Skip to main content

Critical Remarks on a Theocentric Solution to the Problem of Evil

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 161 Accesses

Part of the book series: Münster Lectures in Philosophy ((MUELP,volume 5))

Abstract

In this paper, Robert Audi’s thoughts on the ineffaceable problem of evil are critically discussed. Audi develops his thought on God and evil within a broader framework that seeks to defend the possibility of rational religious commitment. He proposes a theocentric solution to the problem, which is focused on the divine experience with creation and which asks for the conditions a world has to fulfill in order to be good enough for being created by an omnicompetent God. Following this line of thought, the problem of evil can be solved if the enormous value of divine experience made in the world and with all creatures that live on earth is included in the overall comparison of good and evil. The paper provides a detailed reconstruction of Audi’s argumentation and locates it within its broader philosophical contexts. Furthermore, it considers three difficulties Audi’s theocentric solution has to resolve: Firstly, a theocentric theodicy cannot fully explain the existence of natural evil, especially horrendous natural evil. Secondly, such a position seemingly has to accept fairly burdensome metaphysical assumptions regarding the character of divine experience. Finally, an alternative theocentric conception that allows for divine regret seems to be in line with Audi’s philosophy of religion and might eventually be more responsive to human experience with great moral evil.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, e.g., Audi (2011, 67f.): “Roughly, to say that a faith is rational is to say that, at the time in question (normally the time of the attribution), there are grounds available such that someone holding the tenets of the faith on those grounds would hold them rationally […]. There are, however, different ways to hold the tenets of a religious faith. If a kind of ardent hope that the tenets are true is minimally sufficient for holding (being ‘of’) a faith, then holding a faith can surely be shown to be rational, provided the creedal content is not, say, readily seen to be inconsistent or clearly false. For […] rationality of hopes is achievable with considerably less in the way of grounding than is needed for beliefs with the same content, and it can be rational to hope even for something one has no evidence will occur and at least some good reason to think will not occur.”

  2. 2.

    Consider the contributions of Ford and Hare/Madden to Peterson (1992), who explore the possibilities of process theology to circumvent the problem of evil.

  3. 3.

    See also Audi (2011, 212), where he explicitly mentions the importance of his axiological assumptions for understanding his conception of evil.

  4. 4.

    Peter van Inwagen frames a somehow similar distinction by separating the “global” from the “local” problem of evil. See van Inwagen (2006, lectures 4–6).

  5. 5.

    Originally put forward by Rowe: “In some distant forest lightning strikes a dead tree, resulting in a forest fire. In the fire a fawn is trapped, horribly burned, and lies in terrible agony for several days before death relieves its suffering” (Rowe 1979, 337).

  6. 6.

    Otherwise it would be incomprehensible why believers devout such a fair amount of time and effort to prayers.

  7. 7.

    In fact, it would be a solution to the problem of evil if the suffering of innocent beings was rewarded in the hereafter. Then one could even argue that young children who died would be especially benefitted since they were spared a lifetime of having to prove themselves and were rewarded for the pain they suffered without having to answer for their sins on Judgment Day.

  8. 8.

    For a definition of horrendous evil see McCord Adams (1999, 26–29).

  9. 9.

    Even if horrendous evil was needed for some reason, without natural horrendous evil there would still be horrendous moral evil, which, under the free will hypothesis, only humans are responsible for.

  10. 10.

    The theistic scriptures occasionally try to describe the differentness of divine temporal perception. See, e.g., Ps. 90:4: “For a thousand years in thy sight are but as yesterday when it is past, and as a watch in the night.”

  11. 11.

    Pope Francis, Yad Vashem, 26 May 2014: https://w2.vatican.va/content/francesco/en/speeches/2014/may/documents/papa-francesco_20140526_terra-santa-memoriale-yad-vashem.html, accessed 1 October 2016.

References

  • Adams, Marilyn McCord. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 2000. Religious Commitment and Secular Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Architecture of Reason. The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. The Good in the Right. A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Rationality and Religious Commitment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, William Lane. 1978. God, Time, and Eternity. Religious Studies 14: 497–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Stephen T. 1981. Free Will and Evil. In Encountering Evil. Live Options in Theodicy, ed. Stephen T. Davis, 69–83. London: Continuum International Pub. Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, John. 1966. Evil and the God of Love. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. An Irenaean Theodicy. In Encountering Evil. Live Options in Theodicy, ed. Stephen T. Davis, 39–52. London: Continuum International Pub. Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, Daniel, ed. 1996. The Evidential Argument from Evil. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, Brian. 2014. Immutability. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/immutability/. Accessed 23 Feb 2017.

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1974. What Is It Like to Be a Bat? The Philosophical Review 83: 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, Graham. 2014. Describing Gods. An Investigation of Divine Attributes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Michael L., ed. 1992. The Problem of Evil. Selected Readings. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. God and Evil. An Introduction to the Issues. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. God, Freedom and Evil. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, William. 1979. The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, Richard. 1998. Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, Nick. 2016. The Evidential Problem of Evil. In The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evil-evi/. Accessed 10 Aug 2016.

  • van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, Michael B., and Hugh N. Campbell. 2010. Philosophy of Religion. An Introduction. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johannes Müller-Salo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kontny, Y.M., Müller-Salo, J. (2018). Critical Remarks on a Theocentric Solution to the Problem of Evil. In: Müller-Salo, J. (eds) Robert Audi: Critical Engagements. Münster Lectures in Philosophy, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00482-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics