Skip to main content

Difference and Robustness: An Aristotelian Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biological Robustness

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 23))

  • 270 Accesses

Abstract

The paper starts by recalling the ordinary and etymological sense of the word “robustness”, for placing it then in the context of the current systemic view. Then I focus discussion on systems robustness in the paradigmatic case of living organisms. We discover that the notion of robustness is closely linked, in the case of organism, with the notion of difference, given that organisms arise precisely by a differentiation process (Sect. 13.1). So, in order to understand the ontology of robustness, we need to explore the ontology of difference; and in order to do so, we must distinguish between constitutive and comparative difference (Sect. 13.2.1). Then I deal with the problem of unity of the constitutive differences: I wonder if it is possible to unify the many differences that an organism exhibits in a single difference. It is an important question, given that unity is one of most essential characteristics of the organism (Sect. 13.2.2). And the answer to this question raises immediately a query for the intelligibility of this final and unique constitutive difference (Sect. 13.2.3). Such intellibility is possible thanks to the formal nature of the final difference, but it requires also a pluralistic approach. Besides that, we have to sketch the ontological and epistemological relationships between difference, identity and similarity (Sect. 13.3), which will be crucial for intelligibility of the difference, since according to a certain tradition, intelligibility depends on identity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the other hand, the degree of robustness of a system is always finite, since otherwise the system would be eternal, which cannot be said even of the entirety of the universe as a whole.

  2. 2.

    Here “physical” is read as being opposed to “logical”. The physical is that which has reality apart from thought. In this sense, the physical is not opposed to the biological. In fact, all living beings have their own reality whether or not they are thought of. Nor is there any assertion of reductionism here: it is not held that biology can be reduced to physics , but only that living beings have their own reality.

  3. 3.

    In the interpretation I present here, I follow contemporary authors such as Pierre Pellegrin (1982) and David Balme (1987, 1987a). I have argued in favor of this interpretation in various works (Marcos 1996, 2012).

  4. 4.

    Metaphysics , 1031b 31 and ff.

  5. 5.

    On the Parts of Animals, 643a 24.

  6. 6.

    There have even been cases of editors and translators of Aristotle’s texts that have sought to amend this reading. Nevertheless, it figures precisely in this way in all manuscripts save one (Inciarte 1974, 276).

  7. 7.

    Metaphysics VIII 6; On the Soul II 1; On the Parts of Animals I.

  8. 8.

    Metaphysics, 1038a 19–20.

  9. 9.

    On the Generation of Animals, 742b 32.

  10. 10.

    Metaphysics, 1037b 30 – 1038a 4.

  11. 11.

    Metaphysics, 1038a 5–8.

  12. 12.

    Metaphysics, 1038a 8–9.

  13. 13.

    Metaphysics, 1038a 19–20.

  14. 14.

    Metaphysics , 1038a 9; On the Parts of Animals, 642b 5 – 644a 12.

  15. 15.

    On the Parts of Animals, 643b 10 and ff.

  16. 16.

    On the Parts of Animals, 645b 13–22; On the Soul, 402b 10–16, 415a 16–20.

  17. 17.

    Sophistical Refutations, 165a 5–14.

  18. 18.

    Physics 204b 1–12; Metaphysics Z and H.

References

  • Amundson, R. (2005). The changing rule of the embryo in evolutionary biology: Structure and synthesis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Metaphysics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. On the Generation of Animals.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. On the Parts of Animals.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. On the Soul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Physics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Sophistical Refutations.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balme, D. (1987a). Aristotle’s use of divisio and differentiae. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 69–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balme, D. (1987b). Aristotle’s biology was not essentialist. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 291–312). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1968). Différence et répétition. París: P.U.F..

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1967). L’Écriture et la différence. París: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Identity and Difference (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inciarte, F. (1974). El reto del positivismo lógico. Madrid: Rialp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. (2017). An Aristotelian philosophy of biology: Form, Function and Development. In M. Bertolaso (Ed.), Emerging trends in the philosophy of biology. Acta Philosophica (Vol 26, pp. 33–52).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J. F. (1983). Le différend. París: Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcos, A. (1996). Aristóteles y otros animales. Barcelona: PPU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcos, A. (2012). Postmodern Aristotle. Newcastle: CSP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2004). Why integrative pluralism? E:CO Special Double Issue, 6(1–2), 81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos. Why the materialist Neo-Darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2014). The return of the organism as a fundamental explanatory concept in biology. Philosophy Compass, 9(5), 347–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin, P. (1982). La classification des animaux chez Aristote. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaltsas, T. (1994). Substances & Universals in Aristotle’s metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zubiri, X. (1980). La inteligencia sentiente [Sentient Intelligence]. Madrid, Alianza. English translation from http://www.zubiri.org/works/englishworks/si/SI1C1.htm.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfredo Marcos .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Marcos, A. (2018). Difference and Robustness: An Aristotelian Approach. In: Bertolaso, M., Caianiello, S., Serrelli, E. (eds) Biological Robustness. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-01198-7_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics