. The case was discussed in Chap. 2 above.

  44. 44.

    Möller (2014), p. 31.

  45. 45.

    McCrudden (2014), p. 20.

  46. 46.

    Webber (2010), pp. 199–200; Sullivan (1992), p. 293; Schauer (1981), p. 265; Barak (2012a, b), pp. 752–754; Tushnet (1999), p. 1278. For a complete study on the U.S. categorical conception of rights, see Gardbaum (2008), p. 32 ff. Curiously, Gardbaum resists the idea of an American exceptionalism and argues that ‘the United States shares the same deep structure, conception, and analysis of constitutional rights as other modern Western democracies’.

  47. 47.

    See Dworkin (1986), p. 46, on genuine conceptual controversies, in which ‘the competing interpretations are directed toward the same objects or events of interpretation’.

  48. 48.

    See for instance Rivers (2006), p. 176, distinguishing the optimising conception, which “sees proportionality as a structured approach to balancing fundamental rights with other rights and interests in the best possible way,” and the state-limiting conception, which “sees proportionality as a set of tests warranting judicial interference to protect rights.” At p. 179, he also reports on ‘the tendency of British, and it would seem, Canadian and South African courts, to treat “necessity” as the final stage of proportionality review and to suppress the language of balancing’.

  49. 49.

    Alexy (1992), p. 149.

  50. 50.

    Particularly concerning the sub-test of legitimate aims, it is controversial whether it should precede or operate within balancing. See Andrade Neto (2015).

  51. 51.

    See Möller (2014), pp. 31–40, for an overview on the competing versions theorists and courts have suggested to proportionality; Möller (2012a), pp. 137–140, mapping four different concepts of balancing.

  52. 52.

    Kumm (2004), p. 579; Rivers (2006), p. 181; Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 76; Klatt and Meister (2012a), p. 7; Grimm (2007), p. 16; Webber (2009), p. 71; Urbina (2012), p. 57; Barak (2012a, b), p. 742.

  53. 53.

    Schlink (1976), p. 76 ff.; Böckenförde (1999), p. 83.

  54. 54.

    von Bernstorff (2014), p. 66 ff.

  55. 55.

    Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982, C. 11 (U.K.).

  56. 56.

    R. v. Oakes, 17550, Judgment of Can., [1986] 1 S.C.R.. See Grimm (2007), p. 383.

  57. 57.

    Gardbaum (2010), p. 83.

  58. 58.

    Grimm (2007), p. 393.

  59. 59.

    Sweet and Mathews (2010), p. 107.

  60. 60.

    Grimm (2007), p. 389.

  61. 61.

    See also Sweet and Mathews (2010), p. 107.

  62. 62.

    Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 67.

  63. 63.

    See Chap. 2 above for a brief discussion about the conception of justice that underlies the principles theory.

  64. 64.

    See for instance, Alexy (2003b), p. 433; Alexy (2010f), p. 9. C.f. Schauer (2010), pp. 40–45.

  65. 65.

    See for instance, Rivers (2010), p. xvii. C.f. Habermas (1996), p. 259.

  66. 66.

    Dworkin (1986), pp. 52, 65–68.

  67. 67.

    See Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), footnote 87 at 389, observing that “the German fundamental concept of the Rechtsstaat —‘a state governed by law’—differs from the common law concept of rule of law, in that it is tied to an organic conception of the state that seeks to integrate state and society.”

  68. 68.

    Alexy (1992), p. 149.

  69. 69.

    Grundgesetz für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Article 19 (1) and (2): “Insofar as, under this Basic Law, a basic right may be restricted by or pursuant to a law …, the law must specify the basic right affected and the Article in which it appears;” and “[i]n no case may the essence of a basic right be affected.” The controversy over the normative source for proportionality is mentioned in Currie (1994), p. 309.

  70. 70.

    See Alexy (2010b), pp. 66–69, 214, on the connection of proportionality with the optimization thesis and the wide-scope conception of rights, respectively; and Alexy (2005), p. 578, on its connection with the thesis of argumentative representation.

  71. 71.

    Borowski (2011), pp. 579–580.

  72. 72.

    Brugger (1994), pp. 396–398.

  73. 73.

    Kaufman and Hassemer (1969), pp. 484–486.

  74. 74.

    Borowski (2011), p. 580.

  75. 75.

    See e.g., Poscher (2003), pp. 80–81; (2009), p. 438 ff.

  76. 76.

    Klatt (2012), p. 7; Borowski (2011), p. 579.

  77. 77.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 5.

  78. 78.

    Rivers (2010), p. xvii; Kumm (2004), pp. 574–575.

  79. 79.

    Alexy (2010b), pp. 13–14.

  80. 80.

    Ibid., p. 14.

  81. 81.

    Ibid.

  82. 82.

    Schlink (1992), p. 718, says: “the Bundesverfassungsgericht does not speak expressly of principles as rules of optimization. However, constitutional scholarship correctly observes that a relative conception of fundamental rights as rules of optimization harmonizes well with the conception of them as objective principles.”

  83. 83.

    Borowski (2011), p. 580.

  84. 84.

    Kumm (2004), pp. 575, 576.

  85. 85.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 66.

  86. 86.

    Ibid., pp. 66–67, footnote 84.

  87. 87.

    Ibid.

  88. 88.

    Alexy (1992), p. 149.

  89. 89.

    For instance, Alexy (2004), p. 45; (2010c), p. 24; (2014a), p. 512.

  90. 90.

    For instance, BVerfG, Child Welfare Case, 22 BVerfGE 180, Judgment of 18 July 1967, p. 199.

  91. 91.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 66.

  92. 92.

    Kirsch (1977), p. 77, translated in Alexy (2010b), pp. 105, footnote 222.

  93. 93.

    Alexy (2014a), p. 513.

  94. 94.

    Alexy (2010c), pp. 27–28.

  95. 95.

    Alexy (2003a), p. 135.

  96. 96.

    Ibid., pp. 135–136.

  97. 97.

    Ibid.

  98. 98.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 411.

  99. 99.

    Alexy (2003a), pp. 135–136.

  100. 100.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 28.

  101. 101.

    Alexy (2003a), pp. 135–136.

  102. 102.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 401.

  103. 103.

    Alexy (2003a), pp. 135–136.

  104. 104.

    Alexy (1994), p. 227.

  105. 105.

    Alexy (2007), p. 25.

  106. 106.

    Alexy (2014a), p. 514. An ongoing debate about balancing concerns how one can allocate formal principles within the weight formula by connecting it to the variable R, which stands for the ‘reliability of the empirical assumptions concerning what the measure in question means for the non-realization of the one principle and the realization of the other principle’. As it happens with the treatment Alexy reserves to formal principles in general, this part of the principles theory has been discussed, criticized, and revised, but doubts persist, and the debates seem to be far from a satisfactory conclusion.

  107. 107.

    See for example, Alexy (2003b), pp. 443–448; (2014a), pp. 512–524; Borowski (2011), pp. 578–586; (2013), pp. 1413–1416; Klatt and Meister (2012a), pp. 11–13, 56–58; (2012b), pp. 694–700; Klatt and Schmidt (2012a), pp. 71–77; Pavlakos (2007), p. 13; Pulido (2004), pp. 129–140.

  108. 108.

    Alexy (2009a), p. 9.

  109. 109.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 409.

  110. 110.

    ‘The problem of scales’ or the discussion on the commensurability/incommensurability of the elements that ought to be considered in the balancing test according to Alexy is the subject of an intense academic controversy. See Alexy (2003a), p. 136; (2003b), pp. 440–442; (2010b), pp. 10–11; (2010b), p. 32; Barak (2010), pp. 15–16; Huscroft et al. (2014), pp. 11, 14–17; Jackson (2004), pp. 833–834; Khosla (2010), p. 299; Klatt and Meister (2012a), pp. 58–66, 72–73; (2012b), pp. 695–699; Möller (2012b), pp. 719–723, 728–729; Rivers (2006), pp. 199–203; Rivers (2007), pp. 179–180, 185; Schauer (2010), pp. 35–36; da Silva (2011), pp. 273–301; Tsakyrakis (2009), pp. 471–475, 482; Urbina (2012), pp. 57–74, 80; Webber (2010), pp. 187, 191–198; Endicott (2014), pp. 311–342; Allan (2014), p. 222; Somek (2006), pp. 135–136.

  111. 111.

    Alexy (2007), p. 11; (2003a), p. 136. Interestingly, Alexy (2007), p. 15, says that “‘l’ stands not just for the common term ‘light,’ but also for other expressions such as ‘minor’ or ‘weak,’ and ‘s’ stands for ‘high’ and ‘strong’ as well as for ‘serious’.”

  112. 112.

    Alexy (2007), p. 15.

  113. 113.

    Ibid., p. 15.

  114. 114.

    Ibid.

  115. 115.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 410. If the quotient is equal to 1, one is before a stalemate, which received special treatment in the principles theory for leading to a case where the legislature is granted discretion to deliberate. See Chap. 6 below.

  116. 116.

    Ibid., p. 107.

  117. 117.

    Klatt (2012), p. 20.

  118. 118.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 407.

  119. 119.

    Klatt and Meister (2012a), p. 57.

  120. 120.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 66.

  121. 121.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 24. See also Alexy (2000), p. 297; (2007), p. 10.

  122. 122.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 24; (2010b), p. 66; (2012), p. 333

  123. 123.

    Borowski (2011), p. 580.

  124. 124.

    Alexy (2010b) , p. 67.

  125. 125.

    Alexy (2005), pp. 572–573. See also Alexy (2000), pp. 297–298.

  126. 126.

    C.f. Poscher (2015), p. 74, opposing the optimization thesis, thus rejecting the connection between proportionality and principles as optimization requirements.

  127. 127.

    Alexy (2000), p. 298; (2003a), p. 135; (2010b), p. 67.

  128. 128.

    Alexy (2000), p. 298; (2010b), p. 102; (2010e), p. 174.

  129. 129.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 69.

  130. 130.

    Ibid., p. 388.

  131. 131.

    C.f. Klement (2008), p. 761, rejecting the identity between fundamental rights and principles, thus objecting the identity thesis and the necessary connection between fundamental rights and proportionality.

  132. 132.

    Alexy (2010c), pp. 23–24.

  133. 133.

    Barak (2012a, b), p. 131.

  134. 134.

    See Kumm (2004), pp. 582–584; (2007), p. 141; Cremer (2014), pp. 59–62; Borowski (2011), pp. 581–582.

  135. 135.

    Alexy (2014b), p. 58.

  136. 136.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 76.

  137. 137.

    Alexy (2005), p. 578.

  138. 138.

    Alexy based his conception of external/internal justification on Wróblewski (1992), pp. 209–264; (1985), pp. 288–291. See Borowski (2011), p. 578, on the influence of Wróblewski’s ideas on the principles theory; Klatt and Schmidt (2012a), p. 74; and (2012b), p. 13, on how proportionality (and particularly balancing) relates to the internal justification/external justification dichotomy.

  139. 139.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 221.

  140. 140.

    Alexy (2003b), p. 434.

  141. 141.

    Alexy (2010a), pp. 221, 230–231; (2010d), pp. 35–94.

  142. 142.

    Klatt and Schmidt (2012a), p. 74.

  143. 143.

    See Alexy ( 2010f), pp. 9–18. See also de Bustamante (2012), pp. 59–71; Duarte (2015); Brożek (2008), pp. 188–201.

  144. 144.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 29.

  145. 145.

    Klatt (2012), p. 20.

  146. 146.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 32.

  147. 147.

    Ibid., p. 32.

  148. 148.

    Klatt (2014), p. 898; Alexy (2010d), p. 69, refers to those as ‘doubtful cases’.

  149. 149.

    Alexy (2012), p. 356, highlights that “each instance of balancing begins with at least two subsumptions.” Yet, as I explain in the text, it is also correct to say that balancing ends with a subsumption.

  150. 150.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 53.

  151. 151.

    Ibid., p. 85.

  152. 152.

    Klatt (2014), pp. 898–899. See also Klatt and Schmidt (2012a), p. 74.

  153. 153.

    STF, Ineligibility Act Case, ADPF 144/DF, Judgment of 6 August 2008, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J.e. 35, 26 Feb. 2010.

  154. 154.

    STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case I, HC 84078/MG, Judgment of 5 February 2009, Relator: Min. Eros Grau, D.J.e. 26 Feb. 2010; STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case II, RHC 93172/SP, Judgment of 12 February 2009, Relatora: Min. Carmen Lúcia, D.J.e. 84, 6 May. 2011.

  155. 155.

    STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011.

  156. 156.

    STF, Ellwanger Case, HC 82424/RS, Judgment of 17 September 2003, Relator (acórdão): Min. Maurício Corrêa, D.J. 10 Mar. 2004.

  157. 157.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009; STF, Arrested Defaulter Case II, RE 466.343/SP, Judgment of 3 December 2008, Relator: Min. Cezar Peluso, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009.

  158. 158.

    STF (First Panel), Abortion Case, HC 124306/RJ, Judgment of 9 August 2016, Relator (acórdão): Min. Roberto Barroso, D.J.e. 52, 17 Mar. 2017.

  159. 159.

    STF, Ineligibility Act Case, ADPF 144/DF, Judgment of 6 August 2008, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J.e. 35, 26 Feb. 2010.

  160. 160.

    Lei Complementar 64, de 21 de maio de 1990, Brazil, D.O.U., 21.05.1990, Article 1, d, e, g, h (repealed 2010).

  161. 161.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 5, LVII: “No one shall be considered guilty before the issuing of a final and unappealable criminal sentence.” All references in English to the Federal Constitution are taken from http://bd.camara.gov.br/bd/bitstream/handle/bdcamara/1344/constituicao_ingles_3ed.pdf, unless it is indicated otherwise.

  162. 162.

    Alexy (1986), p. 146, quoted in STF, Ineligibility Act Case, ADPF 144/DF, Judgment of 6 August 2008, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J.e. 35, 26 Feb. 2010.

  163. 163.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009; STF, Arrested Defaulter Case II, RE 466.343/SP, Judgment of 3 December 2008, Relator: Min. Cezar Peluso, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009. For more on the cases, see Varella (2014), pp. 146–147; Daly (2014), pp. 12–13; Santos (2013), pp. 27–40; de Morais (2016), p. 140.

  164. 164.

    Organization of American States, American Convention on Human Rights, Article 7, Paragraph 7.

  165. 165.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 5, LXVII: “There shall be no civil imprisonment for indebtedness except in the case of a person responsible for voluntary and inexcusable default of alimony obligation and in the case of an unfaithful trustee.”

  166. 166.

    Código Civil, Lei 10.406, de 1o de outubro de 2002, D.O.U., 11.01.2002, Article 652.

  167. 167.

    Decreto-Lei 911, de 10 de janeiro de 1969, D.O.F.C., 03.10.1969, Article 4.

  168. 168.

    See in this respect, Santos (2013), pp. 24–25.

  169. 169.

    Alexy (1986), p. 146, quoted in STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009. Identical quotation had been used before in STF, Ineligibility Act Case, ADPF 144/DF, Judgment of 6 August 2008, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J.e. 35, 26 Feb. 2010.

  170. 170.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009 (my translation).

  171. 171.

    Ibid.

  172. 172.

    The first decision on the matter is STF, RE 80004/SE, Judgment of 1 June 1977, Relator: Min. Xavier de Albuquerque, D.J. 29 Dec. 1977.

  173. 173.

    See STF, HC 72131/RJ, Judgment of 23 November 1995, Relator: Min. Marco Aurélio, D.J. 1 Aug. 1995.

  174. 174.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case II, RE 466.343/SP, Judgment of 3 December 2008, Relator: Min. Cezar Peluso, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009.

  175. 175.

    STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case I, HC 84078/MG, Judgment of 5 February 2009, Relator: Min. Eros Grau, D.J.e. 26 Feb. 2010; STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case II, RHC 93172/SP, Judgment of 12 February 2009, Relatora: Min. Carmen Lúcia, D.J.e. 84, 6 May 2011.

  176. 176.

    Código de Processo Penal, Decreto-Lei 3.689, de 3 de outubro de 1941, D.O.F.C. 13.10.1941, Article 637.

  177. 177.

    For instance, HC 72.366/SP, HC 72.366/SP, Judgment of Brazil, Relator: Min. Néri da Silveira, 13 Sep. 1995, D.J. 26 Nov. 1999 (1995).

  178. 178.

    In a series of previous decisions, the STF had extended the pre-trial detention to heinous crimes, for instance. See e.g., STF, HC 70634/PE, Judgment of 9 November 1993, Relator: Min. Francisco Rezek, D.J. 24 Jun. 1994.

  179. 179.

    STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011.

  180. 180.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 5, XXXVI: “The law shall not injure the vested right, the perfect juridical act and the res judicata.”

  181. 181.

    Código de Processo Civil, Lei 5.869, de 11 de janeiro de 1973, D.O. 17.01.1973, Article 468 (repealed 2015).

  182. 182.

    STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011.

  183. 183.

    Alexy (1993), p. 92, paraphrased in STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011.

  184. 184.

    Alexy (2003b), paraphrased in STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011.

  185. 185.

    STF, Paternity Test Case, RE 363889/DF, Judgment of 2 June 2011, Relator: Min. Dias Toffoli, D.J.e. 238, 16 Dec. 2011, my translation.

  186. 186.

    Ibid.

  187. 187.

    STF (First Panel), Abortion Case, HC 124306/RJ, Judgment of 9 August 2016, Relator (acórdão): Min. Roberto Barroso, D.J.e. 52, 17 Mar. 2017.

  188. 188.

    STF, Anencephaly Case, ADPF 54/DF, Judgment of 12 April 2012, STF, Relator: Min. Marco Aurélio, D.J.e. 80, 30 Apr. 2013.

  189. 189.

    Ibid.

  190. 190.

    STF, Sugarcane-Straw-Burning Case, RE 586224/SP, Judgment of 5 March 2015, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 85, 8 May 2015.

  191. 191.

    STF, Intellectual Property Management Case, ADI 5062/DF, Judgment of 27 October 2016, STF, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 134, Jun. 21, 2017.

  192. 192.

    STF, Treasury Debt Update Case, RE 870947/SE, Judgment of 20 September 2017, STF, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 262, Nov. 20, 2017.

  193. 193.

    STF, Ellwanger Case, HC 82424/RS, Judgment of 17 September 2003, Relator (acórdão): Min. Maurício Corrêa, D.J. 10 Mar. 2004.

  194. 194.

    STF, Ineligibility Act Case, ADPF 144/DF, Judgment of 6 August 2008, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J.e. 35, 26 Feb. 2010.

  195. 195.

    STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case I, HC 84078/MG, Judgment of 5 February 2009, Relator: Min. Eros Grau, D.J.e. 26 Feb. 2010; STF, Pre-Trial Detention Case II, RHC 93172/SP, Judgment of 12 February 2009, Relatora: Min. Carmen Lúcia, D.J.e. 84, 6 May. 2011.

  196. 196.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case II, RE 466.343/SP, Judgment of 3 December 2008, Relator: Min. Cezar Peluso, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009; STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009.

  197. 197.

    STF, Sugarcane-Straw-Burning Case, RE 586224/SP, Judgment of 5 March 2015, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 85, 8 May 2015.

  198. 198.

    STF, Treasury Debt Update Case, RE 870947/SE, Judgment of 20 September 2017, STF, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 262, Nov. 20, 2017.

  199. 199.

    STF, Intellectual Property Management Case, ADI 5062/DF, Judgment of 27 October 2016, STF, Relator: Min. Luiz Fux, D.J.e. 134, Jun. 21, 2017.

  200. 200.

    STF (First Panel), Abortion Case, HC 124306/RJ, Judgment of 9 August 2016, Relator (acórdão): Min. Roberto Barroso, D.J.e. 52, 17 Mar. 2017.

  201. 201.

    STF, Arrested Defaulter Case I, RE 349.703/RS, Judgment of 2 December 2008, Relator: Min. Carlos Britto, D.J.e. 104, 5 Jun. 2009.

  202. 202.

    Alexy (2007), p. 21.

  203. 203.

    STF, ADI 815/DF, Judgment of 28 March 1996, Relator: Min. Moreira Alves, D.J. 10 May 1996.

  204. 204.

    According to Sarmento (2003), pp. 37–40, two conceptions of hierarchy of constitutional principles fit the Brazilian legal system: static and dynamic.

  205. 205.

    da Silva (2001), p. 31, maintains similar opinion.

  206. 206.

    See e.g., de Morais (2016); Sarlet (2009), p. 397.

  207. 207.

    da Silva (2001), p. 34.

  208. 208.

    Martins (2003), p. 21.

  209. 209.

    Sarmento (2006), pp. 198–204.

  210. 210.

    Silva (2001), p. 31 (my translation).

  211. 211.

    de Morais (2016), pp. 249–253.

  212. 212.

    Ibid., p. 249.

  213. 213.

    Ibid., p. 243 ff.

  214. 214.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 388.

  215. 215.

    In fact, Alexy conceives of a right as something distinct of an interest, but not all the principles-theory enthusiasts adhere to this differentiation. See Klatt and Meister (2012a), Chap. 3, for a discussion in this respect.

  216. 216.

    See Webber (2009), pp. 5–6, for instance.

  217. 217.

    Schlink (1992), p. 718.

  218. 218.

    Schlink (1992), p. 718; (1995), p. 1237.

  219. 219.

    de Morais (2016), p. 248 (my translation).

  220. 220.

    Ibid., p. 121.

  221. 221.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 66.

  222. 222.

    Grimm (2007), p. 393.

  223. 223.

    Gardbaum (2010), p. 83.

  224. 224.

    STF, Electricity Rationing Case, ADC 9/DF, Judgment of 13 December 2001, Relator (acórdão): Min. Ellen Gracie, D.J. 24 Apr. 2004; STF, Gas Cylinders Case, ADI 855/PR, Judgment of 6 March 2008, Relator (acórdão): Min. Gilmar Mendes, D.J.e 59, 27 Mar. 2009. See da Silva (2001), pp. 36–41, for an analysis of how the STF applied the proportionality test to these cases.

  225. 225.

    da Silva (2001), pp. 44–45.

  226. 226.

    de Morais (2016), p. 248.

  227. 227.

    Costa, pp. 248–253.

  228. 228.

    Barros (1996), p. 88.

  229. 229.

    Morais (2016), pp. 248–249.

  230. 230.

    See e.g., STF, HC 76060/SC, Judgment of 31 March 1998, Relator: Min. Sepúlveda Pertence, D.J. 15 May 1998.

  231. 231.

    da Silva (2001), pp. 28–31. See also Stumm (1995), p. 159; Costa (2008), footnote 2 at 15, and 248–253.

  232. 232.

    Barroso (2009), p. 230, for example. Ávila (2012), p. 182, affirms that proportionality and reasonableness are not identical, but concedes that the former comprehends the latter.

  233. 233.

    See Barroso (2009), p. 230: ‘the scholarship and case law in Europe as in Brazil usually refer to the principle of proportionality, concept that in general lines bears a relation of fungibility to the principle of reasonableness’. (my translation).

  234. 234.

    See for instance, Cohn (2010), p. 585, pointing out that, behind the difference in wording, proportionality as developed in Germany shares basic similarities with the unreasonableness review in the U.K.

  235. 235.

    da Silva (2001), pp. 28–31.

  236. 236.

    Legal comparatists refer to the phenomena as assimilatory modification. See Wise (1990), p. 17: “[Borrowing] need not result in exact replication of the borrowed model. Cultural elements are rarely copied in precisely their original form; they usually undergo ‘assimilatory modification’ or ‘functional shift’. Borrowing itself is a highly creative, selective process;” Sapir (1916), p. 32: “almost invariably … a new idea or activity borrowed from outside falls in line with already existing ideas or activities.”

  237. 237.

    Barroso and de Barcellos (2008), pp. 362–363. See Barros (1996), p. 125; Sarmento (2003), p. 87.

  238. 238.

    Barroso (2009), p. 231.

  239. 239.

    Curiously, similar conception of reasonableness as a regulative idea deriving from practical rationality is not strange to Alexy’s theory, judicial decision-making in general, or the case law of the BVerfG in particular. See Alexy (2009b), pp. 7–9, on the connection between reasonableness and balancing; MacCormick (2005), p. 168, on different meanings of reasonableness in law including the requirement that a judicial decision should be reasonable; and Schwarze (1992), on the notion of reasonableness in the early case law of the BVerfG.

  240. 240.

    For more on the mixed influence of U.S. and European law on Brazilian constitutionalism, see Chap. 2 above on the peculiarities of the STF’s structure and functioning, and Chap. 6 below on the constitutional text and STF’s duty to guard the Federal Constitution.

  241. 241.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 5, LIV: “No one shall be deprived of freedom or of his assets without the due process of law.” This wording is altogether similar to the U.S. Const. amend. V: “No person shall be … deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.” See Barros (1996), pp. 122–123, on the influence of the U.S. constitutionalism in Brazil; and Sarmento (2003), pp. 91–93; and Mendes (1996), pp. 14–16, on how the concept of reasonableness is familiar to the Brazilian legal practice.

  242. 242.

    See Mendes (2001), p. 2, e.g.

  243. 243.

    Constitutional comparatists have documented other cases in which the idea of reasonableness and proportionality appeared together, but in common law systems. See Cohn (2010), pp. 625–626, for an example of a British judgement.

  244. 244.

    Freire (2007), p. 11.

  245. 245.

    Ibid., p. 11.

  246. 246.

    Alexy (1991), p. 77; (1992), p. 150.

  247. 247.

    Alexy (1992), p. 150.

  248. 248.

    Ibid., p. 150.

  249. 249.

    Freire (2007), p. 1; Barroso (2009), pp. 128–145; Brugger (1994), p. 396.

  250. 250.

    This does not come as a surprise. As Alexy (1991), p. 74, realizes, the uncertainty of legal methodology is only one reason for the existence of disputes in legal interpretation; others are the openness of law and the possibility of divergences about rightness or justice.

  251. 251.

    da Silva (2013), pp. 569–584; de Chueiri (2012), pp. 1–11; de Baracho Júnior (2003), pp. 509–520; Rodriguez (2013).

  252. 252.

    da Silva (2001), p. 26.

  253. 253.

    Sarlet (2009), p. 396.

  254. 254.

    Sarmento (2003), p. 53; Barros (1996), p. 87.

  255. 255.

    Leiria (2008), p. 168.

  256. 256.

    Ávila (2012), pp. 182–184.

  257. 257.

    See Mendes (2001), p. 2; Barroso (1998), pp. 75–77; Barros (1996), pp. 93–94; Sarlet (2009), p. 396.

  258. 258.

    Barroso (2009), pp. 374–375; Stumm (1995), p. 173.

  259. 259.

    See STF, ADI 1.407 MC/DF, Judgment of 7 March 1996, Relator: Min. Celso de Mello, D.J. 24 Nov. 2000, for an example of a decision that derived proportionality from this clause. See also da Silva (2001), p. 32; Sarmento (2006), p. 164; Costa, p. footnote 2 at 15; and Mendes (2012), pp. 76–79; (2001) p. 18, on the connection between proportionality and due process of law in Brazil, particularly in the case law of the STF.

  260. 260.

    da Silva (2001), p. 43.

  261. 261.

    Ibid., pp. 45–46.

References

  • Aleinikoff TA (1987) Constitutional law in the age of balancing. Yale Law J 96(5):943–1005. https://doi.org/10.2307/796529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1986) Theorie der Grundrechte. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1991) Statutory interpretation in the Federal Republic of Germany. In: MacCormick N, Summers RS (eds) Interpreting statutes: a comparative study. Dartmouth, Aldershot, Hants, England; Brookfield, Vt., USA, pp 73–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1992) Rights, legal reasoning and rational discourse. Ratio Juris 5(2):143–152. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1992.tb00121.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1993) Teoría de los Derechos Fundamentales (Valdés EG Trans.). Centro de Estudios Constitutionales, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1994) Basic rights and democracy in jurgen habermas’s procedural paradigm of the law. Ratio Juris 7(2):227–238. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1994.tb00177.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2000) On the structure of legal principles. Ratio Juris 13(3):294–304. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9337.00157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003a) Constitutional rights, balancing, and rationality. Ratio Juris 16(2):131–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003b) On balancing and subsumption structural comparison. Ratio Juris 16(4):433–449. https://doi.org/10.1046/j.0952-1917.2003.00244.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2004) Discourse theory and fundamental rights. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 35–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2005) Balancing, constitutional review, and representation. Int J Const Law 3(4):572–581. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moi040

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2007) The weight formula. In: Stelmach J, Brożek B, Zaluski W (eds) (Paulson SL, Brożek B Trans.), Frontiers of the economic analysis of law, vol 3. Jagiellonian Univ. Press, Kraków, pp 9–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2009a) On constitutional rights to protection. Theory Pract Legislation (Formelly Legisprudence) 3(1):1–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2009b) The reasonableness of law. In: Bongiovanni G, Sartor G, Valentini C (eds) Reasonableness and law. Springer, Dordrecht; New York, pp 5–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010a) A theory of legal argumentation: the theory of rational discourse as theory of legal justification (Adler R, MacCormic N Trans). Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010b) A theory of constitutional rights (Rivers J Trans.). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010c) The construction of constitutional rights. Law Ethics Human Rights 4(1):21–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010d) The argument from injustice: a reply to legal positivism (Paulson SL, Paulson BL Trans). Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010e) The dual nature of law. Ratio Juris 23(2):167–182. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2010.00449.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010f) Two or three? In: Borowski M (ed), On the nature of legal principles : proceedings of the special workshop ‘The Principles Theory’ held at the 23rd world congress of the international association for philosophy of law and social philosophy (IVR), Kraków, 2007. Franz Steiner Verlag, Nomos, Stuttgart, pp 9–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2012) Comments and responses. In: Klatt M (ed), Institutionalized reason : the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2014a) Constitutional rights and proportionality. Revus Revija Za Ustavno Teorijo in Filozofijo Prava/J Const Theory Philos Law 22:51–65. https://doi.org/10.4000/revus.2783

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2014b) Formal principles: some replies to critics. Int J Const Law 12(3):511–524. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mou051

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allan TRS (2014) Democracy, legality, and proportionality. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber GCN (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, pp 205–233

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Andrade Neto J (2015) Should all arguments matter? on the exclusion of certain reasons from the proportionality test. In: Paulson SL, Trivisonno ATG, de Oliveira JA (eds), Alexy’s theory of law: proceedings of the special workshop ‘Alexy’s Theory of Law’ held at the 26th world congress of the international association for philosophy of law and social philosophy in Belo Horizonte, 2013. Franz Steiner Verlag, pp 111–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Ávila HB (2012) Teoria dos princípios: da definição à aplicação dos princípios jurídicos, 13th edn. Malheiros Editores, São Paulo

    Google Scholar 

  • Balmer TA (2008) Some thoughts on proportionality. Oregon Law Rev 87(3):783–818

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2010) Proportionality and principled balancing. Law Ethics Human Rights 4(1):1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012a) Proportionality. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 738–755

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012b) Proportionality: constitutional rights and their limitations (Kalir D Trans.). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K., New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barros S de T (1996) O princípio da proporcionalidade e o controle de constitucionalidade das leis restrictivas de direitos fundamentales. Brasília Jurídica

    Google Scholar 

  • Barroso LR (1998) Os princípios da razoabilidade e da proporcionalidade no direito constitucional. Revista dos tribunais: cadernos de direito constitucional e ciência política 23:65–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Barroso LR (2009) Interpretação e aplicação da Constituição: fundamentos de uma dogmática constitucional transformadora. Saraiva, São Paulo

    Google Scholar 

  • Barroso LR, de Barcellos AP (2008) O começo da história: A nova interpretação constitucional e o papel dos princípios no direito brasileiro. A nova interpretação constitucional: ponderação, direitos fundamentais e relações privadas, 3rd edn. Renovar, Rio de Janeiro, São Paulo, Recife, pp 327–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Böckenförde E-W (1999) Vier Thesen zur Kommunitarismus-Debatte. In: Siller P, Keller B (eds) Rechtsphilosophische Kontroversen der Gegenwart. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 83–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2008a) Balancing, the global and the local: judicial balancing as a problematic topic in comparative (Constitutional) law. Hastings Int Comp Law Rev 31(2):555–586

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2008b) Luth’s 50th anniversary: some comparative observations on the German foundations of judicial balancing. German Law J 9:121

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2010) Genealogies of balancing as discourse. Law Ethics Human Rights 4(1):109–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2013) Balancing constitutional rights: the origins and meanings of postwar legal discourse. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2011) Discourse, principles, and the problem of law and morality: Robert Alexy’s three main works: Robert Alexy’s three main works by Martin Borowski. Jurisprudence 2(2):575–595. https://doi.org/10.5235/204033211798716899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2013) On apples and oranges comment on Niels Petersen. German LJ 14:1409

    Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2008) Analogy in legal discourse. Archiv Fuer Rechts- Und Sozialphilosphie 94(2):188–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Brugger W (1994) Legal interpretation, schools of jurisprudence, and anthropology: some remarks from a German point of view. Amer J Comp Law 42(2):395–421. https://doi.org/10.2307/840752

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Bustamante T da R (2012) Finding analogies between cases: on Robert Alexy’s third basic operation in the application of law. In: de Bustamante T da R, Pulido CB (eds), Proceedings of the 24th world congress of the international association for philosophy of law and social philosophy, Beijing, 2009. Stuttgart, Sinzheim, Steiner, Nomos, pp 59–71

    Google Scholar 

  • de Chueiri VK (2012) Judicial review, reasons and technology: a glance at constitutionalism and democracy. Presented at the 25th IVR world congress: law, science and technology Frankfurt am Main 15–20 August 2011, Paper Series: 019, Frankfurt am Main: Universität-Bibliothek Frankfurt am Main. Retrieved from urn:nbn:de:hebis:30:3–248774

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2009) The hidden foreign law debate in Heller: the proportionality approach in American constitutional law. San Diego Law Rev 46:367–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2010) American balancing and German proportionality: the historical origins. Int J Const Law 8(2):263–286. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moq004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohn M (2010) Legal transplant chronicles: the evolution of unreasonableness and proportionality review of the administration in the United Kingdom. Am J Comp Law 58(3):583–629. https://doi.org/10.5131/ajcl.2009.0048

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa AA (2008) O princípio da proporcionalidade na jurisprudência do STF. Thesaurus Editora

    Google Scholar 

  • Cremer W (2014) The basic right to ‘free development of the personality’: mere protection of personality development versus general right of freedom of action. In: Pünder H, Waldhoff C (eds), Debates in German public law. Bloomsbury Publishing, pp 57–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie DP (1994) The constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiria C da S (2008) Repensando o Artigo 236 do Código Eleitoral. Revista Jurídica UNIJUS/Universidade de Uberaba, Ministério Público do Estado de Minas Gerais 11(15):155–176

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva VA (2001) O proporcional e o razoável. Revista dos Tribunais 798:23–50

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva VA (2011) Comparing the incommensurable: constitutional principles, balancing and rational decision. Oxford J Leg Stud 31(2):273–301. https://doi.org/10.1093/ojls/gqr004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • da Silva VA (2013) Deciding without deliberating. Int J Const Law 11(3):557–584. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mot019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly TG (2014) The differential openness of Brazil’s supreme federal court to external jurisprudence. Presented at the international association of constitutional law world congress, Oslo. http://www.jus.uio.no/english/research/news-and-events/events/conferences/2014/wccl-cmdc/wccl/papers/ws5/w5-daly.pdf

  • de Baracho Jr JAO (2003) A nova hermenêutica no supremo tribunal federal. In: Sampaio JAL (ed) Crise e desafios da Constituição: perspectivas críticas da teoria e das práticas constitucionais brasileiras. Del Rey, Belo Horizonte, pp 509–520

    Google Scholar 

  • de Morais FS (2016) Poderação e arbitrariedade: A inadequada recepção de Alexy pelo STF. JusPodivm, Salvador

    Google Scholar 

  • Duarte D (2015) Analogy and balancing: the partial reducibility thesis and its problems. Revus (25). https://doi.org/10.4000/revus.3244

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott T (2014) Proportionality and incommensurability. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber GCN (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, pp 311–342

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frantz LB (1961) The first amendment in the balance. Yale Law J 71:1424

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freire AR (2007) Evolution of constitutional interpretation in brazil and employment of balancing “method” by the federal supreme court in judicial review. In: Workshop 15: the balancing and proportionality in the constitutional review. http://www.enelsyn.gr/papers/w15/Paper%20by%20Prof%20Alonso%20Reis%20Freire.pdf

  • Gardbaum S (2008) The myth and the reality of American constitutional exceptionalism. Mich Law Rev 107:391–466

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardbaum S (2010) A democratic defense of constitutional balancing. Law Ethics Human Rights 4(1):79–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm D (2007) Proportionality in Canadian and German constitutional jurisprudence. Univ Toronto Law J 57(2):383–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber G (2014) Introduction. In: Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. University Press, New York, Cambridge. http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2434091

  • Jackson VC (2004) Being proportional about proportionality. Book review of: the ultimate rule of law. By Beatty DM. Univ Minnesota Digital Conserv Const Comment 21(3):803–859

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman A, Hassemer W (1969) Enacted law and judicial decision in German jurisprudential thought. Univ Toronto Law J 461–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khosla M (2010) Proportionality: an assault on human rights?: a reply. Int J Const Law 8(2):298–306. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moq002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsch W (1977) Einführung in die Theorie der Entscheidungsprozesse (2., durchges. u. erg. Aufl. d. Bd. 1 bis 3 als Gesamtausg). Verlag Gabler, Wiesbaden

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M (2012) Robert Alexy’s philosophy of law as system. In: Institutionalized reason : the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M (2014) An egalitarian defense of proportionality-based balancing: a reply to Luc B Tremblay. Int J Const Law 12(4):891–899. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mou061

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister M (2012a) Proportionality—a benefit to human rights? remarks on the I·CON controversy. Int J Const Law 10(3):687–708. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mos019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister M (2012b) The constitutional structure of proportionality, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Schmidt J (2012a) Abwägung unter Unsicherheit. Archiv Des Oeffentlichen Rechts 137(4):545–591. https://doi.org/10.1628/000389112804720023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Schmidt J (2012b) Epistemic discretion in constitutional law. Int J Const Law 10(1):69–105. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mor056

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klement JH (2008) Vom Nutzen einer Theorie, die alles erklärt. JuristenZeitung, 63(15–16(8)), 756–763. http://dx.doi.org/10.1628/002268808785259767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kommers DP, Miller RA (2012) The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany, 3rd edn, rev. and expanded. Duke University Press, Durham, N.C

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2004) Constitutional rights as principles: on the structure and domain of constitutional justice. a review essay on a theory of constitutional rights. Int J Const Law 2(3):574–596. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/2.3.574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2007) Political liberalism and the structure of rights: on the place and limits of the proportionality requirement. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse: the legal philosophy of Robert Alexy. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon, pp 131–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2012) Total rights and the banality of injustice. Centuty’s Rev J Rational Leg Debate 1:10–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Law DS (2004) Generic constitutional law. Minnesota Law Rev 89:652

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick N (2005) Rhetoric and the rule of law: a theory of legal reasoning. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martins L (2003) Proporcionalidade Como Critério de Controle de Constitucionalidade: Problemas de Sua Recepção Pelo Direito e Jurisdição Constitucional Brasileiros. Cadernos de Direito, Editora Unimep 3(5):15–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden C (2014) The pluralism of human rights adjudication. In: Lazarus L, McCrudden C, Bowles N (eds) Reasoning rights: comparative judicial engagement. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon, pp 3–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes GF (1996) Prefácio. In: Barros S de T, O princípio da proporcionalidade e o controle de constitucionalidade das leis restrictivas de direitos fundamentales. Brasília Jurídica, pp 13–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes GF (2001) O Princípio da Proporcionalidade na Jurisprudência do Supremo Tribunal Federal: Novas Leituras. Revista Diálogo Jurídico, 1(5). http://www.direitopublico.com.br/pdf_5/DIALOGO-JURIDICO-05-AGOSTO-2001-GILMAR-MENDES.pdf

  • Mendes GF (2012) Direitos fundamentais e controle de constitucionalidade estudos de direito constitucional, 4th edn. Saraiva, São Paulo

    Google Scholar 

  • Möller K (2012a) Proportionality: challenging the critics. Int J Const Law 10(3):709–731. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mos024

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Möller K (2012b) The global model of constitutional rights, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, United Kingdom

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Möller K (2014) Constructing the proportionality test: an emerging global conversation. In: Lazarus L, McCrudden C, Bowles N (eds) Reasoning rights: comparative judicial engagement. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon, pp 31–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavlakos G (2007) Introduction. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse: the legal philosophy of Robert Alexy. Hart Pub, Oxford; Portland, Or., pp 1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Pildes RH (1993) Avoiding balancing: the role of exclusionary reasons in constitutional law. Hastings LJ 45:711

    Google Scholar 

  • Pildes RH (1998) Why rights are not trumps: social meanings, expressive harms, and constitutionalism. J Leg Stud 27(S2):725–763. https://doi.org/10.1086/468041

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porat I (2014) Mapping the American debate over balancing. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber G (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 397–416

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Poscher R (2003) Grundrechte als Abwehrrechte: reflexive Regelung rechtlich geordneter Freiheit. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Poscher R (2009) Insights, errors and self-misconceptions of the theory of principles. Ratio Juris 22(4):425–454. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2009.00434.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poscher R (2015) Theory of a phantom: the principles theory’s futile quest for its object. In: de Oliveira JA, Paulson SL, Trivisonno ATG (eds), Alexy’s theory of law proceedings of the special workshop ‘Alexy’s Theory of Law’ held at the 26th world congress of the international association for philosophy of law and social philosophy in Belo Horizonte, 2013 (1. Aufl). Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 111–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulido CB (2004) On Alexy’s weight formula. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: On Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 129–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Reznik I (2000) The distinction between legislative and adjudicative decisions in Dolan v City of Tigard. NYUL Rev 75:242–282

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2006) Proportionality and variable intensity of review. Cambridge Law J 65(01):174–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2007) Proportionality, discretion and the second law of balancing. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse: the legal philosophy of Robert Alexy. Hart Pub, Oxford; Portland, Or., pp 167–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2010) A theory of constitutional rights and the british constitution. A theory of constitutional rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez JR (2013) Como decidem as cortes?: para uma crítica do direito (brasileiro). FGV, Rio de Janeiro

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos GF (2013) Treaties X human rights treaties: a critical analysis of the dual stance on treaties in the Brazilian legal system. Eur JL Reform 15:20

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapir E (1916) Time perspective in aboriginal american culture: a study in method. Geol Surv Memoir 90(13):1–87. https://doi.org/10.2307/1837696

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarlet IW (2009) A eficácia dos direitos fundamentais: uma teoria deral dos direitos fundamentais na perspectiva constitucional. Livraria do Advogado, Porto Alegre

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarmento D (2003) A ponderação de interesses na Constituição Federal, 1st edn. Lumen Juris, Rio de Janeiro

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarmento D (2006) Legalização do aborto e Constituição. In: Livres e iguais: estudos de Direito Constitucional. Editora Lumen Juris, pp 95–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1981) Categories and the first amendment: a play in three acts. Vand L Rev 34:265

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2010) Balancing, subsumption, and the constraining role of legal text. Law Ethics Human Rights 4(1):35–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (1976) Abwägung im Verfassungsrecht (1. Aufl). Duncker und Humblot, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (1992) German constitutional culture in transition. Cardozo L Rev 14:711

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (1995) The dynamics of constitutional adjudication. Cardozo L Rev 17:1231

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (2012) Proportionality. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 718–737

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarze J (1992) European administrative law. Luxembourg: London: Office for Official Publications of the European Communities ; Sweet & Maxwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Somek A (2006) Rechtliches Wissen (1. Aufl). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumm RD (1995) Princípio da proporcionalidade no Direito Constitucional Brasileiro. Livraria do Advogado, Porto Alegre

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan KM (1992) Post-liberal judging: the roles of categorization and balancing. U Colo L Rev 63:293

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan ET, Frase RS (2009) Proportionality principles in American law: controlling excessive government actions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS, Mathews J (2008) Proportionality balancing and global constitutionalism. Columbia J Trans Law 47:68–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS, Mathews J (2010) All things in proportion-American rights review and the problem of balancing. Emory LJ 60:797

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakyrakis S (2009) Proportionality: an assault on human rights? Int J Const Law 7(3):468–493. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mop011

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (1999) The possibilities of comparative constitutional law. Yale Law J 108(6):1225–1309. https://doi.org/10.2307/797327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Urbina FJ (2012) A critique of proportionality. Am J Jurisprudence 57

    Google Scholar 

  • Varella MD (2014) Internationalization of law: globalization, international law and complexity. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bernstorff J (2014) Proportionality without balancing: why judicial ad hoc balancing is unnecessary and potentially detrimental to the realisation of individual and collective self-determination. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber G (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 63–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber G (2009) The negotiable constitution: on the limitation of rights. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK,  New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber G (2010) Proportionality, balancing, and the cult of constitutional rights scholarship. Canad J Law Jurisprudence 23(1). http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1322810

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wise EM (1990) The transplant of legal patterns. Am J Comp Law 38:1–22. https://doi.org/10.2307/840531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1985) Presuppositions of legal reasoning. In: Bulygin E, Gardies J-L, Niiniluoto I (eds), Man, law, and modern forms of life. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Holland , Boston, D. Reidel Pub. Co. , Hingham, MA, U.S.A. , pp 283–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1992) The judicial application of law (Bankowski Z, MacCormic N, eds). Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Yowell P (2014) Proportionality in the United States constitutional law. In: Lazarus L, McCrudden C, Bowles N (eds) Reasoning rights: comparative judicial engagement. Hart Publishing, Oxford, Portland, Oregon, pp 87–114

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Andrade Neto, J. (2018). The Principles-Theory Variant of Proportionality. In: Borrowing Justification for Proportionality. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 72. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02263-1_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02263-1_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-02262-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-02263-1

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics