Skip to main content

Neuropsychiatry and Numbers

  • Chapter
The Myth of Neuropsychiatry
  • 47 Accesses

Abstract

Neuropsychiatrists confer a seeming validity on their ideas by linking them to numbers. The brain itself has been selected as an object of study because of its measurable dimensions: length, width, depth, weight, motion, temperature, and electrical charge. Indeed, the rising tide of neuropsychiatry might be best understood as little more than a search for one-to-one numerical correlations between mental symptoms and abnormalities within the brain. In this way, biological psychiatry tries to conform to demands of technical science for objectivity and quantitative exactitude.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Genova, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  2. E. T. Bell, pp. 20–24.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Collinson, pp. 8–10.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Flew, pp. 494–495.

    Google Scholar 

  5. “Pythagoras” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 665.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Kramer, pp. 18–40.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 16–18.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Russell, pp. 29–37.

    Google Scholar 

  9. This definition, despite use of the word “one” in the phrase “one-to-one,” is not circular. The hyphenated expression, its appearance notwithstanding, does not presuppose the actual concept of a number [Morris Kline, Mathematics, the Loss of Certainty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980), p. 223; Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, pp. 246–247].

    Google Scholar 

  10. Collinson, pp. 125–127.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Flew, p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, p. 241.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Flew, pp. 373–374.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Whitehead, Alfred North” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 809–810.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Collinson, pp. 134–138.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Flew, pp. 308–309.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gregory, “Russell, Bertrand Arthur William,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 687–688.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, pp. 6–18.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hearnshaw, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hutchinson, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Collinson, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kline, p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Kramer, pp. 627–632.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Felix Browder, “Does Pure Mathematics Have a Relation to the Sciences?” American Scientist 64 (September-October 1976), pp. 546–548.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Kline, pp. 192, 198, 227, 248.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Capra, pp. 375–376.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Collinson, pp. 47–51.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Flew, p. 495.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Oldroyd, pp. 176–182.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “Mach, Ernst” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 445.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Oldroyd, pp. 231, 234–235.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Collinson, pp. 142–144.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Oldroyd, p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hearnshaw, p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Scruton, From Descartes to Wittgenstein, p. 278.

    Google Scholar 

  36. John Losee, A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980), p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Oldroyd, pp. 275–281.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., p. 239.

    Google Scholar 

  39. William Kessen and Emily Cahan, “A Century of Psychology: From Subject to Object to Agent,” American Scientist 24 (November-December 1986), p. 647.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Hearnshaw, pp. 226–229, 231.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Flanagan, pp. 222–223.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Palmer, Does the Center Hold? p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Hearnshaw, pp. 226–227.

    Google Scholar 

  45. “Weber, Ernst Heinrich” (no author given), in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 808–809.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Fechner’s statistical innovations resulted in the methods of average error and of right and wrong cases. His experimental efforts produced a law relating the intensity of a sensation to the logarithm of a stimulus magnitude. The principle led to the acoustic decibel scale and later found parallels in observed relations between light stimulus intensities and evoked neural impulse frequencies. The logarithmic aspect of Fechner’s law ultimately gave way to S. S. Stevens’s power equation in the 1950s, but Stevens owed his methodology to Fechner’s influence (Hearnshaw, pp. 126–129).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Capra, pp. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  48. O. L. Zangwill, “Fechner, Gustav Theodor,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 258–259.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Hearnshaw, pp. 135, 137, 139–140.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Gregory, “Helmholtz, Hermann Ludwig Ferdinand von,” Gregory, ed., in The Oxford Companion, pp. 308–310.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Hearnshaw, pp. 134–137.

    Google Scholar 

  52. O. L. Zangwill, “Wundt, Wilhelm Max,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, pp. 816–817.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Kessen and Cahan, pp. 641–642.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Kerry Buckley, “Watson, John Broadus,” in The Social Science Encyclopedia, eds. Adam Kuper and Jessica Kuper (New York: Routledge, 1985), pp. 891–892.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Robert Epstein, “Watson, John Broadus,” in Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion, p. 808.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Johnson-Laird, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Kessen and Cahan, pp. 645–646.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Epstein, p. 808.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Capra, pp. 175–176.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Kessen and Cahan, p. 647.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Hearnshaw, pp. 226–227, 230–233.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Justin Weiss and Larry Seidman, “The Clinical Use of Psychological and Neuropsychological Tests,” in Nicholi, ed., The New Harvard Guide, pp. 47, 48, 58.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Frattaroli, p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Donald Mender

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mender, D. (1994). Neuropsychiatry and Numbers. In: The Myth of Neuropsychiatry. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-6010-8_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-306-44652-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4899-6010-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics