Skip to main content

The Downside of Machine Metaphors

  • Chapter
The Myth of Neuropsychiatry
  • 47 Accesses

Abstract

Is it meaningful to ask how many subunits, circuits, and cross-connections among channels1 will turn a computer into a mind? Is it possible to measure how complicated computing machines need to be in order to attain consciousness?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Ladd, p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  2. J. Bernstein, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bronowski, The Origins of Knowledge and Imagination, p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Jacob Bronowski, A Sense of the Future (Cambridge: M.I.T. Press, 1977), p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Kline, p. 204.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Jacob Bronowski, Magic, Science, and Civilization (New York: Columbia University Press, 1978), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kline, pp. 221–222.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Koestler, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kline, pp. 190, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Flew, p. 296.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Though delineating a class through some universal defining property can create paradoxes, overall definitions also have advantages. They can handle infinite sets not tractable through definitions that simply list a finite number of constituent class elements.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Kline, pp. 187, 199, 201, 203, 205, 212, 217, 221.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, pp. 245–246.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Flew, pp. 349–350.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Mary Elizabeth Tiles, “Gödel, Kurt,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 294–295.

    Google Scholar 

  16. “Turing, Alan Mathison” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 783–784.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Douglas Hofstadter, Gödel, Escher, Bach (New York: Vintage, 1979), pp. 594–595.

    Google Scholar 

  18. These quandaries relate to the vain formalistic project of constructing an axiomatic system tightly enough to avoid inconsistencies yet loosely enough to encompass all of mathematics. The entire enterprise has proven unable to achieve either goal. Its double failure is mirrored in Gödel’s restrictions on axiomatic completeness and in the so-called Lowen-heim-Skolem theorem, which allows multiple interpretations of undefined terms in mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Max Delbruck, Mind from Matter? (Palo Alto: Blackwell, 1986), pp. 177–183.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kline, pp. 176, 181, 191, 227–228, 255, 261, 263, 267–268, 271–273.

    Google Scholar 

  21. William Barrett, The Death of the Soul (Garden City: Double-day, 1986), p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  22. J. Bernstein, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bronowski, A Sense of the Future, pp. 65, 82.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Flanagan, p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Kline, p. 263.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? pp. 124, 344.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 178, 309, 331–338, 358.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, p. 247.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Bronowski, A Sense of the Future, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Palmer, Looking at Philosopher, pp. 202–204.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Erwin Schrödinger, What Is Life?/Mind and Matter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, pp. 125–126.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Dick Teresi, “Perhaps This Universe Is Only a Test,” New York Times Book Review (5 September 1993), p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Browder, “Does Pure Mathematics Have a Relation to the Sciences?” p. 549.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, pp. 145–146, 152, 157, 162–163.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Vaclav Havel, “The End of the Modern Era,” New York Times (1 March 1992), p. E15.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, p. xiv.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Frattaroli, pp. 73–74.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Briggs and Peat, pp. 24–32.

    Google Scholar 

  40. David Bloor, “Kuhn, Thomas Samuel,” in Kuper and Kuper, eds., The Social Science Encyclopedia, pp. 432–433.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Losee, p. 203.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Oldroyd, pp. 320–327.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Bronowski, The Origins of Knowledge and Imagination, pp. 46–47.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Bronowski, A Sense of the Future, pp. 46, 86–87, 90.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Martin Gardner, “WAP, SAP, PAP & FAP: The Anthropic Cosmological Principle,” New York Review of Books (May 8, 1986), pp. 22–25.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Bronowski, The Identity of Man, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., pp. 132–133.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Hearnshaw, pp. 226–227, 230–233.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Kessen and Cahan, p. 647.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Bronowski, The Identity of Man, p. 78.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Hearnshaw, pp. 128, 132, 136–137.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Harold Morowitz, The Wine of Life (New York: Bantam, 1979), p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Hubel, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ladd, p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Winson, p. 188.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ladd, pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Kandel, pp. 1033–1036.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Eric Kandel, “Environmental Determinants of Brain Architecture and of Behavior: Early Experience and Learning,” in Principles of Neural Science, eds. Eric Kandel and James Schwartz (New York: Elsevier, 1981), pp. 625–631.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Gregory Chaitin, “Randomness and Mathematic Proof,” Scientific American 232 (May 1975), pp. 47–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Capra, pp. 123, 132, 143–144.

    Google Scholar 

  62. David Gelman, Debra Rosenberg, Paul Kandell, and Rebecca Crandall, “Is the Mind an Illusion?m” Newsweek (20 April 1992), pp. 71–72.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. x.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ibid., p. xi.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Daniel Dennett and John C. Haugeland, “Intentionality,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, p. 361.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Dennett and Haugeland, p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Intentionality has roots going back to Aristotle. Medieval Scholastics such as Saint Thomas Aquinas coined the actual term from a Latin word that means “to point at” or “extend toward.” More modern ways to address intentionality include “hermeneutic” modes of inquiry, which approach their subject matter as an interpretable “text” concealing levels of meaning that require imaginative commentary. The latter perspective forms the basis for work by such philosophers as Nietzsche, Heidegger, Gadamer, Feyerabend, Derrida, Kuhn, and, to some extent, Freud [Flanagan, p. 28; Quentin Skinner, ed., The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 6–7, 10].

    Google Scholar 

  69. Flanagan, pp. 62, 179.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Hearnshaw, pp. 233–237, 239–243.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Flanagan, p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid., p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  73. John Searle, Minds, Brains and Science (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1984), p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Flanagan, p. 376.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Flew, pp. 48–49.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Hearnshaw, p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Georges Thines, “Brentano, Franz,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 117–118.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Franz Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, as quoted in Hearnshaw, p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Flanagan, pp. 62, 179.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Searle, Minds, Brains and Sciences, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Flanagan, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid., p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  83. John Searle, “Is the Brain’s Mind a Computer Program?” Scientific American 262 (January 1990), p. 27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  84. Hearnshaw, pp. 240–241

    Google Scholar 

  85. George Kerner, Three Philosophical Moralists (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), p. 172.

    Google Scholar 

  86. William Barrett, The Illusion of Technique (Garden City: Anchor, 1976), p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Bronowski, A Sense of the Future, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Eccles, p. 348.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Flanagan, p. 336.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Goodman, p. 559.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Crick, p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Fodor, pp. 107, 122.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ladd, pp. 28–29, 31.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Hearnshaw, p. 272.

    Google Scholar 

  95. “Babbage, Charles” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Frank George, “Wiener, Norbert,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 810–811.

    Google Scholar 

  97. J. E. Young, Information Theory (New York: Wiley, 1971), pp. 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Flanagan, p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Hearnshaw, pp. 240–241.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Searle, “Is the Brain’s Mind a Computer Program?” p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Hearnshaw, pp. 240–241.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Searle, “Is the Brain’s Mind a Computer Program?,” p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Hearnshaw, pp. 275, 293.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Flanagan, pp. 107–109, 237.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Johnson-Laird, pp. 184–190.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Johnson-Laird, p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Bronowski, The Identity of Man, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Mario Bunge, Causality and Modern Science (New York: Dover, 1979), pp. 309–350.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Roger Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp. 243, 248, 249–251, 269–270, 288, 295–298.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Lawrence Wile, “Quantum Concepts,” Psychiatric Times (February 1993), p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  112. John Searle, “Minds and Brains without Programs,” in Mind-waves, eds., Colin Blakemore and Susan Greenfield (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), pp. 209–210.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Flanagan, p. 258.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Donald Mender

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mender, D. (1994). The Downside of Machine Metaphors. In: The Myth of Neuropsychiatry. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-306-44652-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4899-6010-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics