Skip to main content

How to Pursue the Adaptationist Program in Psychology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Method Matters in Psychology

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 45))

Abstract

This chapter is concerned with the methodological foundations of evolutionary psychology. Evolutionary psychologists have offered adaptation explanations for a wide range of human psychological characteristics. Critics, however, have argued that such endeavours are problematic because the appropriate evidence required to demonstrate adaptation is unlikely to be forthcoming. More specifically, doubts have been raised over both the methodology employed by evolutionary psychologists for studying adaptations and about the possibility of ever developing acceptably rigorous evolutionary explanations of human psychological phenomena. In this chapter, it is argued that by employing a wide range of methods for inferring adaptation and by adopting an inference to the best explanation strategy for evaluating adaptation explanations, these two doubts can be adequately addressed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although as we note later, some (e.g., Gould & Lewontin, 1979) have suggested that alternatives to natural selection are not given as much consideration as they should be in explaining phenotypic characteristics.

  2. 2.

    We rehearse the received view of adaptation and biological function here, sometimes called the etiological account of function (Wright, 1973). However, alternative accounts have also been offered which focus instead on the dispositional features of traits as the appropriate method of identifying function (e.g., Reeve & Sherman, 1993).

  3. 3.

    Although critics have pointed out, with some justification, that the detailed use of comparative methods and findings from the relevant paleosciences rarely figure prominently in the explanatory accounts offered by evolutionary psychologists. Moreover, the concept of the “environment of evolutionary adaptedness” has not gone without criticism (Foley, 1996).

  4. 4.

    One important caveat to our discussion of the various methods of identifying adaptations is that some of these methods may be less relevant for identifying sexually selected traits. As Miller (2000) has vigorously and persuasively argued, many of the cognitive and behavioural traits possessed by humans and other animals may be the products of sexual selection. These traits may not be identifiable using the same set of criteria that we have outlined above. For example, we should expect a much greater degree of heritable variability in sexually selected traits and they will not obviously demonstrate design for survival.

  5. 5.

    It should be noted here that for the theory of explanatory coherence explanatory breadth is the appropriate measure of empirical adequacy, not predictive success, as the hypothetico-deductive method would have it. We urge an expanded view of theory testing that recaptures the 19th century idea that a successful theory should, where appropriate, explain the relevant phenomena in its domain as well as being responsible for its entailments.

References

  • Aiello, L. C. (1996). Terrestriality, bipedalism and the origin of language. In W. G. Runciman, J. Maynard-Smith, & R. I. M. Dunbar (Eds.), Evolution of social behavior patterns in primates and man. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aitchison, J. (1998). On discontinuing the continuity–discontinuity debate. In J. R. Hurford, M. Studdert-Kennedy, & C. Knight (Eds.), Approaches to the evolution of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, R. D., & Noonan, K. M. (1979). Concealment of ovulation, parental care and human social evolution. In N. A. Chagnon & W. Irons (Eds.), Evolutionary biology and human social behavior: an anthropological perspective. North Scituat, MA: Duxbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruch, S. G. (1989). Prediction and theory evaluation: The case of light bending. Science, 246, 1124–1129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M. (1995). Evolutionary psychology: A new paradigm for psychological science. Psychological Inquiry, 6, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M., Haselton, M. G., Shackelford, T. K., Bleske, A. L., & Wakefield, J. C. (1998). Adaptations, exaptations, and spandrels. American Psychologist, 53, 533–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caro, T. M., & Borgerhoff Mulder, M. (1987). The problem of adaptation in the study of human behavior. Ethology & Sociobiology, 8, 61–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carstairs-McCarthy, A. (1999). The origins of complex language: An inquiry into the evolutionary beginnings of sentences, syllables, and truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1972). Language and mind. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1991). Linguistics and cognitive science: Problems and mysteries. In A. Kasher (Ed.), The Chomskyan turn. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corballis, M. C. (1999). The gestural origins of language. American Scientist, 87, 138–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. S. (1996). Evolutionary theory in cognitive psychology. Minds and Machines, 6, 445–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1986). The blind watchmaker. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the human brain. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duchlin, L. E. (1990). The evolution of articulate speech: comparative anatomy of the oral cavity in Pan and Homo. Journal of Human Evolution, 19, 687–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1954). The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R. I. M. (1993). Coevolution of neocortical size, group size and language in humans. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16, 681–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R. I. M. (1996). Grooming, gossip, and the evolution of language. London: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R. I. M., Duncan, N. D. C., & Nettle, D. (1995). Size and structure of freely forming conversational groups. Human Nature, 6, 67–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1996). The adaptive legacy of human evolution: A search for the environment of evolutionary adaptedness. Evolutionary Anthropology, 4, 194–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frumhoff, P. C., & Reeve, H. K. (1994). Using phylogenies to test hypotheses of adaptation: A critique of some current proposals. Evolution, 48, 172–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangestad, S. W., & Simpson, J. A. (2000). The evolution of human mating: Trade-offs and strategic pluralism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 573–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1999). Adaptationism and the power of natural selection. Biology and Philosophy, 14, 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1978). Sociobiology: The art of storytelling. New Scientist, 16, 530–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 205, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1996). The historical turn in the study of adaptation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 511–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harcourt, A. H., Harvey, P. H., Larson, S. G., & Short, R. V. (1981). Testis weight, body weight and breeding system in primates. Nature, 293, 55–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, P. H., & Pagel, M. D. (1991). The comparative method in evolutionary biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcomb, H. R. (1996). Just so stories and inference to the best explanation in evolutionary psychology. Minds and Machines, 6, 525–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hrdy, S. B. (1981). The women that never evolved. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J. R., & Josephson, S. G. (1994). Abductive inference: Computation, philosophy, technology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ketelaar, T., & Ellis, B. J. (2000). Are evolutionary explanations unfalsifiable? Evolutionary psychology and the Lakatosian philosophy of science. Psychological Inquiry, 11, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirkpatrick, L. (1999). Toward an evolutionary psychology of religion and personality. Journal of Personality, 67, 920–952.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, C., Studdert-Kennedy, M., & Hurford, J. R. (Eds.). (2000). The evolutionary emergence of language: Social function and the origins of linguistic form. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause, M. A. (1997). Evolutionary psychology, adaptation and the evolution of language: Is there need for comparison? International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 10, 180–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, A., & Losos, A. L. (1996). Phylogenetic systematics of adaptation. In M. R. Rose & G. V. Lauder (Eds.), adaptation. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauder, G. V. (1996). The argument from design. In M. R. Rose & G. V. Lauder (Eds.), Adaptation. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1979). Sociobiology as an adaptationist program. Behavioral Science, 24, 5–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1998). The evolution of cognition. In D. Scarborough & S. Sternberg (Eds.), An invitation to cognitive science: Methods, models, and conceptual issues. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (1999). Evolutionary psychology: The burdens of proof. Biology and Philosophy, 14, 211–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Looren de Jong, H., & van der Steen, W. J. (1998). Biological thinking in evolutionary psychology: Rockbottom or quicksand? Philosophical Psychology, 11, 183–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manning, J. T., Scutt, D., & Lewis-Jones, D. I. (1998). Developmental stability, ejaculate size, and sperm quality in men. Evolution and human behavior, 19, 273–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. F. (2000). The mating mind: How sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moller, A. P., Soler, M., & Thornhell, R. (1995). Breast asymmetry, sexual selection, and human reproductive success. Ethology & Sociobiology, 16, 207–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack, S. H., & Sober, E. (1994). Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. American Naturalist, 143, 361–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piatelli-Palmarini, M. (1989). Evolution, selection, and cognition: From learning to parameter setting in biology and the study of language. Cognition, 31, 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. London: Allen Lane, Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S., & Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, 707–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, H. K., & Sherman, P. W. (1993). Adaptation and the goals of evolutionary research. Quarterly Review of Biology, 68, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R. C. (1996). The prospects for an evolutionary psychology: Human language and human reasoning. Minds and Machines, 6, 541–557.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, S., Kamin, L. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1984). Not in our genes: Biology, ideology and human nature. London: Pelican Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, M. R., & Lauder, G. V. (1996). Post-spandrel adaptationism. In M. R. Rose & G. V. Lauder (Eds.), adaptation. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (1998). Do’s and don’ts for Darwinizing psychology. In D. D. Cummins & C. Allen (Eds.), The evolution of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sillen-Tullberg, B., & Moller, A. P. (1993). The relationship between concealed ovulation and mating systems in anthropoid primates: A phylogenetic analysis. American Naturalist, 141, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E. A., Borgerhoff Mulder, M., & Hill, K. (2001). Controversies in the evolutionary social sciences: A guide for the perplexed. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 16, 128–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to the philosophy of biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1978). The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 76–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1989). Adaptation versus phylogeny: The role of animal psychology in the study of human behavior. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 2, 175–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990a). The past explains the present: Emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11, 375–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990b). On the universality of human nature and the uniqueness of the individual: The role of genetics and adaptation. Journal of Personality, 58, 17–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., & Byrne, R. W. (Eds.). (1997). Machiavellian intelligence II: Extensions and evaluations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S. (1994). Adaptive genetic variation and human evolutionary psychology. Ethology and Sociobiology, 15, 219–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82, 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurif, E. B. (1995). Brains regions of relevance to syntactic processing. In L. R. Gleitman & M. Liberman (Eds.), An invitation to cognitive science (second edition): Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian D. Haig .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Haig, B.D. (2018). How to Pursue the Adaptationist Program in Psychology. In: Method Matters in Psychology. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 45. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-01051-5_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics