Skip to main content

Conversational Implicatures of Normative Discourse

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 537 Accesses

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 20))

Abstract

Grice (1967) formulated his famous maxims having mainly in mind the assertive discourse, i.e. a discourse which aims to inform, and can be true or false. However, as it is well known, norms do not aim to inform: they aim to guide behaviours, and, therefore, they are neither true nor false. However, Grice conceived of the cooperative principle as a general principle that also guides non-assertive conversations. Following a classical Gricean approach (although with some modifications), this essay aims to restate Gricean conversational maxims in order to make them applicable to normative discourse. The restatement will also seek to shed new light on debated issues of normative discourse, such as the relation of sub-contrariety between deontic concepts or the distinction between commands, on the one hand, and suggestions and requests, on the other. Moreover, it provides some clues to reconstruct the mechanisms through which we usually interpret certain utterances as normative, i.e. as instances of a normative discourse.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “Our talk exchanges do not normally consist of a succession of disconnected remarks, and would not be rational if they did. They are characteristically, to some degree at least, cooperative efforts; and each participant recognizes in them, to some extent, a common purpose or set of purposes, or at least a mutually accepted direction” (Grice 1989: 26).

  2. 2.

    The clarification “at least to a certain extent” is indispensable when taking account of cases of the so-called exploitation or flouting of the maxims: cases in which a maxim is overtly violated, in order to intentionally exploit the evidence of violation and convey a certain message. In Grice’s opinion, irony, metaphors, meiosis and hyperbole fall into this category: c.f., e.g., Grice 1967, 1989; Levinson 1983.

  3. 3.

    See, among many, Hare 1952: 5; von Wright 1963: 100ff.; Bulygin 1982; Guastini 1990: 35ff.

  4. 4.

    On this complex topic see, e.g., the classical works of Searle 1975b, and Récanati 1980.

  5. 5.

    This notion can be traced back to Anscombe, 1957, and it was then employed by many authors, among them: Kenny 1963: 217; Geach 1963: 281; Warnock 1971: 111; Strawson 1973: 59; Searle, 1975a, b; Humberstone 1992; Celano 1994: 695ff.; Barberis 2003: 67f.; Villa 2004: 135f.

  6. 6.

    So I will not be concerned with utterances that also have an informative, assertive function: this does not mean that I opine that some of them cannot, in some context, play a normative function. However, the problems related to the indirect speech acts are too many and much too complex to be addressed here.

  7. 7.

    The normative nature of permissions is very discussed: surely, they are very different from commands and prohibitions since they do not impose only one course of action and, therefore, they cannot be violated or disobeyed. However, as I extensively argued in previous works, a permissive utterance can express a standard according to which behaviours are to be evaluated and it can directly aim to influence the listener’s behaviour by telling her what she is permitted to do (or to omit): see Poggi 2004a, b.

  8. 8.

    Although it is debated, many authors assimilate the questions to requests to say something: see Hare 1949; Ross 1968, 77n; Lewis 1969, 186; Searle 1969: 69; Schiffer 1972: 95ss.; Hintikka 1974; Searle 1975a; Bach and Harnish 1979: 48.

  9. 9.

    Obviously, there exist more sophisticated accounts of normative discourse, but they are very debated and they are theoretical reconstructions that presuppose that we have already an intuitive idea of what the normative discourse is. In this regard, consider, e.g., the modal analysis of imperatives or all the analysis based on the sense/force distinction—variously labelled phrastic/neustic, illocutionary force/representational part (or proposition, or sentence, or sentence radical, or state description), indicative sentence−/mood-setter: see, among many, Hare 1952; Ross 1968; Alchourrón and Bulygin 1981; Davidson 1984: 109ff. For a critical overview of the most recent contributions in this field see Sardo 2016.

  10. 10.

    In fact, if the listener interpreted (a) as an assertion and replied something like “No, you are wrong, it is permitted”, she would give rise to a misunderstanding, and the speaker might well replicate “I’m not saying that it is forbidden: I’m forbidding it”.

  11. 11.

    Although this is not Grice’s opinion: “When I speak of the assumptions required in order to maintain the supposition that the Cooperative Principle and maxims are being observed on a given occasion, I am thinking of assumptions that are nontrivially required; I do not intend to include, for example, assumption to the effect that some particular maxim is being observed, or is thought of by the speaker as being observed. This seemingly natural restriction has an interesting consequence with regards to Moore’s ‘paradox’. On my account, it will not be true that when I say that p, I conversationally implicate that I believe that p; for to suppose that I believe that p […] is just to suppose that I am observing the first maxim of Quality on this occasion” (Grice, 1989: 41–42). However, this point is questionable: even if it is true that the first Maxim of Quality is very important because “the other Maxims come into operation only on the assumption that this maxim of Quality is satisfied” (Grice 1989: 27), it is true as well that – with the exception of the inference from “p” to “I believe that p” – this maxim does not seem to hold any specific implicature, so, pace Grice, it would play a role which is completely different from the other maxims. Moreover, sometimes the implicatures which are governed by the other maxims seem to be nothing else than the assumption to the effect that some particular maxim has been observed.

  12. 12.

    Recently, the role of cancellability as a necessary condition for conversational implicatures has been challenged by Weiner 2006. For some replies to Weiner cf. Blome-Tillmann 2008; Borge 2009.

  13. 13.

    See, e.g., Leonard 1959; Grice 1969; Searle 1969; Searle 1975b; Bach and Harnish 1979; von Wright 1983; Bentham 2010: 22footnote.

  14. 14.

    Obviously, we can imagine some unusual contexts in which such utterances are not so anomalous, but this is true also about Moore’s paradox: see, e.g., Wittgenstein 1980: §§ 485–7; Kobes 1995: especially 303; Green 2007.

  15. 15.

    Also according to Ross (1968, 38ss.) requests are norms (personal directives in Ross’ terms) in the speaker’s interest based on solidarity, while suggestions are norms in the listener’s interest based on solidarity or disinterested norms (exhortations, admonitions, and so on): i.e. Ross does not consider the possibility of suggestion in the speaker’s interest, or, better, he equates them to requests.

  16. 16.

    At least if we exclude metaphysical questions, such as the existence of God or the immortality of the human soul.

  17. 17.

    Actually Searle formulates his thesis regarding the distinction between suggestions and commands (and his example concerns the utterance “You should clean up your room”). However, if we agree that some suggestions do not express norms, his argument can be adapted to the distinction between requests and commands.

  18. 18.

    Atlas has criticized the maxims of Quality because they confuse what an utterance means on the basis of the CP with the mental attitudes of the speaker: “whatever (in the way of reasons) explains why the speaker said (in the context) what he said is not necessarily, even in part, what the speaker meant” (Atlas 2005, 73).The normative formulation of (nQL2) avoids this criticism, because it has nothing to do with the speaker’s reasons to say what she says.

  19. 19.

    Other authors claim that the so-called “scalar implicature” is a semantic mechanism linked to the presence of an articulated constituent at the level of the logical form of scalar utterances, the so-called exhaustification operator: see, e.g., Pistoia Reda, 2014.

  20. 20.

    The strong epistemic modification has been suggested, for the first time, by Gazdar, 1979, 59.

  21. 21.

    See, e.g., Soames, 1982; Horn, 1989. Horn initially had argued (cf. Horn, 1972, 90) that not all scalar implicatures have the same epistemic force: in particular, in his opinion, given a scale with more than two members, e.g. <a, b, c >, the statement of the weaker member, “c’”, implicates that the recipient could (and not that she should) infer that the speaker knew that non-b and non-a. Instead Hirschberg (1985, 75ff.) believes that scalar implicatures have as their object a disjunction: so, for example, “Some of my children have graduated” implicates “I think that not-all my children have graduated or I do not know if all my children have graduated”.

  22. 22.

    The existence of a linguistic scale is also much debated between the conjunctions < and, or > according to which if a speaker asserts the weaker “or”, she is not in the position to assert “and”. Also the scalar implicatures related to numerical expressions and the possibility of negative scalar implicatures are very controversial. With respect to the first problem, see, e.g., Sadock, 1981; Atlas, 2005: 186ss.; Kempson, 1975; Kempson, 1986; Carston, 1988. With respect to negative scalar implicatures, see Gazdar, 1979: 56ss.; Hirschberg, 1985, 73; Horn, 1989: 234; Atlas and Levinson, 1981; Levinson, 2000: 80ss.

  23. 23.

    I discuss this thesis also in Poggi 2004a, b, 2016.

  24. 24.

    On this axiom see Poggi 2000; Ratti 2016.

  25. 25.

    I have developed this thesis in Poggi 2004a, b.

  26. 26.

    This is an instance of the famous Jorgensen’s dilemma: see Jørgensen, 1937.

  27. 27.

    I think that this is a further argument against the semantic interpretation of scalar implicatures: how can an articulated constituent be associated to the logical form of a scalar sentence, like (q), if it is the context (and a conversational maxim) that guides the interpretation of (q) either as a scalar utterance (a permission) or a command (with no scalar implicature associated to it)?

  28. 28.

    On both issues see, among many, Carston 1995; Davies 1998, 46ff.; Levinson 2000: 122ff.

References

  • Alchourrón, Carlos E. 1969. Logic of Norms and Logic of Normative propositions. Logique & Analyse 12, 242–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, Carlos E, Bulygin, Eugenio. 1981.The Expressive Conception of Norms. In:Hilpinen, R. (Ed.),New Studies in Deontic Logic.Holland, Dordrecht: pp. 95–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret. 1957.Intention.Basil Blackwell,Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay D. 1993. The Implication of Conversation: the 1990 Leuven Lectures.Pomona College, Claremont.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay D. 2005.Logic, Meaning and Conversation.OUP, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay D., Levinson, Stephen C. 1981. It-Clefts, Informativeness, and Logical Form: Radical Pragmatics. In: Cole, P. (Ed.), Radical Pragmatics. Academic Press, New York: pp. 1–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 1994.Conversationalimplicature. Mind& Language 9, 124–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 1997.The semantic-pragmatic distinction: What it is and why it matters. Pragmatik 8, 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent, Harnish, Robert M. 1979.Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. MIT Press,Cambridge (Mass.)-London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, Mauro. 2003.Filosofia Del Diritto. Un’introduzione Teorica. Giappichelli,Torino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 2010.Of the limits of the penal branch of jurisprudence. P. Schofield (Ed.), Clarendon Press,Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2008. Conversationalimplicature and the cancellability test. Analysis68 (2), 156–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borge, Steffen. 2009. Conversationalimplicatures andcancellability. Acta Analytica 24 (2), 149–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin, Eugenio. 1982. Norms, Normative Propositions and Legal Statements. In:Fløistad, G. (Ed.),Contemporary Philosophy. A New Survey, vol. 3, Philosophy of Action.MartinusNijhoff Publishers, The Hague-Boston-London: pp. 127–152.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 1988. Implicature, Explicature, and Truth-Theoretic Semantics. In:Kempson,R.M. (ed.), Mental Representations: The Interface between Language and Reality.Cambridge University Press,Cambridge: 155–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 1995. Quantity maxims and generalised implicature. Lingua 96,213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celano, Bruno. 1994.Dialettica Della GiustificazionePratica,Giappichelli, Torino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald.1984.Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation.OUP, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Wayne A. 1998.Implicature, Intention, Convention and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory.Cambridge University Press.Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics, Implicature, Presupposition and Logical Form. Academic Press,New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, Peter Thomas. 1963.Imperative Inference. Analysis (Suppl.) 23,37–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, Mitchell S. 2007.Moorean Absurdity and Showing What’s Within. In: Green,M.S.,Williams,G.N. (Eds.), Moore’s Paradox. Clarendon Press, Oxford: pp. 189–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul H. 1967.Logic and Conversation.In Cole,P., andMorgan,J.L. (Eds.), Syntax and Semantics, 3, Speech Acts.Academic Press,New York-London: 1975, pp. 41–58. Reprinted in Grice 1989, pp.22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul H. 1969. Utterer’s Meaning and Intentions. Philosophical Review 78: 147–177. Reprinted in Grice 1989: pp. 86–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul H. 1989.Studies in the Way of Words.Harvard University Press,Cambridge-London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini, Riccardo. 1990. Dalle fonti alle norme. Giappichelli,Torino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, Richard Mervyn. 1949.Imperative Sentences. Mind 58,21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, Richard Mervyn. 1952. The Language of Morals. Clarendon Press,Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Kaarlo Jaakko Juhani.1974.Questions about Questions. In:Muniz, M.K., Unger,P.K. (Eds.),Semantics and Philosophy. New York University Press,New York:pp. 103–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschberg, Julia. 1985. A Theory of Scalar Implicature.Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence R. 1972.On the semantic properties of logical operator in English.Ph.D. dissertation, UCLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence R.1989.A natural history of negation. University of Chicago Press,Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, Lloyd. 1992.Direction of Fit.Mind 101,59–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jørgensen, Jørgen. 1937. Imperatives and Logic.Erkenntnis 7,288–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempson, Ruth M. 1975.Presupposition and the Delimitation of Semantics. Cambridge University Press,Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempson, Ruth M. 1986.Ambiguity and Semantics-Pragmatics Distinction. In: Travis,C. (Ed.), Meaning and Interpretation. Blackwell,Oxford:77–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, Anthony. 1963.Action, Emotion and Will. Routledge&Kegan Paul,London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kobes, Bernard W. 1995. Telic Higher-order Thoughts and Moore’s Paradox.Philosophical Perspectives9,291–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonard, Henry S. 1959.Interrogatives, Imperatives, Truth, Falsity and Lies.Philosophy of Science26,172–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen C. 1983.Pragmatics.Cambridge University Press,Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen C. 2000.Presumptive Meaning. MIT Press,Cambridge-London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David, 1969.Convention. Harvard University Press,Cambridge (Mass.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pistoia Reda, Salvatore. 2014. Semantica E Pragmatica Linguistica: Tracce Di Normalità Nelle Implicature Scalari. Carocci,Roma.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, Francesca. 2000.“Obbligatorio” implica “permesso”.Analisi e diritto 2000,195–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, Francesca, 2004a. Norme Permissive.Giappichelli,Torino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, Francesca, 2004b. I Permessi nel diritto.Materiali Per Una Storia Della Cultura Giuridica 3(1), pp.147–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, Francesca, 2016. Grice, the Law and the Linguistic Special Case Thesis.In: Capone, A., Poggi, F. (Eds.), Pragmatics and Law: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer,Dordrecht, pp. 231–248.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ratti, Giovanni Battista. 2016. “Obligatorio” implica “Permitido”. ¿Implicación formal o material?, Analisi e diritto 2016, 419–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Récanati, François. 1980.Some Remarks on Explicit Performatives, Indirect Speech Acts, Locutionary Meaning and Truth-Value. In:Bierwisc,M.,Kieferand,F., Searle,J.R. (Eds.),Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics. D. Reidel Publishing Company,Dordrecht-Boston-London: pp. 205–220.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2013. Content, Mood, and Force.In: Barnes, E. (Ed.), Philosophy Compass,Wiley & Sons, Hoboken (NJ): pp. 622–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, Marga.1998.Whatismeant by “Whatissaid”. A reply to Cappelen and Lepore. Mind&Language 13 (4), 598–604.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Alf. 1968.Directives and Norms.Routledge&Kegan Paul,London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, Patrick. 2007. Beyond words: Communication, truthfulness, and understanding.Episteme 4,285–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, Jerrold M.1981. Almost. In: Cole, P.(Ed.), Radical Pragmatics.Academic Press,New York:pp. 281–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sardo, Alessio. 2016. The Dark Side of Imperatives. In: Poggi, F., Capone, A. (Eds.), Law and Pragmatics: Practical and Theoretical Perspectives. Springer, Dordrecht: pp. 243–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, Stephen R. 1972.Meaning.Clarendon Press,Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1969.Speech Acts.Cambridge University Press,Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1975a.A Taxonomy of Illocutory Acts. In: Gunderson,K. (Ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge.University of Minnesota Press,Minneapolis: pp. 344–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1975b. Indirect Speech Acts. In:Cole, P., Morgan,J.L.(Eds.), Syntax and Semantics – Speech Acts. Academic Press, New York-London: pp. 59–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R., Vanderveken, Daniel. 1985. Foundation of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, Scott. 1982.How presuppositions are inherited: A solution to the projection problem.Linguistic Inquiry 13,483–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter Frederick. 1973. Austin and “locutionary meaning”. In: Berlin, I et al. (Eds.),Essays on J.L. Austin. Clarendon Press, Oxford: pp. 46–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, Vittorio. 2004.Il Positivismo Giuridico: Metodi, Teorie E Giudizi Di Valore. GiappichelliTorino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, Geoffrey James. 1971.The Object of Morality. Methuen,London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, Matthew. 2006. Are allconversationalimplicaturescancellable? Analysis 66 (2), 127–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1980.Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. I. G. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright (eds.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Georg Henrik von. 1963. Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry.Routledge&Kegan Paul,London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Georg Henrik von. 1969. On the Logic and Ontology of Norms. In:Davis, J.W., Hockney,D.J.,Wilson,W.K. (Eds.),Philosophical Logic. D. Reidel, Dordrecht: pp. 89–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Georg Henrik von. 1983. Practical Reason.Blackwell,Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this essay was delivered on 19thMay2016at the International Conference Pragmasophia (Palermo, Italy) and on 24thNovember 2016at a seminar which took place at Jagiellonian University (Kracow, Poland).I would like to thank all the members of the audience for discussion, and in particular Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki and Andrzej Grabowsk for their useful comments and criticisms.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesca Poggi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Poggi, F. (2019). Conversational Implicatures of Normative Discourse. In: Capone, A., Carapezza, M., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy: Part 2 Theories and Applications. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_15

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-00972-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-00973-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics