Skip to main content

The Ethical Basis for Animal Use in Research

  • Chapter
Sourcebook of Models for Biomedical Research
  • 7584 Accesses

Abstract

The concern of biomedical researchers for the well-being of laboratory animals reflects a consensus that animals are conscious subjects. Partisans of the animal rights movement believe that researchers must go beyond the acknowledgment of consciousness and consequent attention to animal well-being. They should recognize just how similar human and animal consciousness are, and then address animal interests and animal rights. Consideration of these issues would challenge all uses, even painless uses, of animals. In any effort to identify the interests and rights of animals, even animal rights philosophers admit that the nature of consciousness and cognition—human and animal—matters. A theory of human consciousness and cognition developed by B.F.J. Lonergan is helpful in understanding and comparing human and animal consciousness. According to Lonergan, elemental wonder makes human consciousness and cognition a dynamic, self-assembling process moving from presentations given in experience through successive levels of understanding, judgment, and responsibility to the affirmation of values. Questioning sweeps humans across a divide between elementary knowing, which is shared with animals, and a type of knowing that is exclusively human. None of the animal behaviors catalogued by animal rights partisans reveals wonder and the drive to understand, affirm and decide. That drive is a single, restless activity generating successive levels of consciousness. If, as animal rights philosophers agree, animals are incapable of responsible behavior, it must also be that their cognitional feats are qualitatively different from those of humans. Absent questioning and the drive to understand, animals never emerge on the level of intelligent and rational, much less responsible, consciousness. Their cognitional achievements appear to fall within the province of elementary knowing, a realm in which they are accomplished associative learners— clever, to be sure, but not capable of the beginnings of full human knowing. Human consciousness and cognition differ enough from animal consciousness and cognition that humans claim rights while animals do not. So it is that even if we use animals in research, having vouched for their humane care, we use humans as experimental subjects only when they give informed consent. We safeguard the welfare of animals; we guarantee the rights of persons.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References and Notes

  1. Cf. American Association for the Advancement of Science: http://archives.aaas.org/docs/resolutions.php?doc_id=381; Federation of American Societies for Experimental Biology: http://opa.faseb.org/pages/PolicyIssues/animalresearch_restatement.htm; Society for Neuroscience: http://www.sfn.org/index.cfm?pagename=guidelinesPolicies_UseOfAnimalsandHumans; American Psychological Association: http://www.apa.org/science/anguide.html. Professional societies helped animal protectionists craft and then update the 1966 Animal Welfare Act that sets standards of animal care for research institutions. Cf. The National Research Council-Institute of Laboratory Animal Resources. Guide for the Care and Use of Laboratory Animals. Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1996. Moreover, they endorse regulations that implement the Act—regulations that stipulate conditions for the housing, feeding, cleanliness, exercise, and medical needs of laboratory animals; prescribe anesthesia for potentially painful procedures and analgesic drugs during postoperative care; and require participation on Institutional Animal Care and Use Committees (IACUCs) to ensure that research animals are treated responsibly and compassionately.

  2. Singer P. Animal Liberation: A New Ethic for Our Treatment of Animals, 2nd ed. New York: New York Review of Books, 1990 and Singer P. Practical Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Hearne V. What’s wrong with animal rights. Harpers 1991;283:1696:59–64. The citation is from Bentham J. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1946:310–311.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Singer (1990, 18–19),2 and Singer (1993:117)2

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Singer (1990, 81–82).2

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Singer (1990, 21).2

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. Berkowitz P. Other people’s mothers. New Repub 2000:4:434: 27–37; Russell SM, Nicoll CS. A dissection of the chapter “Tools for Research” in Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation. Proc Soc Exp Biol Med 1996;211:109-139; Carruthers P. The Animals Issue. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Singer allows the use of animals when it is clear that small harm to few animals is outweighed by great benefits for many humans. Such cases, however, are very few. Biomedical research—especially basic research—does not proceed in a straight line from a handful of animals to certain specific persons. Ten years after declaring that the routine use of hundreds of thousands of laboratory animals in research “without the remotest prospect of significant benefits for human beings or any other animals” is ethically unacceptable, Singer heralded experiments in which experimentally damaged nervous systems of rats were repaired with stem cells derived from embryos. (Cf. Singer P. Sense and sentience: We might not need pig hearts if the ban on human embryo experiments were lifted. Guardian August 21, 1999:24.) Singer touted these experiments because they could lead to the practice of growing tissues for the repair or replacement of damaged organs, thus eliminating the need of temporary animal transplants for patients on human organ waiting lists. This research, however, depended on decades of basic research, much of it conducted with little understanding of its role in stem cell therapy and all of it involving the routine use of thousands of laboratory rats. None of it would have been approved if Singer’s moral calculus had been used prospectively.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Regan T. Editorial. News Observer, Raleigh, NC. April 3, 2001: A11.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Regan T. The case for animal rights. In: Singer P, Ed. In Defense of Animals. New York: Harper & Row, 1985:20–21.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Regan T. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983. Wise SM. Rattling the Cage: Toward Legal Rights for Animals. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Books, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Wise SM (2000, 236).11

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Wise SM (2000, 125–131).11

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Regan T (1983, 56).11

    Google Scholar 

  15. Dennett DC. Animal consciousness: What matters and why. Soc Res 1995;62(3):700.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lonergan BJF. Insight. New York: Longmans, Green and Todd, 1953. For readable summaries of Lonergan on consciousness and cognitional activity, cf. Lonergan BJF. Cognitional structure. Continuum 1964;2:230-242; and Novak M. Lonergan’s starting place: The performance of asking questions. Continuum 1964;2:89-101.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Lonergan BJF (1953, 251).16

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Lonergan BJF (1953, 324).16

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Lonergan BJF. Method in Theology. New York: Herder and Herder, 1972:27–41.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Regan T (1983, 279–281).11

    Google Scholar 

  21. Warren MA. The case for weak animal rights. In: Leone D, Leone B, Eds. Animal Rights: Opposing Viewpoints. San Diego, CA: Greenhaven Press, Inc., 1996:47.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Nelson JL. Animals, handicapped children and the tragedy of marginal cases. J Med Ethics 1988;14:191–193. As Nelson reminds us, “The distinction is this: the birth of a’ marginal’ human, or the reduction of a normal human to a marginal state, is a tragedy; the birth of say, a healthy collie pup, whose potentials are roughly on a par with the human’s is not.”

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  23. Budiansky S. If a Lion Could Talk. New York: The Free Press, 1998:27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Dawkins MS. Through Our Eyes Only? The Search for Animal Consciousness. Oxford: W.H. Freeman Spektrum, 1993:24.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Gallup GG Jr. Chimpanzees: Self-recognition. Science 1970;167:86–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Cheney D, Seyfarth RM. How Monkeys See the World. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1990:240.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See Cheney D, Seyfarth RM.27 Ever tentative, the two scientists leave open the possibility that chimpanzees possess a very limited theory of mind. They may share another’s feelings just as we spontaneously flinch at another’s pain or grin at another’s laugh, and they may be aware that feeling states such as pain underlie actions such as grimaces. Wise identifies such fellow-feeling as an “implicit theory of mind,” while Lonergan names it the intersubjective and “potential meaning” of experience. Whatever it is called, it seems qualitatively different from an explicit theory of mind, which requires that one hold and compare two different states of mind, one’s own and that of another. The ability to do that requires the introspection and active questioning of full human knowing.

    Google Scholar 

  28. See Wise SM (2000, 221).11 Cf. Trefil J. Are We Unique?: A Scientist Explores the Unparalleled Intelligence of the Human Mind. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1997:55.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Wolfe A. The Human Difference: Animals, Computers and the Necessity of Social Science. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1993:79.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Wheeler D. With ingenious experiments, a psychologist studies the mental lives of chimps. Chron Higher Ed June 25, 1999:B2.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cited in Budiansky 1998, xv. Compare contemporary philosopher Charles Hartshorne, cited in Derr TS. Animal rights, human rights. First Things 1992;20:23–30, who, although sympathetic to animal rights issues, notes that the human/animal difference is “so vast that for many purposes one can safely forget that it is a matter of degree.”

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Humana Press Inc., Totowa, NJ

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Parker, J. (2008). The Ethical Basis for Animal Use in Research. In: Conn, P.M. (eds) Sourcebook of Models for Biomedical Research. Humana Press. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-59745-285-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-59745-285-4_4

  • Publisher Name: Humana Press

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-58829-933-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-59745-285-4

  • eBook Packages: MedicineMedicine (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics