Skip to main content

Madness and Alienation

  • Chapter
The Myth of Neuropsychiatry
  • 48 Accesses

Abstract

Local symmetry offers some hope for mind-body rapprochement in a way that transcends the pitfalls of older philosophical models. Locally invariant principles retain the positive features of neutral monism as a “flat” linear limit but also include nonlinear “curvature” to make room for intrinsic intentionality Gauge field concepts thus get us a fair distance beyond the horizon of neuropsychiatry However, in the form presented so far, local subject-object symmetry still has a few inadequacies that need more ironing out. This can be done by generalizing the concept of an intentional gauge field yet further.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Searle, Minds, Brains and Science, pp. 39, 60.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind, pp. 335–339.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Stuart Shapiro and Saul Teukolsky, “Black Holes, Naked Singularities and Cosmic Censorship,” American Scientist 79 (July-August, 1991), pp. 330–343.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Physical gauge fields can include not only cusplike singularities but also other anomalies resembling plateaus and jug handles. Analogies to these additional structures, in the setting of an intentional gauge field, might conceivably represent nonpsychotic mental disturbances like neuroses and personality disorders. They may therefore merit further investigation.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Capra, pp. 171, 377–381.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Michel Foucault, Mental Illness and Psychology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987), p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A. J. Ayer, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century (New York: Vintage 1982), p. 214.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Collinson, pp. 128–130.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Flew, p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, pp. 257–259.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Flanagan, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hearnshaw, p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Herbert Marcuse, Negations (London: Free Association Books, 1988), pp. 58–60.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Priest, 198–199, 207.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Robert Solomon, Continental Philosophy Since 1750 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 129–138.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1978), p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Marcuse, Negations, pp. 58–60.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Priest, pp. 198–199, 207.

    Google Scholar 

  20. F. David Peat, Superstrings and the Search for the Theory of Everything (Chicago: Contemporary Books, 1988), p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Penrose, “The Geometry of the Universe,” in Steen, ed., Mathematics Today, pp. 108–109.

    Google Scholar 

  22. If the elemental “point” in an intentional gauge field is ontic in character, then that point’s expansion into a torsional ‘line may correspond to Heidegger’s concept of self-transcendent existence or Dasein (Barrett, Irrational Man, pp. 218–222, 226).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Peat, pp. 163–273.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Penrose, “The Geometry of the Universe,” pp. 122–124.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Roger Penrose, “Minds, Machines and Mathematics,” in Blakemore and Greenfield, eds., Mindwaves, p. 274.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Peat, pp. 168–169.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, p. 361.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Priest, pp. 82, 208–209.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Barrett, The Death of the Soul, pp. 44–46.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 204–205.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Scruton, Prom Descartes to Wittgenstein, p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Barrett, The Death of the Soul, pp. 64, 114–115.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 222–234.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Priest, pp. 80–97.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, pp. 165–180.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Barrett, The Death of the Soul, p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  38. The rising accord given to neutral monism in modern thought has heightened this blurring. Some modern versions of neutral monism have even tried to replace numbers with the self as their invariant, leading to new variations on the infinite regressions of global epistemic symmetry (Priest, pp. 170–182).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Goodman, pp. 554–558.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Koestler, p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Capra, p. 373.

    Google Scholar 

  42. A threefold approach to representations of reality is not new. Karl Popper, for example, has advocated his own “three-world” metaphysical construct, consisting not of a simple matter-mind dualism but instead of physics, consciousness, and “objective” knowledge as a triad (Hutchinson, p. 26).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Hearnshaw, pp. 284, 286–288.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Koestler, pp. 34, 70–71.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 36–37, 379.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Although scientists like Premack and Gardner have trained chimpanzees to communicate in sign language, their achievement falls short of human language acquisition, which is spontaneous (Hearnshaw, pp. 261–262.)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Hearnshaw, pp. 270–271, 282–284, 287–289.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Linguistic bewitchment has habitually plagued the philosophy of mind and its intellectual progeny. Even Plato fell under the spell of words, but modern philosophers in particular have been seduced by their false potential. The critical seductions occurred in the eighteenth century, when Vico made the overblown claim that language determines all the properties of thought and Berkeley dubbed language as the glue holding together all ideational reality. In the 1850s, de Saussure formally dedicated himself to a specialized study of language by creating the discipline of philology. By 1950, researchers were diligently applying tools from information theory, particularly with regard to redundancy and noise, to language. These developments induced even skeptics like Skinner to accept language as a subject of singularly crucial psychological concern. With language then fully in the limelight, attempts at linguistic simulations on machines sprang up through programs such as SHIRDLU and proposals that consciousness itself is an encoded language (Hearnshaw, pp. 265–267, 271, 276, 286–289, 294; Oldroyd, p. 12; Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 100, 104; Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 192–193).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Koestler, pp. 57, 226–227, 231–266.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, p. xv.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 308, 368.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 293–294.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Priest, pp. 57–58, 62–63.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Jonathan Turner, “Mead, George Herbert,” in Kuper and Kuper, eds., The Social Science Encyclopedia, p. 508.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Schellenberg, pp. 38–62.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Priest, p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Flew, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Losee, pp. 131–132.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Priest, pp. 37–43.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Collinson, pp. 145–150.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Flew, pp. 374–377.

    Google Scholar 

  62. “Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 811.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Priest, pp. 56–64.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Flew, pp. 309–310.

    Google Scholar 

  65. T. R. Miles, “Ryle, Gilbert,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 691–692.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 143–153.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Priest, pp. 35–64.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Albert Gilgen, “Skinner, Burrhus F., ” in Kuper and Kuper, eds., The Social Science Encyclopedia, pp. 752–753.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Schellenberg, pp. 87–111.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Flanagan, pp. 99–103.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Oldroyd, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 104–105.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 192–193.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Gerald Grob, “Origins of DSM-I: A Study in Appearance and Reality,” American Journal of Psychiatry 148:4 (April 1991), p. 421.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  75. The psychiatrist’s handling of violence in particular has depended on wider social contexts and demands. There are few reliable ways of predicting whether specific persons are prone to future violent behavior. Nevertheless, psychiatrists working as agents of society must often act in presumptive haste in deciding whether to incarcerate potentially assaultive patients [Carl Sherman, “MDs Urged to Take Lead Role in Efforts to Reduce Violence,” Clinical Psychiatry News (January 1993), p. 23; Tardiff, p. 496].

    Google Scholar 

  76. Eichelman, p. 491.

    Google Scholar 

  77. William Glazer, “Psychiatry and Medical Necessity,” Psychiatric Annals 22:7 (July 1992), p. 366.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Calvin Pierce, “APA Ready to Launch Practice Guidelines Era,” Clinical Psychiatry News 20:6 (June 1992), pp. 1, 22.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Measuring Psychiatry’s Cost-Effectiveness: When a Dollar Saved Is Not a Dollar Earned, Psychiatric News (19 June 1922), p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Tardiff, pp. 493, 496, 498.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Hearnshaw, pp. 246–249.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid., pp. 124, 129, 130, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  83. There also appeared at this time internationally oriented journals, including the Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologic der Sinnesorgane, Journal de Psychologie normal et pathologique, British journal of Psychology, and L’Année Psychologique.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Hearnshaw, pp. 134, 137–138.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Training under Wundt helped to influence Emil Kraepelin in favor of institutional settings and concrete experimental methods. Kraepelin also came to see mental illnesses as collective categories. His method of gathering statistical data according to epidemiologic principles at the turn of the century first created concepts of mental illnesses as reified entities. Alzheimer, Nissl, Brodmann, and the other members of Kraepelin’s neuropsychiatric department spread his ideas throughout the universities of Europe. His clinical approaches eventually also took root across the Atlantic in the United States, where early acceptance of statistical, epidemiological approaches to research prompted the predecessor of the American Psychiatric Association to endorse “a uniform system to gather data on mental diseases and mental hospitals.” Psychiatrists became even more prone to deal with patients as “uniform” collective categories during their military experiences in World War II. Consequently, by the time the first Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (DSM-I) appeared in 1952, the committee responsible for its publication had embraced the use of standardized diagnostic categories. The committee’s chairman stated that “accurate diagnosis is the keystone of appropriate treatment and competent prognosis” while downplaying concerns that standardized categories would jeopardize the understanding of individual patients. With the development of later DSM versions, particularly those in use since the 1970s, categorization and description have become paramount. Many alarmed practitioners have voiced the concern that these developments will completely remove from psychiatry’s ken the individual patient’s life history, his inner experiences and suffering, and their subjective impact. Symbolic, schematic excesses of disease taxonomy carry the danger of expanding to vaporize personal meaning completely, leaving the arbitrariness of semantic emptiness and vacuous protocols and routines. Hierarchical lumping of phenomena by DSM harks back to the most primitive kinds of thought, which merely pigeonhole phenomena instead of really explaining them. Past historical examples from protoscience include the arbitrary categories into which the ancients forced their physical constructs and the pre-Darwinian classes of plants and animals catalogued by Carolus Linneaus [Andreasen, The Broken Brain, p. 14; Jacob Bronowski, The Common Sense of Science (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), p. 50; Flanagan, pp. 76, 128; Grob, pp. 421–426, 427–430; George N. Raines, quoted in Grob, p. 430; Mitchell Wilson, “DSM-III and the Transformation of American Psychiatry: A History,” American Journal of Psychiatry 150:3 (March 1993), pp. 399–410; Winson, p. 63; Zangwill, “Kraepelin” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 414].

    Google Scholar 

  86. Hearnshaw, pp. 137–140, 141–143.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ibid., pp. 271, 273–274.

    Google Scholar 

  88. “Big Brother May Soon Be Another Party to Every Drug Prescription Transaction,” Psychiatric News (3 July 1992), pp. 4, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  89. “Measuring Psychiatry’s Cost-Effectiveness,” p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Roger Coleman, “Utilization Management and Quality Care,” Psychiatric Annals 22:7 (July 1992), pp. 356–360.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Jan Fawcett, “Utilization Management—We Don’t Have to Love It—We’ve Got to Learn About It,” Psychiatric Annals 22:7 (July 1992), p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Daniel Moore, “Utilization Management and Outpatient Treatment,” Psychiatric Annals 22:7 (July 1992), pp. 373–377.

    Google Scholar 

  93. “Psychotherapy Under the Knife,” U. S. News and World Report (24 May 1993), p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Joyce Edward and Karen Shore, “The Trauma of Managed Mental Health Care,” New York Times (15 February 1993), p. A14.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Janet Kamin, “When Managed Care Manages Psychotherapy,” New York Times (13 May 1993), p. A22.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Elisabeth Rosenthal, “Insurers Second-Guess Doctors, Provoking Debate Over Savings,” The New York Times (24 January 1993), pp. 1, 22.

    Google Scholar 

  97. “Big Brother,” pp. 4, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Fawcett, p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Glazer, pp. 363–365.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Moore, pp. 373–377.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Harold Alan Pincus and Theodora Fine, “The Anatomy’ of Research Funding of Mental Illness and Addictive Disorders,” Archives of General Psychiatry 49 (July 1992), p. 578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  102. “Measuring Psychiatry’s Cost-Effectiveness,” p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Eccles, pp. 351–353.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Flanagan, pp. 201, 203–206.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Erich Fromm, The Sane Society (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1955), p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Goodman, p. 560.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Eysenck, Decline and Fall of the Freudian Empire, p. 204.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Barrett, Irrational Man, p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Norman O. Brown, Life Against Death (Middletown: Wes-leyan University Press, 1959), p. 253.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Flanagan, p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Freedman and van Nieuwenhuizen, pp. 132, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Kerner, pp. 176–177.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Koestler, p. 228.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Kramer, pp. 442–447.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 320–323, 476–477.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 293–294, 320–323.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Priest, p. 93.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Scruton, Kant, pp. 67–68.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Koestler, pp. 309–310.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 458–460.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 238–243.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Henry Margenau, The Nature of Physical Reality (Woodbridge: Oxbow Press, 1977), pp. 427–447.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Flanagan, p. 87.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Bronowski, Magic, Science, and Civilization, p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 476–477.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Brown, p. 279.

    Google Scholar 

  129. The Campus: ‘An Island of Repression in a Sea of Freedom,’ Commentary (September 1989), pp. 18–20, 22.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Koestler, pp. 226–227, 231–266.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Doris Lessing, “Language and the Lunatic Fringe,” New York Times (26 June 1992), p. A27.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Camille Paglia, “Ninnies, Pedants, Tyrants, and Other Academics,” New York Times Book Review (5 May 1991), pp. 1, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Palmer, Does the Center Hold p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Harold Morowitz, Mayonnaise and the Origin of Life (New York: Berkeley, 1985), pp. 110–111.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Jacques Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner (Garden City: Dou-bleday, 1958), p. 338.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Genova, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Sherman, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Genova, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  139. R. Coleman, p. 360.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Glazer, pp. 362–366.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Moore, pp. 373–377.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Erica Goode and Betsy Wagner, “Does Psychotherapy Work?” 17. S. News and World Report (24 May 1993), pp. 56–65.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Janice Krupnick and Harold Alan Pincus, “The Cost-Effectiveness of Psychotherapy: A Plan for Research,” American Journal of Psychiatry 149:10 (October 1992), pp. 1295–1305.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  144. Stephen Slatkin, “Short-Term Treatment, Better Results: IS-TDP,” Psychiatric Times (March 1993), pp. 23–27.

    Google Scholar 

  145. R. Coleman, pp. 356–360.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Fawcett p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Genova, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Glazer, pp. 363–364, 366.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Moore, p. 376.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Pierce, pp. 1, 22.

    Google Scholar 

  151. “Measuring Psychiatry’s Cost-Effectiveness,” p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Ernest Becker, The Denial of Death (New York: Macmillan, 1973), pp. 72–73.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Flanagan, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Winson, pp. 135–136.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Flanagan, pp. 41, 106.

    Google Scholar 

  156. Koestler, pp. 3, 15, 130.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Fodor, p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Arnold Relman, “What Market Values Are Doing To Medicine,” Atlantic Monthly (March 1992), p. 101.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 402–403.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Arendt, pp. 7, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Capra, pp. 381–383.

    Google Scholar 

  162. Ibid., pp. 370–371.

    Google Scholar 

  163. Alastair Bruce and David Wallace, “Critical Point Phenomena: Universal Physics at Large Length Scales,” in The New Physics, ed. P. Davies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 236–267.

    Google Scholar 

  164. Kenneth Wilson, “Problems in Physics with Many Scales of Length,” Scientific American 241 (August 1979), pp. 158–179.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  165. E. T. Bell, pp. 340–361.

    Google Scholar 

  166. Bernstein and Phillips, pp. 126–127.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Freedman and van Nieuwenhuizen, pp. 132, 137.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Howard Georgi, “A Unified Theory of Elementary Particles and Forces,” Scientific American 244 (April 1981), pp. 48–49.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  169. R. I. G. Hughes, “Quantum Logic,” Scientific American 245 (Oct 1981), pp. 205, 211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  170. Kramer, pp. 304–307, 350.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Ernst Sondheimer and Alan Rogerson, Numbers and Infinity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 69–85.

    Google Scholar 

  172. Singh, pp. 85–87.

    Google Scholar 

  173. David Spergel and Neil Turok, “Textures and Cosmic Structure,” Scientific American 266 (March 1992), pp. 55, 57–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  174. t’Hooft, pp. 118, 122.

    Google Scholar 

  175. Steven Weinberg, “Unified Theories of Elementary Particle Interaction,” Scientific American 231 (July 1974), p. 54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Donald Mender

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mender, D. (1994). Madness and Alienation. In: The Myth of Neuropsychiatry. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-306-44652-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4899-6010-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics