Skip to main content

Raiders of the Lost Spacetime

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories

Part of the book series: Einstein Studies ((EINSTEIN,volume 13))

Abstract

Spacetime as we know and love it is lost in most approaches to quantum gravity. For many of these approaches, as inchoate and incomplete as they may be, one of the main challenges is to relate what they take to be the fundamental non-spatiotemporal structure of the world back to the classical spacetime of general relativity (GR). The present essay investigates how spacetime is lost and how it may be regained in one major approach to quantum gravity, loop quantum gravity.

I thank audiences at the University of London’s Institute of Philosophy and at the spacetime workshop at the Bergisch University of Wuppertal. I am also grateful to my fellow Young Guns of General Relativity, Erik Curiel, John Manchak, Chris Smeenk and Jim Weatherall for valuable discussions and comments, and to Francesca Vidotto for correspondence. Finally, I owe thanks to two perceptive referees for their comments. Work on this project has been supported in part by a Collaborative Research Fellowship by the American Council of Learned Societies, by a UC President’s Fellowship in the Humanities, and by the Division for Arts and Humanities at the University of California, San Diego. Some of the material in this essay has its origin in [47].

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Given this formidable success of the classical theory, one might wonder why we need a quantum theory of gravity at all. There are good reasons to think that we do, but they do not fully align with the standard lore one finds in the physics literature ([49] §1).

  2. 2.

    For a very recent critical view, see, e.g. [25].

  3. 3.

    Cf. ([46], Appendix E.2). A locus classicus for the Cauchy problem in GR is [12]; a more recent survey article is [19].

  4. 4.

    A useful introduction to the Lagrangian and the Hamiltonian formulation of GR is given in ([46], Appendix E). Wald’s textbook of 1984 only deals with the ADM version of Hamiltonian GR and, as time travel was not yet invented in 1984, does not treat Ashtekar’s version, pioneered in 1986.

  5. 5.

    Of course, for most cases we care about, Hamiltonian theories afford a corresponding equivalent Lagrangian theory, and vice versa. Currently, a debate rages in philosophy of physics over which of the two, if any, is more fundamental or more perspicuous. Nothing I say here should be taken to entail a stance in that debate.

  6. 6.

    There are, of course, purely internal degrees of freedom of particles, such as classical spin, which admit of a Hamiltonian treatment without the system necessarily being extended in space. Now, even a point particle with internal degrees of freedom is at least a physical system in space, and it certainly also evolves over external time.

  7. 7.

    In connection with what follows, Chapter 1 of [21] is recommended reading. For a less formal and hence more accessible treatment of the problem of time, cf. ([23], §2) and references therein. Cf. also Kiefer’s contribution to this collection.

  8. 8.

    For more details on how the constraints arise in some Hamiltonian systems, see ([21], Ch. 1). My exposition largely follows this reference.

  9. 9.

    They are not referred to as tertiary, quaternary etc. constraints, but only collectively as ‘secondary’ constraints.

  10. 10.

    Cf. ([21], §1.2.1).

  11. 11.

    Cf. ([21] §1.2.2).

  12. 12.

    Cf. ([8] §10.2.2).

  13. 13.

    Second-class constraints can be regarded as resulting from fixing the gauge of a ‘larger’ system with an additional gauge invariance. They can be replaced by a corresponding set of first-class constraints which capture the additional gauge invariance. Second-class constraints are thus eliminable. In fact, in some cases, it may prove advantageous to thus ‘enlarge’ a system as this permits the circumvention of some technical obstacles ([21] §1.4.3), albeit at the price of introducing new ‘unphysical’ degrees of freedom. Without loss of generality, we can thus consider a Hamiltonian system whose constraints are all first-class.

  14. 14.

    This manner of counting the physical degrees of freedom is well defined for any finite number of degrees of freedom, and perhaps for countably many too. For uncountably many degrees of freedom, new subtleties arise. Cf. ([21] §1.4.2).

  15. 15.

    See ([46] §4.4b); cf. also ([46] 266) for a slightly different way of calculating the degrees of freedom of the gravitational field.

  16. 16.

    For an explanation of the failures of determinism in this setting, cf. ([47] §4.1), on which the past few pages have been based. Also, and at the peril of burying an absolutely central point in a footnote, this severance of space and time threatens the general covariance so central to GR. How general covariance gets implemented in Hamiltonian GR and the subtleties that arise in doing so are discussed in ([47] §4.4). What follows explicates the gist of this implementation.

  17. 17.

    For a somewhat rigorous execution in the case of the so-called ADM and Ashtekar-Barbero versions of Hamiltonian GR, cf. [47], §4.2.1 and §4.2.2, respectively.

  18. 18.

    A spacetime diffeomorphism is a one-to-one and onto \(C^\infty \)-map from \(\mathscr {M}\) onto itself which has a \(C^\infty \)-inverse. Diffeomorphisms induce transformations in the fields defined on the manifolds. Intuitively, a map between manifolds is active if it ‘moves around’ the points without recourse to any coordinate system. Thus, an active transformation is not a change in coordinate systems, but a transformation pushing around the physical fields on the manifold. But this metaphorical picture should be enjoyed with the adequate mathematical caution.

  19. 19.

    This is the received view, but it should be noted that there has been recent dissent, e.g. in ([14] §3).

  20. 20.

    For a detailed analysis and justification, cf. ([47] §3, particularly §3.2).

  21. 21.

    For a discussion of philosophical reactions to this situation, cf. ([23] §2.3).

  22. 22.

    For a thorough introduction to LQG, cf. [34]; for the mathematical foundations, cf. [44]. [35] is a recent review article.

  23. 23.

    For a more systematic explication of global hyperbolicity and neighbouring concepts, see ([41] 593).

  24. 24.

    A more detailed analysis of dynamics in LQG can be found in ([47] §5.3).

  25. 25.

    For the technical background of this basis and its interpretation, cf. ([35] §2.3).

  26. 26.

    More precisely, they are represented by labelled graphs embedded in some background space. Thus, they are not invariant under spatial diffeomorphisms, i.e., when they are ‘pushed around’ on the embedding manifold. In order to fully solve the diffeomorphism constraints, then, we need equivalence classes of spin network states under three-dimensional diffeomorphisms on the background manifold. Sometimes, these equivalence classes, represented by abstract labelled graphs, are called ‘s-knot states’ in the literature. So I am being slightly sloppy by using the locution ‘spin network states’ ambiguously.

  27. 27.

    It should be kept in mind, however, that these operators are not Dirac observables and should therefore be taken with a grain of salt. They are partial observables in the sense of [33].

  28. 28.

    Cf. e.g. [28].

  29. 29.

    Cf. Figure 1 in [22].

  30. 30.

    Cf. Section 4. Cf. also ([28] §2) who give a related reason.

  31. 31.

    This does not entail that the fundamental non-localities could not have observable consequences, such as those proposed by [32].

  32. 32.

    For an up-to-date review on emergent properties, cf. [31].

  33. 33.

    At least at the level of ordinary quantum mechanics; in relativistic quantum theories, matters become more subtle. Cf. ([38] §2.2).

  34. 34.

    Strictly speaking, LQG basic variables are the holonomies and fluxes introduced in §2.1, which are not identical to the connection and the canonically conjugate electric field of the connection representation but are constructed from them.

  35. 35.

    The remainder of this section draws on ([47] §9).

  36. 36.

    Consider the n-body problem: while the phase space of states of an n-particle system in a physical space of m dimensions is topologically \(\mathbb {R}^{2mn}\) and therefore finite-dimensional in classical mechanics, the corresponding quantum space of states is the infinite-dimensional Hilbert space \(L^2(\mathbb {R}^{mn})\), the space of square-integrable functions on \(\mathbb {R}^{mn}\).

  37. 37.

    No attempt shall be made to substantially consider the wider literature on the topic. Cf. [43] for an analysis of various proposals for reduction as an inter-theoretic relation, with a particular eye on the physical sciences.

  38. 38.

    The clause “appropriately related quantities in the theory to be approximated” in Definition 6 above occludes substantive work that must be completed to achieve such “appropriate relation”. I am grateful to Erik Curiel for pushing me on this point—I most certainly deserve the pushing here.

  39. 39.

    I wish to thank Jeremy Butterfield for suggesting this relaxation.

  40. 40.

    Thanks to Erik Curiel for holding me to task here.

  41. 41.

    For a more thorough discussion of Landsman’s argument, cf. ([47] §9.2.1).

  42. 42.

    For reviews of decoherence, see [7] and [40].

  43. 43.

    For a review, cf. [39] and ([44] §11.2). Thiemann’s book also discusses weave states in §11.1 and the photon Fock states in §11.3.

  44. 44.

    As ([44] §11) points out, there are deep connections between the various semi-classical programmes.

  45. 45.

    For an intuitive introduction, see ([34] §6.7.1). The picture is that of the gravitational field like a (quantum cloud of) fabric(s) of weaves which appears to be smooth if seen from far but displays a discrete structure if examined more closely. Hence weave states.

  46. 46.

    The ‘upper case’ spin network states \(|S\rangle \) live in \(\mathscr {K}^\star \), the pre-kinematical Hilbert space, i.e. the Hilbert space containing all spin network states which solve the Gauss constraints, but not necessarily the spatial diffeomorphism constraints. Thus, the spin network states in \(\mathscr {K}^\star \) are not represented by abstract graphs, as are those in the full kinematical Hilbert space \(\mathscr {H}_K\), but as embedded graphs on a background manifold. This choice is just conveniently following the established standard in the literature on weave states; we will see below in Footnote 47 that this poses no problem as everything can be directly carried over to the spatially diffeomorphically invariant level.

  47. 47.

    The weave states as introduced above have merely been defined at the pre-kinematic level, i.e. they are not formulated in terms invariant under spatial diffeomorphisms (cf. also Footnote 46). The reason for this choice lies mostly in that this is the canonical choice in the literature, but also because in this way, the weave states can be directly related to three-metrics, rather than equivalence classes of three-metrics. This, however, does not constitute a problem whatsoever, as the characterization of weave states carries over into the context of diffeomorphically invariant spin network states in \(\mathscr {H}_K\), as follows. If we introduce a map \(P_{\text{ diff }}: \mathscr {K}^\star \rightarrow \mathscr {H}_K\) which projects states in \(\mathscr {K}^\star \) related by a spatial diffeomorphism unto the same element of \(\mathscr {H}_K\), then the state \(\mathscr {H}_K\ni |s\rangle = P_{\text{ diff }} |S\rangle \) is a weave state of the classical three-geometry \([q_{ab}]\), i.e., the equivalence class of three-metrics \(q_{ab}\) under spatial diffeomorphisms, just in case \(|S\rangle \) is a weave state of the classical three-metric \(q_{ab}\) as defined above.

  48. 48.

    For details, cf. ([47] 181).

References

  1. Abhay Ashtekar and Jerzy Lewandowski. Relation between polymer and Fock excitations. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 18:L117–L128, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Abhay Ashtekar and Jerzy Lewandowski. Quantum theory of geometry I: Area operators. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 14:A55–A81, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Abhay Ashtekar and Jerzy Lewandowski. Quantum theory of geometry II: Volume operators. Advances in Theoretical and Mathematical Physics, 1:388–429, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Abhay Ashtekar and Jerzy Lewandowski. Quantum field theory of geometry. In Tian Yu Cao, editor, Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Field Theory, pages 187–206, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Abhay Ashtekar, Carlo Rovelli, and Lee Smolin. Weaving a classical metric with quantum threads. Physical Review Letters, 69:237–240, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Abhay Ashtekar, Stephen Fairhurst, and Joshua L Willis. Quantum gravity, shadow states, and quantum mechanics. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 20:1031–1062, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Guido Bacciagaluppi. The role of decoherence in quantum theory. In Edward N. Zalta, editor, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2012. URL http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-decoherence/.

  8. Gordon Belot and John Earman. Pre-Socratic quantum gravity. In Craig Callender and Nick Huggett, editors, Physics Meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, pages 213–255. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Jeremy Butterfield and Chris Isham. On the emergence of time in quantum gravity. In Jeremy Butterfield, editor, The Arguments of Time, pages 111–168. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jeremy Butterfield and Christopher Isham. Spacetime and the philosophical challenge of quantum gravity. In Craig Callender and Nick Huggett, editors, Physics Meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, pages 33–89. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Craig Callender and Nick Huggett. Introduction. In Craig Callender and Nick Huggett, editors, Physics Meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, pages 1–30. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Yvonne Choquet-Bruhat and James W York, Jr. The Cauchy problem. In Alan Held, editor, General Relativity and Gravitation: One Hundred Years After the Birth of Albert Einstein, pages 99–172. Plenum Press, New York, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Erik Curiel. Against the excesses of quantum gravity: A plea for modesty. Philosophy of Science, 68(3):S424–S441, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Erik Curiel. General relativity needs no interpretation. Philosophy of Science, 76(1):44–72, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Lokenath Debnath and Piotr Mikusiński. Introduction to Hilbert Spaces with Applications. Academic Press, San Diego, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  16. John Earman. Tracking down gauge: An ode to the constrained Hamiltonian formalism. In Katherine Brading and Elena Castellani, editors, Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections, pages 140–162. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  17. John Earman. The implications of general covariance for the ontology and ideology of spacetime. In Dennis Dieks, editor, The Ontology of Spacetime, pages 3–23. Elsevier, Amsterdam, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  18. John Earman. Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. Oxford University Press, New York, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Helmut Friedrich and Alan Rendall. The Cauchy problem for the Einstein equations. Lecture Notes in Physics, 540:127–224, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Paul R Halmos. Introduction to Hilbert Space and the Theory of Spectral Multiplicity. Chelsea Publishing Company, New York, 1951.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Marc Henneaux and Claudio Teitelboim. Quantization of Gauge Systems. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Nick Huggett and Christian Wüthrich. Emergent spacetime and empirical (in)coherence. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44:276–285, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Nick Huggett, Tiziana Vistarini, and Christian Wüthrich. Time in quantum gravity. In Adrian Bardon and Heather Dyke, editors, A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, pages 242–261. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Claus Kiefer. Quantum gravity: whence, whither? In Felix Finster, Olaf Müller, Marc Nardmann, Jürgen Tolksdorf, and Eberhard Zeidler, editors, Quantum Field Theory and Gravity: Conceptual and Mathematical Advances in the Search for a Unified Framework, pages 1–13. Springer, Basel, 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Vincent Lam and Michael Esfeld. A dilemma for the emergence of spacetime in canonical quantum gravity. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44:286–293, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Nicolaas P Landsman. Between classical and quantum. In Jeremy Butterfield and John Earman, editors, Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 2: Philosophy of Physics, pages 417–553. Elsevier B.V., Amsterdam, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  27. John Byron Manchak. What is a physically reasonable space-time? Philosophy of Science, 78:410–420, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Fotini Markopoulou and Lee Smolin. Disordered locality in loop quantum gravity states. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 24:3813–3823, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Tim Maudlin. Thoroughly muddled McTaggart: Or how to abuse gauge freedom to generate metaphysical monstrosities. Philosophers’ Imprint, 2(4), 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Brian McLaughlin. Emergence and supervenience. Intellectica, 2:25–43, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Timothy O’Connor and Hong Yu Wong. Emergent properties. In Edward N. Zalta, editor, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2015. URL http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/.

  32. Chanda Prescod-Weinstein and Lee Smolin. Disordered locality as an explanation for the dark energy. Physical Review D, 80:063505, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Carlo Rovelli. Partial observables. Physical Review D, 65:124013, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Carlo Rovelli. Quantum Gravity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Carlo Rovelli. A new look at loop quantum gravity. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 28:114005, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Carlo Rovelli and Lee Smolin. Discreteness of area and volume in quantum gravity. Nuclear Physics B, 442:593–622, 1995a. Erratum: Nuclear Physics B, 456:734.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Carlo Rovelli and Lee Smolin. Spin networks and quantum gravity. Physical Review D, 52:5743–5759, 1995b.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Laura Ruetsche. Interpreting Quantum Theories: The Art of the Possible. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Hanno Sahlmann, Thomas Thiemann, and Oliver Winkler. Coherent states for canonical quantum general relativity and the infinite tensor product extension. Nuclear Physics B, 606:401–440, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Maximilian Schlosshauer. Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechancis. Reviews of Modern Physics, 76:1267–1305, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Chris Smeenk and Christian Wüthrich. Time travel and time machines. In Craig Callender, editor, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time, pages 577–630. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Lee Smolin. Generic predictions of quantum theories of gravity. In Daniele Oriti, editor, Approaches to Quantum Gravity: Toward a New Understanding of Space, Time and Matter, pages 548–570. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Marshall Spector. Concepts of Reduction in Physical Science. Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Thomas Thiemann. Modern Canonical Quantum General Relativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Madvahan Varadarajan. Fock representations from \(U(1)\) holonomy algebras. Physical Review D, 61:104001, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Robert M Wald. General Relativity. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Christian Wüthrich. Approaching the Planck Scale from a Generally Relativistic Point of View: A Philosophical Appraisal of Loop Quantum Gravity. PhD thesis, University of Pittsburgh, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Christian Wüthrich. When the actual world is not even possible. Manuscript, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Christian Wüthrich. A la recherche de l’espace-temps perdu. In Soazig Le Bihan, editor, Précis de philosophie de la physique, pages 222–241. Vuibert, Paris, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Wüthrich .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wüthrich, C. (2017). Raiders of the Lost Spacetime. In: Lehmkuhl, D., Schiemann, G., Scholz, E. (eds) Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories. Einstein Studies, vol 13. Birkhäuser, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4939-3210-8_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4939-3210-8_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Birkhäuser, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4939-3209-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4939-3210-8

  • eBook Packages: Physics and AstronomyPhysics and Astronomy (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics