Skip to main content

On the Migration of Proportionality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Borrowing Justification for Proportionality

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 72))

  • 292 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter addresses the controversy surrounding the judicial recourse to proportionality and reconstructs the reasons for and against borrowing the test as a normative argument. It starts providing an overview of the specialized literature on the migration of proportionality and its reception in Brazil, where it has served the Supreme Federal Court (STF). Section 2.1 briefly reconstructs the three phases of the historical development of proportionality in Germany, giving a glimpse of the test in operation and how it has appeared in the case law of the German Federal Constitutional Court (BVerfG). Section 2.2 presents the explanatory reasons often advanced for the worldwide spread of proportionality, ranging from the functions the test allegedly performs in decision-making to certain favorable historical conditions arguably shared by legal cultures. Section 2.3 discusses the Ellwanger Case (2003), which contains the first references to Alexy in the STF’s case law, and discloses peculiarities about the court’s organization and functioning. Finally, Sect. 2.4 expounds the democratic objection against borrowing and advances three theses (weak, moderate, and strong) that could justify the judicial recourse to proportionality. I submit that, whereas the principles theory implies the strong thesis and the STF seemingly justifies its borrowings with the help of the weak thesis, the moderate thesis is the correct one.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Barak (2010), p. 182. See for instance Yi (2007), pp. 263–268.

  2. 2.

    Weinrib (2006), p. 89 ff.; Bomhoff (2013), p. 10 ff.

  3. 3.

    Klatt and Meister (2014a), p. 193 ff.; Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 75; (2010), p. 178; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 264 ff.; (2009), pp. 369, 380.

  4. 4.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), pp. 84–85; Kennedy (2002), pp. 674–675.

  5. 5.

    Bomhoff (2010), p. 123. Much of what is said below about the historical development of proportionality in Germany was also taken from Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2011), p. 465; Barak (2012a, b), pp. 178–179; Schwarze (1992), pp. 685–692. C.f. Pulido (2013), pp. 489–503, dividing the expansion of proportionality into six phases, which the author refers to as ‘migrations.’.

  6. 6.

    Bomhoff (2013), p. 76.

  7. 7.

    See Svarez (1960), pp. 39–40, 485–487. Among the authors who trace the origins of proportionality back to Svarez, one can mention: Currie (1994), pp. 307–308; Sweet and Mathews (2008), pp. 98–100; Barak (2010), pp. 178–179; (2012a, b), pp. 177–178.

  8. 8.

    Würtenberger (1999), pp. 65, 67.

  9. 9.

    Lerche (1999), pp. 24–25; Hirschberg (1981), pp. 2–19; Stern (1993), pp. 168–169; Remmert (1995), p. 200; Grimm (2007), pp. 384–385.

  10. 10.

    Currie (1994), p. 308. Nineteenth-century German legal thought conceived of the Rechtsstaat principle as possessing characteristic elements that included “strict legality of every exercise of state power; freedom from arbitrary state action; proportionality of the means employed by the state to accomplish legitimate ends; and the comprehensive judicial control of every state action that affects the subjective rights of a citizen.” [Ledford (2004), p. 207].

  11. 11.

    Barak (2012a, b), p. 177; Bomhoff (2010), p. 124. For an overview of the jurisprudence of interests, see Cohn (1950), p. 117 ff.

  12. 12.

    See Rümelin and Schoch (1948) for a selection of writings from the jurisprudence of interests.

  13. 13.

    Seagle (1945), p. 71. See e.g., Jhering (1900), pp. 274–275, 287–288, 297.

  14. 14.

    Cohn (1950), p. 118. See Kennedy (2011), p. 194 ff., on the importance of Jhering and Heck for the development of balancing in Germany; Sartor (2010), p. 194 ff., on the connection between proportionality and goal-oriented (or teleological) reasoning, which Jhering believed to be an essential aspect of legal thinking. Interestingly, Alexy (2010a), pp. 88, 115–116, mentioned Jhering two times in A Theory of Constitutional Rights: firstly, when discussing the impossibility of deriving solutions from legal norms by means of techniques that are intended to be exclusively logical and value-free; secondly, when explaining the different types of statements one can make about rights, reasons for rights, and enforcement of rights.

  15. 15.

    Rümelin and Schoch (1948), p. 176.

  16. 16.

    Bomhoff (2010), p. 123. Cf. Currie (1994, p. 179), according to whom it is doubtful that balancing had then a majority position among judges.

  17. 17.

    Smend (1928), pp. 51–53.

  18. 18.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 98.

  19. 19.

    Ibid., pp. 98, 105–106; and Pulido (2013), p. 492, refer to Krauss (1955), as the pioneering work on proportionality in the narrow sense.

  20. 20.

    von Krauss (1955), p. 25, translated in Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 106.

  21. 21.

    Lerche (1999), pp. 19–23. See the reference to Krauss in the footnote 1 at 19.

  22. 22.

    See Bomhoff (2010), pp. 123–124; Grimm (2007), pp. 385–386; Grabitz (1973), pp. 569, footnote 1.

  23. 23.

    BVerfG, 1 BVerfGE 167, Judgment of 20 March 1952, at 178.

  24. 24.

    BVerfG, 3 BVerfGE 383, Judgment of 6 March 1954 at 399.

  25. 25.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Lüth Case, 7 BVerfGE 198, Judgment of 15 January 1958.

  26. 26.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Pharmacy Case, 7 BVerfGE 377, Judgment of 6 November 1958.

  27. 27.

    See e.g., Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 60–61, 448–457, 461, 500, 503, 507–508; Currie (1994), pp. 181–188.

  28. 28.

    Alexy (2003a), pp. 131, 134; Bomhoff (2013), p. 72; Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 442.

  29. 29.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Lüth Case, 7 BVerfGE 198, Judgment of 15 January 1958, translated by Tony Weir, in the website of the University of Texas School of Law.

  30. 30.

    Ibid.

  31. 31.

    BVerfG (First Senate), 7 BVerfGE 230, Judgment of 15 January 1958, p. 234. See Bomhoff (2013), pp. 79–80, for more on the case.

  32. 32.

    BVerfG, Blinkfüer Case, 25 BVerfGE 256, Judgment of 26 February 1969.

  33. 33.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Pharmacy Case, 7 BVerfGE 377, Judgment of 6 November 1958. See Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 108; (2010), p. 138; Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 659, 670–672; Currie (1994), pp. 300–301; Grimm (2007), p. 385; Pulido (2013), pp. 495–496, commenting on the Pharmacy Case.

  34. 34.

    Grundgesetz für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Article 12 (1): “All Germans shall have the right freely to choose their occupation or profession, their place of work and their place of training. The practice of an occupation or profession may be regulated by or pursuant to a law.”.

  35. 35.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Pharmacy Case, 7 BVerfGE 377, Judgment of 6 November 1958, p. 377, translated in the website of the University of Texas School of Law.

  36. 36.

    Ibid.

  37. 37.

    Ibid., p. 404.

  38. 38.

    Ibid., p. 405.

  39. 39.

    BVerfG, Medical Insurance Case I, 11 BVerfGE 30, Judgment of 23 March 1960, pp. 42, 45.

  40. 40.

    BVerfG, 13 BVerfGE 97, Judgment of 17 July 1961, p. at 104. The cases are mentioned by Grimm (2007), p. 385.

  41. 41.

    BVerfG, Spinal Tap Case, 16 BVerfGE 194, Judgment of 6 October 1963, pp. 201–203. Kommers named the decision ‘Spinal Tap Case’ and commented on it in Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 418–419. See Grimm (2007), p. 385; and Pulido (2013), pp. 495–496, for analyses of the case.

  42. 42.

    BVerfG, Pneumoencephalography Case, 17 BVerfGE 108, Judgment of 25 July 1963. The name was given in Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 419.

  43. 43.

    It is beyond my scope here to exhaust the BVerfG’s case law on conflicts related to freedom of speech. The cases below were selected due to their remarkable contribution for the development of the proportionality analysis in general and balancing in particular, and yet, the selection could have included many others, as the BVerfG, Lebach Case, 35 BVerfGE 202, Judgment of 6 May 1973, for instance. See Michael (2001), pp. 654–659, for more decisions of the BVerfG on freedom of speech and other subject-matters that made reference to proportionality or one of its subtests—suitability, necessity, and balancing.

  44. 44.

    BVerfG, Schmid-Spiegel Case/Volga Artikel Case, 12 BVerfGE 113, Judgment of 25 January 1961. For more comments on the case, see Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 453–454, 464–465, 476, 498; Bomhoff (2013), p. 80; Currie (1994), pp. 190–192.

  45. 45.

    BVerfG, Schmid-Spiegel Case/Volga Artikel Case, 12 BVerfGE 113, Judgment of 25 January 1961, translated in (1998), pp. 26–27.

  46. 46.

    BVerfG, Spiegel Case, 20 BVerfGE 162, Judgment of 8 May 1966. For more on the case, see: Bomhoff (2013), pp. 83–84; Bernstein (1967), pp. 547–561.

  47. 47.

    Bomhoff (2013), p. 84. In this respect, see also Bernstein (1967).

  48. 48.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Mephisto Case, 30 BVerfGE 173, Judgment of 24 February 1971. For more on the case, see Currie (1994), pp. 192–198; Quint (1989), pp. 290–318.

  49. 49.

    Grundgesetz, Article 5 (2).

  50. 50.

    Quint (1989), pp. 313, footnote 209. In the same passage Quint speaks of ‘imperialism of balancing.’.

  51. 51.

    Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 461.

  52. 52.

    BVerfG (First Senate), Mephisto Case, 30 BVerfGE 173, Judgment of 24 February 1971, p. 197, translated by J. A. Weir, in the website of the University of Texas School of Law.

  53. 53.

    BVerfG, Deutschland Magazine Case, 42 BVerfGE 143, Judgment of 5 November 1976. For comments on the case, see Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 461, 484–485; Quint (1989), pp. 318–330.

  54. 54.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 418.

  55. 55.

    BVerfG, Deutschland Magazine Case, 42 BVerfGE 143, Judgment of 5 November 1976, p. 148 (my translation).

  56. 56.

    Ibid., p. 148 (my translation).

  57. 57.

    Ibid., pp. 148–149, translated in Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 462.

  58. 58.

    Ibid., p. 149 (my translation).

  59. 59.

    BVerfG, 48 BVerfGE 396, Judgment of 20 June 1978, p. 402, translated in Schwarze (1992), p. 687. On the ‘uncertainty’ sourrounding the court’s early case law on proportionality, see Scharpf (1966), pp. 686–687; Hirschberg (1981), p. 23 ff.

  60. 60.

    BVerfG, 61 BVerfGE 126, Judgment of 19 October 1982, p. 135, translated in Schwarze (1992), p. 688.

  61. 61.

    BVerfG, Hashish Drug Case/Cannabis Judgement, 90 BVerfGE 145, Judgment of 3 September 1994. Concerning the case’s name, whereas Grimm (2007), p. 388, and Sullivan and Frase (2009), p. 29, call it the ‘Cannabis Case’, Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 399, refers to it as the ‘Hashish Drug Case’.

  62. 62.

    BVerfG, Hashish Drug Case/Cannabis Judgement, 90 BVerfGE 145, Judgment of 3 September 1994, p. 172.

  63. 63.

    Ibid., p. 171.

  64. 64.

    Ibid., p. 171.

  65. 65.

    Ibid., p. 172.

  66. 66.

    Ibid. See Bilchitz (2014), p. 43 ff., for an analysis of the concept of necessity that he derives from the Cannabis Case.

  67. 67.

    Ibid., p. 146. The case also raised issues about the intensity of review the BVerfG ought to perform. See in Chap. 6.

  68. 68.

    Kumm (2007), p. 141; (2004a), pp. 582–584; Cremer (2014), pp. 59–62; Borowski (2011), pp. 581–582.

  69. 69.

    See Kumm (2007), p. 141, mentioning these and other decisions.

  70. 70.

    Baer (1998), pp. 258–267; Borowski (2011), pp. 582–583. Social rights are discussed in Chap. 7 below.

  71. 71.

    BVerfG, Tax-Free Subsistence Minimum Case, 82 BVerfGE 60, Judgment of 29 May 1990, p. 85, translated in Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 623. Proportionality is mentioned in the case at 101.

  72. 72.

    Petersen (2015), p. 57; Sweet and Mathews (2010), p. 138; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 285.

  73. 73.

    It is worth noting that Petersen (2015), p. 69, focused on decisions concerning freedom rights only.

  74. 74.

    Ibid., p. 59.

  75. 75.

    Ibid., p. 64. A more favourable political environment, due to the reduced governmental pressure over the decades, along with the goodwill and credibility the BVerfG gained among citizenry and political parties, may be a reason for the shift of focus towards balancing. See in this respect, Kommers (1976), pp. 255–303; Baldus (2005), pp. 237–248; Lembcke (2006), pp. 151–161; Häußler (1994), pp. 22–74; and Vorländer and Brodocz (2006), pp. 259–294.

  76. 76.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), pp. 380–381, speak of a “weighty influence of German constitutional law” on Europe and the Western world in general. Particularly about the influence of the principles theory on European law, see Menéndez (2004), pp. 159–199.

  77. 77.

    Kühling (2006), p. 535 ff.

  78. 78.

    See Sweet (2000), pp. 163–178, on the relationship between the ECJ and national courts of the member states in general; and Petersen (2009), p. 21; Mayer (2006), p. 295 ff.; Garlicki (2008), p. 518, on what they call a ‘paradigm of cooperation’ among courts.

  79. 79.

    Schwarze (1992), p. 692 and 696, respectively, gives some examples, two of which are worth mentioning: Italy and United Kingdom. Respecting the former, Schwarze says, “in Italy, the proportionality principle has come to prominence under this designation only as a result of the case law developed by the European Court of Justice;” concerning the latter, “under the influence of European Community Law, in particular the case law of the ECJ, the proportionality principle has recently been introduced into English law.” Similarly, according to Cohn (2010), p. 585, the pre-existing method for invalidating administrative action in the U.K., unreasonabless review, “was transformed in the late 1980 s to accommodate pressure from Strasbourg,” and proportionality was then “transposed onto British law under British obligations under European Community law.” See also Rivers (2004), pp. 148–163.

  80. 80.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 146 ff.; Schwarze (1992), p. 705. A candidate for the post of the earliest case the ECtHR decided by resort to proportionality is Handyside v. the United Kingdom, App. No. 5493/72, Judgment of 1976, 1 Eur. H.R. Rep. (ser. A, No. 24) 737. It is nevertheless disputable whether this was really the first time the court had recourse to the test. See in this respect, Eissen (1993), p. 126.

  81. 81.

    Pulido (2013), p. 497. See also Zhordania T (2012). The problems relating to the margin of appreciation doctrine under the European convention on human rights. Europa-Kolleg, Institute for European Integration, p. 15 ff.; Greer (2000), p. 20; (2003), p. 409 ff.; McBride (1999), pp. 23–36; Letsas (2006), p. 711 ff.; Arai (2002), pp. 14 ff., 186 ff.; Matscher (1993), pp. 63–81; Gerards and Senden (2009), p. 645. The relevance proportionality has assumed in the ECtHR’s case law led Letsas (2006), p. 711, to comment: ‘the principle … is by far the most important and most demanding criterion for whether the limitation of a right was permissible under the [European] Convention [of Human Rights].’.

  82. 82.

    There is no consensus about which decision was the first to refer to proportionality in the ECJ’s case law. While some authors regard the Case 11/70 as having inaugurated a line of judgments by resort to proportionality, Schwarze (1992), p. 677, says that the ECJ already had recourse to proportionality before 1970, but the “principle made … an occasional and insubstantial appearance” then and “has acquired an extremely important role in the judicial review of administrative decisions and rules since 1970.”.

  83. 83.

    Sweet and Mathews (2010), p. 107. See also Jans (2000), p. 240; and de Búrca (1993), pp. 105–150.

  84. 84.

    Case 11/70, Internationale Handelsgesellschaft mbH v. Einfuhr- und Vorratsstelle für Getreide und Futtermittel, Judgment of 29 January 1970, 1970 E.C.R. 1125. For comments, see Hartley (2003), p. 152; Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 140; Barak (2012a, b), p. 185; Schwarze (1992), pp. 708–709.

  85. 85.

    Jans (2000), pp. 240, footnote 3.

  86. 86.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), pp. 140–141; Schwarze (1992), pp. 726–853; Tridimas (1996), pp. 98–99.

  87. 87.

    Treaty on European Union [TEU], Article 5 (1).

  88. 88.

    Walker (2010), p. 279.

  89. 89.

    Zweigert and Kötz (1998), p. 34, observe that the functionalist approach has been for long deemed as the dominant and “basic” method of analysis in comparative constitutional law, although subjected to severe criticism as well. Generally speaking, scholars conducting functionalist inquiries “identify one or more functions performed by constitutions or constitutional institutions or doctrines in some societies, and analyse whether and how that function is performed elsewhere,” Jackson (2012), p. 62, says. Another possibility is that comparatists employ this method to discover problems shared by different legal systems and compare how each of them attempted to circumvent or solve the same issues, Michaels (2006), p. 346, notices. See Tushnet (1999), pp. 1238–1269, for an account of functionalism as serving not as a method for scholars, but for courts seeking for answers in foreign legal systems.

  90. 90.

    For a definition of ‘transmissibility,’ see Wise (1990), p. 17.

  91. 91.

    McWhinney (1986), p. xiii; Miller (2003), p. 845.

  92. 92.

    Perju (2012a), pp. 335–337; Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 83; Pavlakos (2014), p. 107.

  93. 93.

    Barak (2012a, b), p. 749; Beatty (2004), p. 162; Schlink (2011), p. 302; Sweet and Mathews (2008), pp. 88, 89.

  94. 94.

    Annus (2004), p. 304; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2011), p. 466; Perju (2012b), p. 1318.

  95. 95.

    Luhmann (2009), p. 144; Schauer (2005a), pp. 49–69; (2005b), pp. 29–56; Tremblay (2014), p. 887.

  96. 96.

    Sadurski (2009), pp. 136–137; Sweet and Mathews (2008), pp. 88–89.

  97. 97.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2011), p. 466.

  98. 98.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 263; (2013a, b), pp. 134–135. For more on the reputation-building function of legal borrowings and migrations motivated by the prominence of the foreign system, court, or academic work from which the object was taken, see Graziadei (2006), p. 456; Choudhry (1999), p. 888; Epstein and Knight (2003), p. 210; Law (2008), pp. 1343–1349; Schauer (2000), pp. 11–18; Smits (2006), p. 531; Rosenkrantz (2003), p. 269 ff.; Perju (2010), pp. 348–349; Slaughter (1999), pp. 120–123; Watson (1974), pp. 51–52, 88–94; (1978), p. 327. Miller (2003), p. 854, explains that developing countries like Brazil often emulate constitutional models from the U.S. and Europe in support of their institutional arrangements, which would lack legitimacy otherwise.

  99. 99.

    For more on the contextualist approach, see Jackson (2012), p. 67; McWhinney (1986), vi (foreword). In which concerns the historical approach, since Watson’s seminal work, historically based analysis has been a common method for explaining constitutional migrations and borrowings. See Watson (1974), p. 7, arguing that comparative law approximates to legal history; and Gordley (2006), pp. 754–775, discussing the role of legal history in comparative legal studies.

  100. 100.

    Ackerman (1997), pp. 778, 795–796; Beatty (2004), pp. 2–3; Schlink (2011), p. 301. C.f. Robertson (2010), pp. 29–30, according to whom the explanation for borrowing proportionality does not have to lie in something of impact such as democratization after a violent dictatorship. Canada, for example, has adopted a variant of the test without having faced such a dramatic break in policy—although it is true that the Canadian Charter of Rights represented “a dramatic break from an English-style history of parliamentary supremacy.” Furthermore, he says, if a transition in the political regime was sufficient explanation for the new principle-based approach on rights, “the Italian Constitutional Court should have been as effective as the German court, for they were created at roughly the same time in very similar historical contexts.” Differently from what has been observed in Germany, however, constitutional review has been regarded as “half-hearted and limited” in Italy, he observes.

  101. 101.

    See, for instance, Weinrib (2006) and Chap. 6 below; Hirschl (2007).

  102. 102.

    See Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 87, and Chap. 6 below.

  103. 103.

    See Vieira (2008), pp. 447–450, and Chap. 6 below.

  104. 104.

    Daly (2014), p. 8.

  105. 105.

    Ibid., pp. 7–8.

  106. 106.

    Freire, p. 5. See Martins (2003), pp. 20–21, on the reception of proportionality in Portugal, which he qualifies as “partial and insufficient.”.

  107. 107.

    Sarlet (2009), p. 74; Daly (2014), pp. 7–8; Rosenn (2010), p. 443; Neves (2013), p. 113.

  108. 108.

    Cittadino (2009), pp. 41–43, 60–64. Actually, the Federal Senate provided the members of the constitutional assembly with a compilation of translated constitutions from “more than thirty-six countries, including Germany, Italy, Japan, Spain, and the United States.” [Rosenn (2010), p. 443]. As a result, clauses of the Federal Constitution entirely reproduce the text of their foreign equivalents.

  109. 109.

    Canotilho (1981); Canotilho (1982).

  110. 110.

    Verdú (1984).

  111. 111.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2009), pp. 387–395; (2011), p. 103; (2013a, b), pp. 46–49. See Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 46, 353, discussing the influence of communitarianism on the Basic Law and German philosophical tradition that draws “no clear distinction between state and society,” which has supported the state’s deeply commitment “to an objective order of values.”.

  112. 112.

    Cittadino (2009), p. 43.

  113. 113.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2013a, b), p. 103.

  114. 114.

    Mureinik (1994), p. 32; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), pp. 272–275; (2011), pp. 485–486; (2013a, b), pp. 5–7, p. 103; Kumm (2009), p. 8; Dyzenhaus (1998), pp. 35–36; Gardbaum (2014), pp. 261–266.

  115. 115.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 85 ff.; Weinrib (2006), p. 89 ff.

  116. 116.

    Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2013a, b), p. 122.

  117. 117.

    Ibid., pp. 139–148.

  118. 118.

    Beatty (2004), p. 162.

  119. 119.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 20. See also Alexy (2003a), p. 131, referring to balancing as “indispensable.”.

  120. 120.

    Alexy (2003a), p. 136.

  121. 121.

    In fact, not all constitutions textually provide for the proportionality test as an adjudicative method—only a minority of constitutions actually do—, nor do data support the belief that all courts across the world engage in some kind of proportionality analysis. Beatty (2004), for example, has only devoted close attention to examples from Germany, Canada, Israel, South Africa, Japan, Hungary, Australia, and the European Court of Human Rights. As Posner (2005), p. 301, correctly pointed out, “Beatty cites decisions from only 15 of [the world’s] 193 nations (plus decisions of one United Nations and two European tribunals), and 11 of the 15 are former British possessions. His sample of world judicial opinion, therefore, is hardly representative. He has not demonstrated that ‘proportionality’ is a universal legal norm.”.

  122. 122.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 14; (2010b), p. 228.

  123. 123.

    Markesinis and Fedtke (2005), pp. 16–17.

  124. 124.

    See an example in Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 374. The authors analysed the legal treatment that Germany and the U.S. gave to abortion. They compared the provisions in the Basic Law and the U.S. Constitution, and the different conclusions to which the BVerfG and the U.S. Supreme Court arrived at in the Abortion Case I and Roe v. Wade, respectively. The BVerfG ruled in the Abortion Case I that “the state has a constitutional duty to protect the life of the unborn child, and must criminalize abortion” [39 BVerfGE 1, Judgment of 25 February 1975, translated in Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 374–383]. The U.S. Supreme Court held in Roe v. Wade that “the right to choose an abortion is within a woman’s fundamental right of privacy, invalidating a state law that criminalized abortion.” (410 U.S. 113, Judgment of 1973). Kommers (1997), p. 689, observed that the German judgment “stands in sharp contrast to the doctrinal analysis contained in the seminal American case,” although “there [was] nothing inexorable” about abortion in either German or American authoritative legal material. A conclusion is that, unless for the difference in each court’s understanding, both decisions “might have gone the other way.”.

  125. 125.

    Kokott (1999), p. 77.

  126. 126.

    Barak (2012a, b), pp. 200–201.

  127. 127.

    Kokott (1999), p. 77.

  128. 128.

    Sarlet (2009), p. 74.

  129. 129.

    Rosenn (2010), p. 443.

  130. 130.

    Daly (2014), p. 15. See also Gonçalves (2012), pp. 22–25, in this respect; and Dammann (2002), p. 521, on “authority-based comparisions.”.

  131. 131.

    Kleinheisterkamp (2006), p. 299.

  132. 132.

    The expression was taken from Ferreira and Fernandes (2013); Mariano Silva (2016).

  133. 133.

    Herzog (2013), p. 174 (my translation).

  134. 134.

    Ibid., pp. 174, 182–183.

  135. 135.

    Neves (2013), p. 113.

  136. 136.

    Montoro (1973), p. 4. Accordingly, Benvindo (2010), p. 380, noticed that, in some judgements, the STF seemly implies that it performs its destiny by appropriating from the principles theory and German proportionality, as if “this new approach was the consequence of the irreversible evolution of Brazilian democracy.”.

  137. 137.

    STF, Ellwanger Case, HC 82424/RS, Judgment of 17 September 2003, Relator (acórdão): Min. Maurício Corrêa, D.J. 10 Mar. 2004. The judgement was controversial in the view of da Silva (2013), p. 572, e.g. For in-depth analyses of the case, see Benvindo (2010), pp. 19–29, 298–404; and Freire (2007), pp. 9–10.

  138. 138.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 5, XLII: “the practice of racism is a non-bailable crime, with no limitation, subject to the penalty of confinement, under the terms of the law.” All the translations of the Federal Constitution hereinafter are taken from Chamber of Deputies (2010), unless indicated otherwise.

  139. 139.

    STF, Ellwanger Case, HC 82424/RS, Judgment of 17 September 2003, Relator (acórdão): Min. Maurício Corrêa, D.J. 10 Mar. 2004 (my translation).

  140. 140.

    Ibid.

  141. 141.

    Ibid.

  142. 142.

    Klatt (2012), p. 7.

  143. 143.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 85.

  144. 144.

    Rivers (2010), xvii, says that the Human Rights Act, 1998, c. 42 (Eng.), is now “the prima locus of constitutional rights in the United Kingdom.” Concerning Israel, the rights are listed in the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty (5752-1992), S.H. 1391; and the Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation (5754-1994), S.H. 1454, 90. According to Barak (2007), p. 370, Israeli courts have been interpreting the “Basic Law: Human Dignity and Freedom” as including the principle of proportionality. The vastly documented fact that more and more countries are adhering to a constitutionalist model that favours judicial review led Shinar (2014), p. 195, to sarcastically ask: “if non-constitutionalist regimes are so great, why are countries getting rid of them?”.

  145. 145.

    Weinrib (2006), p. 84 ff.

  146. 146.

    Navia and Ríos-Figueroa (2005), pp. 191–195.

  147. 147.

    McWhinney (1986), pp. 23–34.

  148. 148.

    The mitigated filiation to civil-law traditions is also discernible in the authority given to some courts’ decisions. de Bustamante (2007), p. 293, points out that Brazil is a ‘qualified civil-law country’ because “there is a corpus of formally binding decisions from the Supreme Federal Court, the Higher Electoral Court, and the Higher Labour Court. The authority of such decisions derives from statutory law itself, and neither from a practice nor from the naked authority of the judge, as expounded in the most persuasive accounts of Common Law doctrine.”.

  149. 149.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 95, I, and Article 101, Main Body and Sole Paragraph. See Harding and Leyland (2009), for a comparative study on appointment rules for supreme and constitutional courts from Africa, Asia, Europe, and Latin America; Comella (2009), for an European perspective; and Landfried (1988), pp. 147–151, particularly about the nomination of judges to the BVerfG.

  150. 150.

    Constituição (1988), Article 97; Regimento Interno do Supremo Tribunal Federal, Article 2, Sole Paragraph, and Articles 3 and 4.

  151. 151.

    McWhinney (1986), p. 23.

  152. 152.

    Comella (2011), p. 265. For more on specialization, see: McWhinney (1986); Michelman (2011); Comella (2009), pp. 3–9; Ginsburg (2003), pp. 9–105; Sweet (2012), pp. 817–820.

  153. 153.

    Sweet (2012), p. 818.

  154. 154.

    Ibid., p. 818.

  155. 155.

    Ferejohn and Pasquino (2003). 1682.

  156. 156.

    Comella (2011), p. 268.

  157. 157.

    Kommers and Miller (2012), p. 3.

  158. 158.

    Ibid., p. 3.

  159. 159.

    ‘If a court concludes that a law on whose validity its decision depends is unconstitutional, the proceedings shall be stayed, and a decision shall be obtained … from the Federal Constitutional Court where this Basic Law is held to be violated. This provision shall also apply where the Basic Law is held to be violated by Land law.’ (Grundgesetz für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Article 100 (1)).

  160. 160.

    On the differences between concrete and abstract judicial review, see: Sadurski (2005), pp. 65–74; Sweet (2012), p. 823; concerning the jurisdiction of both German Federal Constitutional Court and the United States Supreme Court, see: Kommers and Miller (2012), pp. 13–15.

  161. 161.

    In the Brazilian legal system, a ‘writ of security’ is the suitable lawsuit to be filed by an applicant who claims for protection against illegal actions and abuse of power, whenever the party responsible for the abusive act is a public officer or an agent of a governmental entity, and since the violated right is not protected by other constitutional actions—namely, habeas corpus and habeas data. Although the writ of security has been commonly translated as ‘writ of mandamus,’ the two terms are not equivalents. In Brazilian law, the writ of security is the appropriate action for situations in which petitions of writs other than the mandamus would be suitable in the Anglo-American system—especially, the writs of certiorari and injunction. Because of this, I have opted for a literal translation from the Portuguese ‘mandado de segurança.’ For more details, see: Marchant (1945); Rosenn (2011), pp. 19–23; Meirelles et al. (2013).

  162. 162.

    Constituição da República Federativa do Brasil de 1988, Article 102, II, III, and Paragraph 3.

  163. 163.

    Constituição (1988), Article 102, I, Paragraphs 1 and 2, and Article 103.

  164. 164.

    Constituição (1988), Article 102, I, d.

  165. 165.

    McWhinney (1986), p. 23.

  166. 166.

    da Silva (2013), p. 569.

  167. 167.

    Ibid., p. 568.

  168. 168.

    McWhinney (1986), p. 26. See Markham (2006), arguing for the anonymity of the dissents of the U.S. Supreme Court. On anonymity in the American model, see Markham, “Individually Signed Judicial Opinions,” 923–951, arguing against individually signed judicial opinions in the U.S. Supreme Court’s case law.

  169. 169.

    See in this respect, da Silva (2012), p. 16 ff.

  170. 170.

    McWhinney (1986), pp. 24–25.

  171. 171.

    Ibid., p. 23.

  172. 172.

    da Silva (2013), pp. 573, footnote 49.

  173. 173.

    Jackson and Greene (2011), p. 600.

  174. 174.

    Ibid., p. 599.

  175. 175.

    Bustamante (2007), p. 304. See Leal (2015), criticising the STF for referring to its precedents often in a too general and imprecise way.

  176. 176.

    Choudhry (2011), p. 10.

  177. 177.

    Sitaraman (2009), pp. 658–661; Walker (2010), p. 321.

  178. 178.

    Choudhry (2011), pp. 9–13. See also Alford (2004), pp. 709–710, detailing four fundamental ways in which “comparativism is inconsistent with political democracy’.”.

  179. 179.

    For an alternative approach, see Pulido (2013), p. 503 ff.

  180. 180.

    Alexy (1993), p. 176.

  181. 181.

    Ibid., p. 177.

  182. 182.

    Ibid., p. 176.

  183. 183.

    On first- or second-order normative justification for proportionality, see Gardbaum (2010), pp. 88–89.

  184. 184.

    Annus (2004), p. 313.

  185. 185.

    Gardbaum (2010), pp. 88–93.

  186. 186.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 417.

  187. 187.

    Pulido (2013), pp. 511–512.

  188. 188.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 20.

  189. 189.

    Ibid., p. 20; Beatty (2004), p. 162.

  190. 190.

    Alexy (2003a), p. 131.

  191. 191.

    Schlink (2011), p. 302.

  192. 192.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 71.

  193. 193.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 388. The identity thesis undermines the difference between the relation of proportionality to principles, on the one hand, and to fundamental rights, on the other; difference which Borowski (1998), pp. 61–63, introduced. For this reason, the present study will not endorse the division of the necessity thesis into a ‘first necessity thesis’ on the connection between principles and proportionality and a ‘second necessity thesis’ on the connection between fundamental rights and proportionality. Alexy (2014), p. 57, suggested this sub-division in reply to Borowski. C.f. Klement (2008), p. 761, objecting the identity between principles and fundamental rights.

  194. 194.

    Alexy (2012a), p. 333.

  195. 195.

    However, some authors had already identified such potential in the principles theory. See Jestaedt (2012), p. 159, affirming that ‘the doctrine of balancing … claims to be … an idea with potentially universal explanatory value’; Rivers (2010), p. xviii, saying that “from the perspective of the Theorie der Grundrechte, many of the distinguishing features of different constitutions are contingent, and transferability between systems is at least plausible”. See also Pulido (2013), p. 505 ff.; Poscher (2009), p. 443; Klatt and Meister (2013), pp. 62–63; (2014b), p. 23.

  196. 196.

    Some excerpts of the principles theory raise doubt about its universalist pretensions. For example, Alexy and Dreier (1990), p. 12: “it is an open question whether general normative statements in this sense [of universally valid statements] can be justified or whether they are always relative to the cultures the legal systems in question are based upon.” Cf. Alexy (2012a), p. 332: “the doctrine of balancing as summarized in the weight formula is the basis of a comprehensive, universal theory of fundamental rights;” and Alexy (2007a), p. 162): “courts are not only participants in a parochial enterprise where they have special authority to establish what the law actually is, they are also participants in an universalistic enterprise, where they have no special authority to decide what is legally correct.”.

  197. 197.

    For a critique of intentionalism as a method of interpretation, see Dworkin (1986), pp. 53–65.

  198. 198.

    Klatt (2012), p. 8, footnote 40.

  199. 199.

    Alexy (1989), p. 169, footnote 4.

  200. 200.

    Ibid., p. 169, footnote 4.

  201. 201.

    Alexy (2010c), pp. 3–4.

  202. 202.

    Or “a legal assertion that is true (or correct) in one legal system need not necessarily be true (or correct) in another legal system” [Golding (1963), p. 57]. Interestingly, Alexy ( 2010d), p. 289, acknowledges that authoritative issuance and social efficacy interfere with legal correctness, for he says that: “the claim to correctness [which is constitutive of legal discourse] … does not relate to whether or not the normative statement in question is absolutely rational, but rather only to whether it can be rationally justified within the framework of the valid legal order.”.

  203. 203.

    Consequently, a change in a legal concept has normative consequences. Curiously, Alexy’s theory includes an example in this respect. See the implications that arise from ‘incorporating into the concept of law the concept of validity’ in Alexy (2010c), p. 24.

  204. 204.

    See Pulido (2013), p. 483, for a similar approach.

  205. 205.

    Borowski (2011), p. 588.

  206. 206.

    Bomhoff (2008), pp. 573, 575.

  207. 207.

    Alexy (2004), p. 47.

  208. 208.

    Alexy (1992a), pp. 149–151; (2000), p. 298; (2003a), p. 131 ff.; (2003b), pp. 433–439; (2004), pp. 46–50; (2009), pp. 8–11; (2010b), pp. 26–32; Klatt (2012), p. 10. See also Beatty (2004), p. 169.

  209. 209.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 74.

  210. 210.

    See Habermas (1996), pp. 258–259; Schlink (2001), p. 460; Webber (2013), pp. 3–4; (2010), pp. 194–198; Torre (2004), pp. 84–88, for examples of this kind of criticism; and Alexy (2014), p. 63, referring to this as the ‘rationality objection’.

  211. 211.

    Or as ‘rational as possible.’ [Alexy and Peczenik (1990), pp. 145–146].

  212. 212.

    See Schlink (1995), p. 1237, on the critique that ‘constitutional legal scholarship’ was “still overwhelmed by the Court’s [BVerfG] presence, even after its forty-year existence.”

  213. 213.

    Alexy (2010c), pp. 35–68.

  214. 214.

    Dworkin (1986), p. 99.

  215. 215.

    See, for instance, Habermas (1996), p. 259, saying that “there are no rational standards for … weighing,” but not that judgements by resort to proportionality are irremediably and necessarily irrational. Rather, in his view, “the danger of irrational rulings increases” as a consequence.

  216. 216.

    See Greer (2004), p. 433, lamenting that “the balance metaphor has been used by the European Court of Human Rights in ways which would, prima facie, confirm Habermas’s worst fears,” but conceding that, “subject to certain modifications, Alexy’s theory can, nevertheless, be applied to its judgments.”

  217. 217.

    Alexy (2007b), p. 14.

  218. 218.

    On the U.S. categorization, see Barak (2012a, b), pp. 752–754, and Chap. 4 below.

  219. 219.

    Alexy and Dreier (1990), p. 3.

  220. 220.

    Bomhoff (2008), pp. 576–578.

  221. 221.

    Alexy (2012a), p. 352.

  222. 222.

    Alexy (2007c), p. 341.

  223. 223.

    For instance, Lafont (2012), pp. 294–297.

  224. 224.

    Eriksen (2004), p. 103.

  225. 225.

    Alexy (2004), p. 38.

  226. 226.

    Ibid., pp. 42–43. On conceptions of substantive justice that underlie the idea of procedural justice, see Gargarella (2012), p. 336 ff.

  227. 227.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 417.

  228. 228.

    Alexy (2004), p. 38.

  229. 229.

    Alexy (2012b), p. 289.

  230. 230.

    Alexy (1992b), p. 238; (2012b), pp. 290–291.

  231. 231.

    Alexy (2010e) p. 177.

  232. 232.

    Kumm (2004b), pp. 222–224, 228–233.

  233. 233.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 66.

  234. 234.

    Ibid., p. 47. For more details about Alexy’s conception of principles as optimization requirements, see Chap. 4 below.

  235. 235.

    Alexy (2000), pp. 300–301.

  236. 236.

    See e.g., Alexy (1992a), p. 148, arguing that “fundamental rights should be furthered by legal practice.”

  237. 237.

    See Alexy (2010a), pp. 210–217, on the wide-scope conception of fundamental rights; Alexy (2005), p. 572, on argumentative representation.

  238. 238.

    Alexy (2014), pp. 58, 63.

  239. 239.

    Alexy (2010b), p. 20.

  240. 240.

    Alexy (2012a), p. 329.

  241. 241.

    Ibid., p. 333.

  242. 242.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 388.

  243. 243.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 71.

  244. 244.

    Choudhry (1999), p. 836. It is noteworthy that the dialogical approach was originally conceived of as a method that comparative constitutional scholars can adopt for studying judicial borrowings, while here the dialogical interpretation is intended to provide judges with justification for borrowing.

  245. 245.

    Ibid., p. 836.

  246. 246.

    Ibid., p. 858.

  247. 247.

    Alexy (1993), p. 177. See also Alexy (2014), p. 62.

  248. 248.

    Aarnio et al. (1981), p. 275.

  249. 249.

    See Alexy (2014), p. 61, on the ‘positivity thesis’ about the connection between proportionality and fundamental rights.

  250. 250.

    Gonçalves (2012), p. 25.

  251. 251.

    Alexy (2014), pp. 60–61.

  252. 252.

    In this sense, I agree with Beatty (2004), p. 176: “for the judges, proportionality is grounded in the word and structure and purposes of constitutional texts, not in the jurisprudence they write.” Nonetheless, differently from what he concluded, it does not follow from this that “proportionality is a constitutive, immutable part of every constitution.”.

  253. 253.

    See McWhinney (1986), pp. xiii–xiv, speaking of “indigenous precursors,” rooted in the influenced country’s “own special, indigenous constitutional and general legal history”.

  254. 254.

    Sweet and Mathews (2008), p. 118.

  255. 255.

    Ibid., p. 118.

  256. 256.

    Davis (2003), pp. 187–190; Gardbaum (2011), p. 390.

  257. 257.

    The requirement of a corresponding legal permission or command is a consequence of being the judge ‘legally bound even in the open area of the positive (issued and efficacious) law.’ [Alexy (2010c), p. 69].

  258. 258.

    Reference is made here to Dworkin (1986), p. 220.

  259. 259.

    This is a conclusion that one can derive from Alexy (2010c), pp. 35–68.

  260. 260.

    Ibid., pp. 62–68.

  261. 261.

    Comparative constitutional lawyers have documented that “borrowing often feeds on itself” [Wise (1990), p. 17]. That is the case if a court “[feels] especially compelled to follow foreign interpretation of [a] statute or constitution” that had migrated from a foreign legal system in the past [Annus (2004), p. 335]. The court responsible for the interpretation of a borrowed clause may “look to the ‘parent’ constitution and its interpretation in resolving constitutional problems.”.

  262. 262.

    Barak (2012a, b), pp. 200–201; Martins (2003), pp. 20–21.

  263. 263.

    Cittadino (2009), p. 43.

  264. 264.

    On constitutional culture, see Goldsworthy (2012), p. 683 ff.; Schlink (1992), p. 711 ff. C.f. Perju (2010), pp. 343–344, on the concept of “constitutional imaginary;” and Jacobsohn (2011), p. 129 ff., on “constitutional identity.”.

  265. 265.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 66, p. 333; (2010b), p. 24.

  266. 266.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 388.

  267. 267.

    Alexy (2010c), p. 71.

  268. 268.

    Alexy (2010a), p. 73.

References

  • Aarnio A, Alexy R, Peczenik A (1981) The foundation of legal reasoning. In: Rechtstheorie: Zeitschrift für Logik und juristische Methodenlehre, Rechtsinformatik, Kommunikationsforschung, Normen- und Handlungstheorie, Soziologie und Philosophie des Rechts, 12th edn. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, pp 133–158, 257–279, 423–448

    Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman B (1997) The rise of world constitutionalism. Va Law Rev 83(4):771–797. https://doi.org/10.2307/1073748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1989) On necessary relations between law and morality. Ratio Juris 2(2):167–183. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1989.tb00035.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1992a) A discourse-theoretical conception of practical reason. Ratio Juris 5(3):231–251. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1992.tb00127.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1992b) Rights, legal reasoning and rational discourse. Ratio Juris 5(2):143–152. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1992.tb00121.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1993) Legal argumentation as rational discourse. Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia Del Diritto 70:165–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2000) On the structure of legal principles. Ratio Juris 13(3):294–304. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9337.00157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003a) Constitutional rights, balancing, and rationality. Ratio Juris 16(2):131–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003b) On balancing and subsumption. Struct Comp Ratio Juris 16(4):433–449. https://doi.org/10.1046/j.0952-1917.2003.00244.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (2004). Discourse theory and fundamental rights. In Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 35–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2005) Balancing, constitutional review, and representation. Int J Const Law 3(4):572–581. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moi040

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2007a) On two juxtapositions: concept and nature, law and philosophy. some comments on Joseph Raz’s “Can there be a theory of law?”. Ratio Juris 20(2):162–169. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2007.00353.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2007b) The weight formula. In: Stelmach J, Brożek B, Zaluski W (eds) Paulson SL, Brożek B (Trans) Frontiers of the economic analysis of law, vol 3. Jagiellonian Univ. Press, Kraków, pp 9–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2007c) Thirteen replies. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse: the legal philosophy of Robert Alexy. Hart Pub, Oxford; Portland, Or

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2009) The reasonableness of law. In: Bongiovanni G, Sartor G, Valentini C (eds) Reasonableness and law. Springer, Dordrecht, New York, pp 5–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010a) A theory of constitutional rights (Rivers J, Trans). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010b) The construction of constitutional rights. Law Eth Hum Rights 4(1):21–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010c) The argument from injustice: a reply to legal positivism. (Paulson SL, Paulson BL, Trans.). Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010d) A theory of legal argumentation: the theory of rational discourse as theory of legal justification. (Adler R, MacCormic N, Trans.). Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010e) The dual nature of law. Ratio Juris 23(2):167–182. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2010.00449.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2012a) Comments and responses. In: Klatt M (ed) Institutionalized reason : the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2012b) Rights and liberties as concepts. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 283–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2014) Constitutional Rights and Proportionality. Revus Revija Za Ustavno Teorijo in Filozofijo Prava/J Const Theory Phil Law 22:51–65. https://doi.org/10.4000/revus.2783

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R, Dreier R (1990) The concept of jurisprudence. Ratio Juris 3(1):1–13. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1990.tb00047.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R, Peczenik A (1990) The concept of coherence and its significance for discursive rationality. Ratio Juris 3(S1):130–147. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.1990.tb00076.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alford RP (2004) In search of a theory for constitutional comparativism. UCLA Law Rev 52:639–714

    Google Scholar 

  • Annus T (2004) Comparative constitutional reasoning: the law and strategy of selecting the right arguments. Duke J Comp Int Law 14(2):301–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Arai Y (2002) The margin of appreciation doctrine and the principle of proportionality in the jurisprudence of the ECHR. Intersentia, Antwerp, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Baer S (1998) Equality: the jurisprudence of the German constitutional court. Colum J Eur L 5:249–279

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldus M (2005) Frühe Machtkämpfe. Ein Versuch über die historischen Gründe der Autorität des Bundesverfassungsgericht. In: Henne T, Riedlinger A (eds) Das Lüth-Urteil aus (rechts-)historischer Sicht: die Konflikte um Veit Harlan und die Grundrechtsjudikatur des Bundesverfassungsgerichts (1. Aufl). BWV, Berliner Wissenschafts-Verlag, Berlin, pp 237–248

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2007) Proportional effect: the Israeli experience. Univ Tor Law J 57(2):369–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2010) Proportionality and principled balancing. Law Eth Hum Rights 4(1):1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012a) Proportionality. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 738–755

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012b) Proportionality: constitutional rights and their limitations (Kalir D, Trans). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York, U.K.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty DM (2004) The ultimate rule of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benvindo JZ (2010) On the limits of constitutional adjudication—deconstructing balancing and judicial activism. Springer, Berlin, London. Retrieved from http://www.springer.com/law/book/978-3-642-11433-5

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein H (1967) West Germany: free press and national security. Reflections on the spiegel case. Am J Comp Law 15(3):547–561

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bilchitz D (2014) Necessity and proportionality: towards a balanced approach? In: Lazarus L, McCrudden C, Bowles N (eds) Reasoning rights: comparative judicial engagement. Hart Publishing, Oxford, Portland, Oregon, pp 41–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2008) Balancing, the global and the local: judicial balancing as a problematic topic in Comparative (Constitutional) Law. Hastings Int Comp Law Rev 31(2):555–586

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2010) Genealogies of balancing as discourse. Law Eth Hum Rights 4(1):109–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Bomhoff J (2013) Balancing constitutional rights: the origins and meanings of postwar legal discourse. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (1998) Grundrechte als Prinzipien: Die Unterscheidung von Prima-facie-Position und definitiver Position als fundamentaler Konstruktionsgrundsatz der Grundrechte, 1st edn. Nomos Verl.-Ges, Baden-Baden

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2011) Discourse, principles, and the problem of law and morality: Robert Alexy’s three main works: Robert Alexy’s three main works by Martin Borowski. Jurisprudence 2(2):575–595. https://doi.org/10.5235/204033211798716899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Canotilho JJG (1982) Constituição dirigente e vinculação do legislador: contributo para a compreensão das normas constitucionais programaticas. Coimbra, Coimbra

    Google Scholar 

  • Canotilho JJG (1981) Direito constitucional, vol 2. Livr. Almedina, Coimbra

    Google Scholar 

  • Choudhry S (1999). Globalization in search of justification: toward a theory of comparative constitutional interpretation. 74 Indiana Law J 819 (1999), 74(3). Retrieved from http://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol74/iss3/4

  • Choudhry S (2011) Migration as a new metaphor in comparative constitutional law. In: Choudhry S (ed) The migration of constitutional ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Cittadino GG (2009) Pluralismo, direito e justiça distributiva: Elementos da filosofia constitucional contemporânea. Editora Lumen Juris, Rio de Janeiro

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2009) The hidden foreign law debate in Heller: the proportionality approach in American constitutional law. San Diego Law Rev 46:367–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2010) American balancing and German proportionality: the historical origins. Int J Const Law 8(2):263–286. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moq004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2011) Proportionality and the culture of justification. Am J Comp Law 59(2):463–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2013a) Proportionality and constitutional culture. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2013b) Proportionality and justification (SSRN Scholarly Paper No. ID 2205702). Social Science Research Network, Rochester, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohn EJ (1950) The jurisprudence of interests. selected writings of Max Rümelin, Philipp Heck, Paul Oertmann, Heinrich Stoll, Julius Binder, Hermann Isay by Magdalena Schoch. Mod Law Rev 13(1):117–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohn M (2010) Legal transplant chronicles: the evolution of unreasonableness and proportionality review of the administration in the United Kingdom. Am J Comp Law 58(3):583–629. https://doi.org/10.5131/ajcl.2009.0048

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comella VF (2009) Constitutional courts and democratic values: a European perspective. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Comella VF (2011) The rise of specialized constitutional courts. In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, pp 265–277

    Google Scholar 

  • Cremer W (2014) The basic right to ‘free development of the personality’: mere protection of personality development versus general right of freedom of action. In: Pünder H, Waldhoff C (eds) Debates in German public law. Bloomsbury Publishing, pp 57–74. Retrieved from http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&scope=site&db=nlebk&db=nlabk&AN=716824

  • Currie DP (1994) The constitution of the federal republic of Germany. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bustamante T da R (2007) Precedent in Brazil. In: Hondius E (ed) Precedent and the law: Reports of the XVIIth congress, International Academy of Comparative Law, Utrecht 16–22 July 2006. Bruylant, Bruxelles

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva VA (2012) Discovering the court: or, how rights awareness puts the Brazilian supreme court in the spotlight. Century’s Rev J Ration Legal Debate 1:16–20

    Google Scholar 

  • da Silva VA (2013) Deciding without deliberating. Int J Const Law 11(3):557–584. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mot019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly TG (2014) The differential openness of Brazil’s supreme federal court to external jurisprudence. In: Presented at the International Association of Constitutional Law World Congress, Oslo. Retrieved from http://www.jus.uio.no/english/research/news-and-events/events/conferences/2014/wccl-cmdc/wccl/papers/ws5/w5-daly.pdf

  • Dammann JC (2002) The role of comparative law in statutory and constitutional interpretation. St Thomas Law Rev 14:513–559

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis DM (2003) Constitutional borrowing: the influence of legal culture and local history in the reconstitution of comparative influence: the South African experience. Int J Const Law 1(2):181–195. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/1.2.181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Búrca G (1993) The principle of proportionality and its application in EC law. Yearb Eur Law 13(1):105–150. https://doi.org/10.1093/yel/13.1.105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyzenhaus D (1998) Law as justification: Etienne Mureinik’s conception of legal culture. South Afr J Hum Rights 14:11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eissen M-A (1993) The principle of proportionality in the case-law of the European court of human rights. In: Macdonald RSJ, Matscher F, Petzold H (eds) The European system for the protection of human rights. M. Nijhoff, Dordrecht, Boston, pp 125–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein L, Knight J (2003) Constitutional borrowing and nonborrowing. Int J Const Law 1(2):196–223. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/1.2.196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen EO (2004) Democratic or Jurist-made law: on the claim to correctness. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 95–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn J, Pasquino P (2003) Constitutional adjudication: lessons from Europe. Tex L Rev 82:1671

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferreira SL, Fernandes EBD (2013) O STF nas ‘Cortes’ Victor Nunes Leal, Moreira Alves e Gilmar Mendes. Revista Direito GV 9(1):23–45. https://doi.org/10.1590/S1808-24322013000100002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freire AR (2007) Evolution of constitutional interpretation in Brazil and employment of balancing “method” by the federal supreme court in judicial review. In: Workshop 15: the balancing and proportionality in the constitutional review

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardbaum S (2010) A democratic defense of constitutional balancing. Law Eth Hum Rights 4(1):79–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardbaum S (2011) The structure and scope of constitutional rights. In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, pp 387–405

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardbaum S (2014) Proportionality and democratic constitutionalism. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber GCN (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, pp 259–283

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gargarella R (2012) The constitution and justice. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 336–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Garlicki L (2008) Cooperation of courts: the role of supranational jurisdictions in Europe. Int J Const Law 6(3–4):509–530. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mon025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerards J, Senden H (2009) The structure of fundamental rights and the European Court of Human Rights. Law 7(4):619–653. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mop028

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg T (2003) Judicial review in new democracies: constitutional courts in Asian cases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Golding MP (1963) Principled judicial decision-making. Ethics 73(4):247–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy J (2012) Constitutional cultures, democracy, and unwritten principles. U Ill L Rev 683

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonçalves GL (2012) Are we aware of the current recolonisation of the south? Centuty’s Rev J Ration Legal Debate 1:22–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordley J (2006) Comparative law and legal history. In: Oxford The (ed) Handbook of comparative law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 754–775

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabitz E (1973) Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit in der Rechtsprechung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts, (98, 4), 568–616

    Google Scholar 

  • Graziadei M (2006) Comparative law as the study of transplants and receptions. In: Oxford The (ed) Handbook of comparative law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 441–475

    Google Scholar 

  • Greer SC (2000) The margin of appreciation: interpretation and discretion under the European Convention on Human Rights. Council of Europe Publishing, Strasbourg, Croton, N.Y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greer S (2003) Constitutionalizing adjudication under the European convention on human rights. Oxf J Legal Stud 23(3):405–433. https://doi.org/10.1093/ojls/23.3.405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greer SC (2004) Balancing and the European Court of Human Rights: a contribution to the Habermas-Alexy debate. Cambridge Law J 63:412–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm D (2007) Proportionality in Canadian and German constitutional jurisprudence. Univ Toronto Law J 57(2):383–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding A, Leyland P (2009) Constitutional courts: a comparative study. Wildy, Simmonds & Hill, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartley TC (2003) The foundations of European Community law: an introduction to the constitutional and administrative law of the European Community, 5th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Häußler R (1994) Der Konflikt zwischen Bundesverfassungsgericht und politischer Führung: Ein Beitrag zu Geschichte und Rechtsstellung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herzog B (2013) A interpretação e a aplicação do direito na Alemanha e no Brasil: uma análise do ponto de vista da teoria de direito comparado funcional, da teoria de direito comparado pós-moderno e da teoria dos legal transplants. In: Stefan G, Mendes GF, Marques CL, Christian B, Malheiros M (eds) Direito Privado, Constituição E Fronteiras, 2nd edn. Revista dos Tribunais, São Paulo, pp 165–193

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschberg L (1981) Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismässigkeit. Schwartz, Göttingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschl R (2007) Towards juristocracy: the origins and consequences of the new constitutionalism. Harvard University Press, London; Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson VC (2012) Comparative constitutional law: methodologies. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 54–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson VC, Greene J (2011) Constitutional interpretation in comparative law: comparing judges or courts? In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsohn GJ (2011) The formation of constitutional identities. In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, pp 129–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Jans JH (2000) Proportionality revisited. Legal Issues Econ Integr 27(3):239–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jestaedt M (2012) The Doctrine of Balancing: its strengths and weaknesses. In: Klatt M (ed) Institutionalized reason: the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (2002) Two globalizations of law & legal thought: 1850–1968. Suffolk UL Rev 36:631

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (2011) A transnational genealogy of proportionality in private law. In: Brownsword R (ed) The foundations of European private law. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon, pp 185–220. Retrieved from http://site.ebrary.com/id/10534377

  • Klatt M (2012) Robert Alexy’s philosophy of law as system. In: Institutionalized reason : the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister M (2013) Verhältinismäßigkeit als Universelles Verfassungsprinzip. Prinzipientheorie und Theorie der Abwägung. Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck, pp 62–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister M (2014a) A Máxima da Proporcionalidade: um elemento estrutural do constitucionalismo global. Observatório Da Jurisdição Constitucional, 1(Jan–Jun), 23–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister, M (2014b) Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit. Ein Strukturelement des globalen Konstitutionalismus. Juristische Schulung: Zeitschrift für Studium und Referendariat, 54(Heft 3), 193–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleinheisterkamp J (2006) Development of comparative law in Latin America. In: Zimmermann R, Reimann M (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 261–301

    Google Scholar 

  • Klement JH (2008) Vom Nutzen einer Theorie, die alles erklärt. JuristenZeitung, 63(15–16 (8)), 756–763. http://dx.doi.org/10.1628/002268808785259767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kokott J (1999) From reception and transplantation to convergence 
of constitutional models in the age of globalization: with particular reference to the German basic law. In: Starck C (ed) Constitutionalism, universalism and democracy: a comparative analysis: the German contributions to the Fifth World Congress of the International Association of Constitutional Law (1. Aufl). Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 71–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Kommers DP (1976) Judicial politics in West Germany: a study of the federal constitutional court. Sage Publications, Beverly Hills, Calif

    Google Scholar 

  • Kommers DP (1997) The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany, 2nd edn, rev. and expanded. Duke University Press, Durham, N.C

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kommers DP, Miller RA (2012) The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany, 3nd edn, rev. and expanded. Duke University Press, Durham, N.C

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kühling J (2006) Fundamental rights. In: von Bogdandy A, Bast J (eds) Principles of European constitutional law. Hart, Oxford; Portland, Or, pp 501–548

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2004a) Constitutional rights as principles: on the structure and domain of constitutional justice. A review essay on a theory of constitutional rights. Int J Const Law 2(3):574–596. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/2.3.574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2004b) Fundamental rights as principles: on the structure and domain of constitutional justice. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 201–233

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2007) Political liberalism and the structure of rights: on the place and limits of the proportionality requirement. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse: the legal philosophy of Robert Alexy. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon, pp 131–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumm M (2009) Democracy is not enough: rights, proportionality and the point of judicial review. In: NYU School of Law, (Public Law Research Paper n. 09-10). Retrieved from http://www.law.harvard.edu/faculty/faculty-workshops/kumm.paper.i.pdf

  • Lafont C (2012) Correctness and legitimacy in the discourse theory of law. In: Klatt M (ed) Institutionalized reason: the jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York, pp 291–306

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Landfried C (ed) (1988) Constitutional review and legislation in the Federal Republic of Germany. In: Constitutional review and legislation: an international comparison. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 147–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Law DS (2008) Globalization and the future of constitutional rights. Northwestern University Law Review 102(3):1277–1350

    Google Scholar 

  • Leal F (2015) Uma jurisprudência que serve para tudo. Retrieved 18 May 2015, http://www.osconstitucionalistas.com.br/uma-jurisprudencia-que-serve-para-tudo

  • Ledford KF (2004) Formalizing the rule of law in Prussia: the supreme administrative law court, 1876–1914. Cent Eur Hist 37(2):203–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lembcke O (2006) Das Bundesverfassungsgericht und die Regierung Adenauer—vom Streit um den Status zur Anerkennung der Autorität. In: van Ooyen RC, Möllers MHW (eds), Das Bundesverfassungsgericht im politischen System. VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften, Wiesbaden, pp 151–161. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/978-3-531-90289-0_11.pdf

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lerche P (1999) Übermass und Verfassungsrecht: Zur Bindung des Gesetzgebers an die Grundsätze der Verhältnismässigkeit und der Erforderlichkeit. Keip, Goldbach

    Google Scholar 

  • Letsas G (2006) Two concepts of the margin of appreciation. Oxf J Legal Stud 26(4):705–732. https://doi.org/10.1093/ojls/gql030

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann N (2009) Law as a social system. Derecho & Poder 1(1):180–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchant A (1945) Brazilian writ of security (Mandado de Segurança) and its relationship to the extraordinary remedies of the Anglo-American common law: an object lesson in Latin American law making. Tulane Law Rev 19:213

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariano Silva J (2016) Jurisdição constitucional em Espanha (1981–1992) e Brasil (1988–1997) (Doctoral thesis (political sciences)). Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro (UERJ), Rio de Janeiro. https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.1.4084.5682

  • Markesinis B, Fedtke J (2005) The judge as comparatist. Tulane Law Rev 80:11

    Google Scholar 

  • Markham J (2006) Against individually signed judicial opinions. Duke Law J 56(3):923–951

    Google Scholar 

  • Martins L (2003) Proporcionalidade Como Critério de Controle de Constitucionalidade: Problemas de Sua Recepção Pelo Direito e Jurisdição Constitucional Brasileiros. Cadernos de Direito, Editora Unimep 3(5):15–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matscher F (1993) Methods of interpretation of the convention. In: Macdonald RSJ, Matscher F, Petzold H (eds) The European system for the protection of human rights. M. Nijhoff, Dordrecht, Boston, pp 63–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer FC (2006) The European constitution and the courts. In: von Bogdandy A, Bast J (eds) Principles of European constitutional law. Hart, Oxford; Portland, Or, pp 281–334

    Google Scholar 

  • McBride J (1999) Proportionality and the European convention on human rights. In: Ellis E (ed) The principle of proportionality in the laws of Europe. Hart Pub, Oxford; Portland, Or, pp 23–36

    Google Scholar 

  • McWhinney E (1986) Supreme courts and judicial law-making: constitutional tribunals and constitutional review. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht; Lancaster, UK; Hingham, USA

    Google Scholar 

  • Meirelles HL, Wald A, Mendes GF (2013) Mandado de segurança e ações constitucionais, 35th edn. Malheiros, São Paulo

    Google Scholar 

  • Menéndez AJ (2004) Some elements of a theory of European fundamental rights. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 159–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael L (2001) Grundfälle zur Verhältnismäßigkeit. In: Juristische Schulung: Zeitschrift für Studium und Referendariat. Verlag C.H. Beck, München and Frankfurt a.M., pp 654–659

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels R (2006) The functional method of comparative law. The Oxford handbook of comparative law, pp 339–382

    Google Scholar 

  • Michelman FI (2011) The interplay of constitutional and ordinary jurisdiction. In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, pp 278–297

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller JM (2003) A typology of legal transplants: using sociology, legal history and Argentine examples to explain the transplant process. Am J Comp Law 51(4):839–885. https://doi.org/10.2307/3649131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montoro F (1973) Filosofia do direito e colonialismo cultural. Revista de informação legislativa 10(37):3–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Mureinik E (1994) A bridge to where: introducing the interim bill of rights. South Afr J Hum Rights 10:31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Navia P, Ríos-Figueroa J (2005) The constitutional adjudication mosaic of Latin America. Comp Polit Stud 38(2):189–217. https://doi.org/10.1177/0010414004271082

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neves M (2013) Transconstitutionalism. Hart Publishing, Oxford; Portland, Oregon

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavlakos G (2014) Between reason and strategy: some reflections on the normativity of proportionality. In: Huscroft G, Miller BW, Webber GCN (eds) Proportionality and the rule of law: rights, justification, reasoning. Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, pp 90–122

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Perju V (2010) Cosmopolitanism and constitutional self-government. Int J Const Law 8(3):326–353. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moq028

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perju V (2012a) Constitutional transplants, borrowing and migrations. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1304–1327

    Google Scholar 

  • Perju V (2012b) Proportionality and freedom—an essay on method in constitutional law. Global Const 1(02):334–367. https://doi.org/10.1017/S2045381712000044

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petersen N (2009) The reception of international law by constitutional courts through the prism of legitimacy. In: Preprints of the Max Planck institute for research on collective goods, vol 39. Retrieved from http://www.coll.mpg.de/pdf_dat/2009_39online.pdf

  • Petersen N (2015) Balancing and judicial self-empowerment: a case study on the rise of balancing in the jurisprudence of the German federal constitutional court. Global Const 4(01):49–80. https://doi.org/10.1017/S2045381714000173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poscher R (2009) Insights, errors and self-misconceptions of the theory of principles. Ratio Juris 22(4):425–454. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2009.00434.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA (2005) Constitutional law from a pragmatic perspective. Univ Toronto Law J 55(2):299–309. https://doi.org/10.1353/tlj.2005.0008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulido CB (2013) The migration of proportionality across Europe. New Z J Public Int Law 11(3):483–516

    Google Scholar 

  • Quint PE (1989) Free speech and private law in German constitutional theory. Maryland Law Rev 48(2):247

    Google Scholar 

  • Remmert B (1995) Verfassungs- und verwaltungsrechtsgeschichtliche Grundlagen des Übermaßverbotes. Heidelberg: Zugl.: Münster (Westfalen), Univ., Diss., 1994

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2004) Constitutional rights in the UK human rights act. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 143–158

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2010) A theory of constitutional rights and the British constitution. In: A theory of constitutional rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson D (2010) The judge as political theorist: contemporary constitutional review. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkrantz CF (2003) Against borrowings and other nonauthoritative uses of foreign law. Int J Const Law 1(2):269–295. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/1.2.269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenn KS (2010) Conflict resolution and constitutionalism: the making of the Brazilian constitution of 1988. In: Miller LE, Aucoin L (eds) Framing the state in times of transition case studies in constitution making. United States Institute of Peace, Washington, DC. Retrieved from http://www.usip.org/sites/default/files/Framing%20the%20State/Chapter16_Framing.pdf

  • Rosenn KS (2011) Procedural protection of constitutional rights in Brazil. Am J Comp Law 2011–15. Retrieved from http://ssrn.com/abstract=1829134

  • Rümelin M, Schoch MM (1948) The jurisprudence of interests: selected writings of Max Rümelin, Philipp Heck, Paul Oertmann, Heinrich Stoll, Julius Binder, Hermann Isay. Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski W (2005) Rights before courts: a study of constitutional courts in postcommunist states of Central and Eastern Europe. Springer, Dordrecht, Netherlands; Norwell, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski W (2009) Reasonableness and value pluralism in law and politics. In: Bongiovanni G, Sartor G, Valentini C (eds) Reasonableness and law, vol 86. Springer, Dordrecht, Netherlands, pp 129–146

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sarlet IW (2009) A eficácia dos direitos fundamentais: uma teoria deral dos direitos fundamentais na perspectiva constitucional. Livraria do Advogado, Porto Alegre

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartor G (2010) Doing justice to rights and values: teleological reasoning and proportionality. Artif Intell Law 18(2):175–215. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-010-9095-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scharpf FW (1966) Judicial review and the political question: a functional analysis. Yale Law J 75:517–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2000) The politics and incentives of legal transplantation. In: Nye JS, Donahue JD (eds) Governance in a globalizing world. Brookings Institution Press, Cambridge, Mass.: Washington, D.C., pp 253–268

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2005a) Freedom of expression adjudication in Europe and the United States: a case study in comparative constitutional architecture. In: Nolte G (ed) European and US constitutionalism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 49–69. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511493904.004

  • Schauer F (2005b) The exceptional first amendment. In: American exceptionalism and human rights, STU-Student edition, vols 1. Princeton University Press, Princeton; Oxford, pp 29–56. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt7skx6.4

  • Schlink B (1992) German constitutional culture in transition. Cardozo L Rev 14:711

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (1995) The dynamics of constitutional adjudication. Cardozo L Rev 17:1231

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (2001) Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit. In: Badura P, Dreier H (eds) Festschrift, 50 Jahre Bundesverfassungsgericht. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 445–465

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlink B (2011) Proportionality in constitutional law: why everywhere but here. Duke J Comp Int L 22:291–302

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarze J (1992) European administrative law. Office for Official Publications of the European Communities, Luxembourg; Sweet & Maxwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Seagle W (1945) Rudolf von Jhering: or law as a means to an end. Univ Chic Law Rev 13(1):71–89. https://doi.org/10.2307/1597562

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shinar A (2014) The end of constitutional law? Const Comment 29(2):181–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Sitaraman G (2009) The use and abuse of foreign law in constitutional interpretation. Harvard J Law Public Policy 32(2):653–693

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaughter A-M (1999) Judicial globalization. Va J Int Law 40:1103

    Google Scholar 

  • Smend R (1928) Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer: VVDStRL; 4. In: Rothenbücher K, Smend R, Heller H, Wenzel M (eds) Das Recht der freien Meinungsäusserung: Verhandlungen der Tagung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer zu München am 24. und 25. März 1927. Mit einem Auszug aus der Aussprache. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Smits JM (2006) Comparative law and its influence on national legal systems. In: Zimmermann R, Reimann M (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 513–538

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern K (1993) Zur Entstehung und Ableitung des Übermaßverbots. In: Badura P, Scholz R (eds) Wege und Verfahren des Verfassungslebens: Festschrift Peter Lerche. Beck, Munich, pp 165–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan ET, Frase RS (2009) Proportionality principles in American law: controlling excessive government actions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Svarez CG (1960) Vorträge über Recht und Staat. In: Conrad H, Kleinheyer G (eds) köln: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. Retrieved from http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:1111-201211281748

  • Sweet AS (2000) Governing with judges: constitutional politics in Europe. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS (2012) Constitutional courts. In: Rosenfeld M, Sajó A (eds) The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 816–830

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS, Mathews J (2008) Proportionality balancing and global constitutionalism. C J Trans Law 47:68–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS, Mathews J (2010) All things in proportion-American rights review and the problem of balancing. Emory L J 60:797

    Google Scholar 

  • Torre ML (2004) Nine critiques to Alexy’s theory of fundamental rights. In: Menéndez AJ, Erik OE (eds) Constitutional rights through discourse: on Robert Alexy’s legal theory-European and theoretical perspectives. Arena, Oslo, pp 77–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Tremblay LB (2014) An egalitarian defense of proportionality-based balancing. Int J Const Law 12(4):864–890. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mou060

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tridimas T (1996) The principle of proportionality in community law: from the rule of law to market integration. In: McAuley F, O’Keefe D (eds) The Irish jurist, vol XXXI. Round Hall Sweet & Maxwell; University College Dublin, Bublin, pp 83–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (1999) The possibilities of comparative constitutional law. Yale Law J 108(6):1225–1309. https://doi.org/10.2307/797327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verdú PL (1984) Curso de Derecho Político, vol 4. Ed. Tecnos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Vieira OV (2008) Supremocracia. Revista Direito GV 4(2):441–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Jhering R (1900) Scherz und Ernst in der Jurisprudenz: eine Weihnachtsgabe für das juristische Publikum, 8th edn. Breitkopf und Härtel, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krauss R (1955) Der Grundsatz der Verhältnismäßigkeit. In seiner Bedeutung für die. Notwendigkeit des Mittels im Verwaltungsrecht. Hamburg, Appel

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorländer H, Brodocz A (2006) Das Vertrauen in das Bundesverfassungsgericht. In: Vorländer H (ed) Die Deutungsmacht der Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit. VS, Verl. für Sozialwiss, Wiesbaden, pp 259–295. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-531-90350-7_11

  • Walker N (2010) The migration of constitutional ideas and the migration of the constitutional idea: the case of the EU. In: Choudhry S (ed) The migration of constitutional ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 316–345. Retrieved from http://www.cambridge.org/gb/academic/subjects/law/jurisprudence/migration-constitutional-ideas

  • Watson A (1974) Legal transplants: an approach to comparative law. Scottish Academic Press, Edinburgh: London

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson A (1978) Comparative law and legal change. Camb Law J 37(2):313–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webber G (2010) Proportionality, balancing, and the cult of constitutional rights scholarship. Can J Law Jurisprud 23(1). Retrieved from http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1322810

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webber G (2013) On the loss of rights (SSRN Scholarly Paper No. ID 2272978). Social Science Research Network, Rochester, NY. Retrieved from http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2272978

  • Weinrib L (2006) The postwar paradigm and American exceptionalism. In: Choudhry S (ed) The migration of constitutional ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 84–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Wise EM (1990) The transplant of legal patterns. Am J Comp Law 38:1–22. https://doi.org/10.2307/840531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Würtenberger T (1999) Der Schutz vom Eigentum und Freiheit im ausgehenden 18. Jahrhundert. In: Gose W, Würtenberger T (eds) Zur Ideen- und Rezeptionsgeschichte des preußischen allgemeinen Landrechts. Trierer Symposion zum 250. Geburtstag von Carl Gottlieb Svarez. Frommann-Holzboog, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, pp 55–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Yi Z (2007) Prinzipientheorie in Korea. In: Sieckmann J-R (ed) Die Prinzipientheorie der Grundrechte: Studien zur Grundrechtstheorie Robert Alexys, 1st edn. Nomos Verl.-Ges, Baden-Baden, pp 263–268

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zhordania T (2012) The problems relating to the margin of appreciation doctrine under the European convention on human rights. Europa-Kolleg, Institute for European Integration. Retrieved from http://epub.sub.uni-hamburg.de/epub/volltexte/2014/35568/

  • Zweigert K, Kötz H (1998) Introduction to comparative law (T. Weir, Trans.), 3rd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford; Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Andrade Neto, J. (2018). On the Migration of Proportionality. In: Borrowing Justification for Proportionality. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 72. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02263-1_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02263-1_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-02262-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-02263-1

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics