Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 134))

Abstract

In their review article on “Scientific Reduction” Van Riel and Van Gulick (Scientific reduction. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 edition). Stanford University, Stanford, 2016) write,

Saying that x reduces to y typically implies that x is nothing more than y or nothing over and above y.

The y to which an x reduces consists most often of x’s components. But virtually nothing can be reduced if to be “nothing more than” or “nothing over and above” its components means to have no properties other than those of its components, individually or aggregated. An atom has properties other than those of its quarks and electrons. A protein, a biological cell, and a hurricane—not to mention such man-made entities as houses, mobile phones, and automobiles—all have properties over and above their components. The properties of most entities depend on both those of the entity’s components and on how those components are put together. (That would seem obvious, but perhaps it’s not.)

One of the defining characteristics of what might be referred to as the creative disciplines—computer science, engineering, the creative arts, etc.—is a focus on understanding and using the effects of putting things together. They ask what new (and in human terms interesting and useful) properties can be realized by putting things together in new ways. Using software as an example I explore software construction, and I ask what, if anything, one gains by thinking of it reductively.

Reduction as nothing-more-than-ism tends to blind one to nature’s constructive aspects. I discuss nature’s tools for creating new phenomena, including negative interactive energy, means for creating and tapping stores of usable energy, autopoiesis, and biological evolution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Extracts are slightly paraphrased throughout the paper.

  2. 2.

    Brigandt and Love (2015) distinguish two primary categories of reduction: “theory reduction, the claim that a higher level theory can be logically deduced from a lower level theory, and explanatory reduction, the claim that representations of higher level features can be explained by representations of lower level features, typically by decomposing a higher level system into parts.” I focus primarily on explanatory reduction.

  3. 3.

    Gerd Van Riel seems to spell his name at different times with an upper or lower case “V.” His current affiliation, KU Leuven, (http://www.kuleuven.be/wieiswie/en/person/u0019425, retrieved Sep 3, 2016) uses upper case.

  4. 4.

    Brigandt and Love also discuss methodological reduction (“biological systems are most fruitfully investigated at the lowest possible generally biochemical level)” and epistemic reduction (“knowledge about one scientific domain can be reduced to knowledge about a more fundamental level”).

  5. 5.

    This sounds uncontroversial, but the exchange of matter and energy between biological organisms and the environment raises questions. When does an oxygen or food molecule become part of an organism? When does waste matter become not part of an organism? Are organ transplants or component implants such as pacemakers, corneal replacements, tooth implants, or dental fillings part of an organism? What about disease agents and toxins? What about an organism’s biome and virome? Does a photon that conveys visual information become part of an organism—and if so when? Given these considerations it seems a much more complex issue to decide what constitutes a biological system than this innocent-sounding statement implies.

  6. 6.

    Physics being what it is, the discovery of any such phenomena would inevitably lead to “new” physics anyway.

  7. 7.

    As I’m using the terms, to implement is to create something that has certain pre-specified properties. Engineers implement systems with required functionality. To realize—as in the heart realizes a pumping capability—is for something to come into existence that happens to have some properties. Nature realizes various functionalities without having those functionalities as teleological goals. See Abbott (2016a) for an expanded discussion.

  8. 8.

    Wilson (1998) called this recomposition: to show that components can be reassembled to “capture the key properties of the entire ensembles.”

  9. 9.

    http://plato.stanford.edu/search/search?query=constructor, conducted Sep 8, 2016.

  10. 10.

    Recall our earlier discussion of implementation and realization.

  11. 11.

    Physics is still investigating the primitives. But given the primitives as currently understood, the point still holds.

  12. 12.

    Although Strassler (2015) coined the term, the phenomenon (under various names) is fundamental to physics.

  13. 13.

    See example images from Lawrence Berkeley National Lab: http://particleadventure.org/history-universe.html

  14. 14.

    I was unable to find a relevant philosophical analysis of the term entity. Bricker (2014), for example, discusses ontological commitment but not an analysis of the grounds that justify ontological commitment.

  15. 15.

    Such phenomena account for many of the things traditionally considered emergent. Abbott (2010) called this static emergence. It is static because the results are statically stable entities. This mechanism is not responsible for aggregations or software objects, which are not bound together by negative interaction energy.

  16. 16.

    Work is defined as force applied over distance. I don’t know whether there is a general term for energy available for doing work. Thermodynamic free energy may not cover all cases, e.g., the kinetic energy of a bowling ball rolling down an alley or energy transferred from a planet to a satellite during a gravitational slingshot maneuver. Even isolated orbiting masses radiate energy—reflecting the consumption of usable energy. See Koberlein (2016).

  17. 17.

    Topological properties such as ball joints also help.

  18. 18.

    In his elegant book, Hoffmann points out that the “wind” is random rather than directional.

  19. 19.

    The term autopoiesis has been dismissed as vacuous, trivial, overly complex, self-referential, circular, and intentionally mysterious. Maturana and Varela’s original idea (1980) was to identify a category of systems that have the capacity to repair themselves. The claim is that all living systems are autopoietic but not that autopoiesis is sufficient for life. See Razeto-Barry (2012) for a review of the history and criticism.

  20. 20.

    Abbott (2010) used the term dynamic emergence for systems that hold themselves together through self- maintenance. Abbott (2016a) argues that together static and dynamic emergence demystify emergence and render the term nearly superfluous.

  21. 21.

    This section discusses biological-style evolution, not general evolution discussed earlier. For convenience, I’ll use the term evolution for biological evolution and general evolution when referring to the broader process.

  22. 22.

    I’m using the term procreation rather than reproduction since the offspring are generally not exact copies.

  23. 23.

    I wouldn’t argue that DNA is the design of an organism or that DNA is the software an organism “runs.” That’s a greatly over-simplified picture of the role of DNA. But I think it’s fair to say that the meta-information about the form and function of organisms that DNA encodes plays a role similar to a product’s design.

References

  • Abbott, Russ. 2010. Abstract data types and constructive emergence. Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers, American Philosophical Society 9(2, Spring 2010): 48–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a. The end of (traditional) emergence; introducing reactive emergence. Journal of Public Policy and Complex Systems 2/2: 91–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. Autonomous causality. Submitted for publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, Hanne, and Brian Hepburn. 2016. Scientific method. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Summer 2016 Edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Philip. 1972. More is different. Science 177/4047: 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, Phillip. 2014. Ontological commitment. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo and Alan Love. 2015. Reductionism in Biology. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2015 ed, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Sean. 2012. Discussions on emergence and reduction. In Moving Naturalism Forward. Sponsored by the Division of Physics, Mathematics, and Astronomy and the Moore Center for Theoretical Cosmology and Physics, California Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1966. Topics in the theory of generative grammar. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 1986. The Blind Watchmaker, 1986 ed. London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickerson, Richard E., Harry B. Gray, and Gilbert P. Haight. 1979. Chemical principles. 3rd ed. Menlo Park: The Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, Phil. 2000. Physical causation. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dybjer, Peter and Erik Palmgren. 2016. Intuitionistic type theory. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2016 edion, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, Albert. 1918. Principles of research. Address delivered before the Physical Society in Berlin at a celebration of Max Planck’s sixtieth birthday. Mein Weltbild. Amsterdam: Querida Verlag, 1934.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, Richard. 1964. Knowing vs understanding. This is a segment of the complete series. Published on YouTube. See http://io9.gizmodo.com/watch-a-series-of-seven-brilliant-lectures-by-richard-f-5894600 for the complete series of lectures.

  • Fodor, J. 1974. Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese 28: 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry. 1997. Special Sciences: Still Autonomous After All these Years. Noûs, Vol. 31, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 11, Mind, Causation, and World, (1997), 149–163. Boston: Blackwell Publishing.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenfeld, Nigel. 2011. Emergence and minimal models in condensed matter physics and biology. Conference on Emergence and Effective Field Theories, Perimeter Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, Peter. 2012. Life’s Ratchet: How molecular machines extract order from chaos. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koberlein, Brian. 2016. Death Spiral. One Universe at a time (blog).

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, Pierre Simon. 1814 A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities. Trans. F.W. Truscott, and F.L. Emory. New York: Dover Publications (1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, Barry. 2009. Why is there anything except physics? Synthese 170/2: 217–233.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P.L. 2003. Autopoiesis: A review and a reappraisal. Naturwissenschaften 90 (2): 49–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The minimal autopoietic unit. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres 44 (4): 335–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacLeod, M., and N.J. Nersessian. 2015. Modeling systems-level dynamics: understanding without mechanistic explanation in integrative systems biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C — Biological and Biomedical Science 49: 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, Humberto, and Francisco Varela. 1980. Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. In Boston studies in the philosophy of science 42, ed. Robert S. Cohen, and Marx W. Wartofsky. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire, Brett A., P.B. Carroll, R.A. Loomis, I.A. Finneran, P.R. Jewell, A.J. Remijan, and G.A. Blake. 2016. Discovery of the interstellar chiral molecule propylene oxide (CH3CHCH2O). Science. doi:https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aae0328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest. 1970. Issues in the logic of reductive explanations. In Mind, science, and history, ed. H.E. Kiefer and K.M. Munitz, 117–137. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, Judah. 2000. Causality. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Razeto-Barry, Pablo. 2012. Autopoiesis 40 years later. A review and a reformulation. Orig Life Evol Biosph. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11084-012-9297-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Gideon. 2014. Abstract objects. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2014 edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, Erwin. 1944. What is life? Cambridge University Press, reprint edition (2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. 1959. Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review 68: 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strassler, Matt. 2015. The energy that holds things together. In Of particular significance: Conversations about science with theoretical physicist matt strassler. Online blog.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Riel, Raphael, and Robert Van Gulick. 2016. Scientific reduction. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2016 edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. 2003. Facing up. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E.O. 1998. Consilience: The unity of knowledge. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, James. 2003. Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Scientific explanation. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2014 edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmer, Carl. 2009. The evolution of the eye. The New York Academy of Sciences Magazine, The New York Academy of Sciences. (October 9, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Russ Abbott .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Abbott, R. (2019). A Software-Inspired Constructive View of Nature. In: Berkich, D., d'Alfonso, M. (eds) On the Cognitive, Ethical, and Scientific Dimensions of Artificial Intelligence. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 134. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-01800-9_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-01800-9_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-01799-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-01800-9

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics