Skip to main content

Abstract

The human propensity to think in causal terms is well known (Young 1978), and the manner in which judgments about causation are made in everyday life has been studied extensively by psychologists (Einhorn and Hogarth 1986; White 1990). No doubt this propensity contributes, for better or worse, to the persistence of causal language in scientific discourse, despite some influential attempts (for example, Russell 1913) to banish such talk to the prescientific era.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Alwin, D. F., and Hauser, R. M. (1975), “The Decomposition of Effects in Path Analysis,” American Sociological Review, 40, 37–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. (1938), “The Problem of Causality,” Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 16, 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T. W. (1984), An Introduction to Multivariate Statistical Analysis ( 2nd ed. ), New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angrist, J. D., Imbens, G. W., and Rubin, D. B. (1993), “Identification of Causal Effects Using Instrumental Variables,” unpublished manuscript, Department of Statistics, Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (1982), Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basmann, R. L. (1965), “A Note on the Statistical Testability of `Explicit Causal Chains’ Against the Class of `Interdependent’ Models,” Journal of the American Statistical Association, 60, 1080–1093.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1979), Causality and Modern Science ( 3rd ed. ), New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, H. (1990), “Causes and Laws: The Asymmetry Puzzle,” in PSA 1990, Proceedings of the 1990 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1, eds. A. Fine, M. Forbes, and L. Wessels, East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T., and Stanley, J. C. (1963) 1966, Experimental and Quasi-Experimental Designs for Research, Chicago: Rand McNally.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chamberlain, G. (1982), “The General Equivalence of Granger and Sims Causality,” Econometrica, 50, 569–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cliff, N. (1983), “Some Cautions Concerning the Application of Causal Modeling,” Multivariate Behavioral Research, 18, 115–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1940) 1948, A n Essay on Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conlisk, J. (1985), Comment on “Technical Problems in Social Experimentation: Cost vs. Ease of Analysis,” by J. A. Hausman and D. A. Wise, in Social Experimentation, eds. J. A. Hausman and D. A. Wise, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 208–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, T. D., and Campbell, D. T. (1979), Quasi-Experimentation: Design and Analysis Issues for Field Settings, Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, D. R. (1958), The Planning of Experiments, New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, D. R. (1992), “Causality; Some Statistical Aspects,” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Ser. A, 155, 291–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (1988), “Probabilistic Theories of Causation,” in Probability and Causality: Essays in Honor of Wesley C. Salmon, ed. J. H. Fetzer, Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 133–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawid, A. P. (1979), “Conditional Independence in Statistical Theory” (with discussion), Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Ser. B, 41, 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, O. D. (1966), “Path Analysis: Sociological Examples”, American Journal of Sociology, 72, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, O. D. (1975) Introduction to Simultaneous Equation Models, New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Efron, B., and Feldman, D. (1991), “Compliance as an Explanatory Variable in Clinical Trials” (with discussion), Journal of the American Statistical Association, 86, 9–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn, H. J., and Hogarth, R. M. (1986), “Judging Probable Cause”, Psychological Bulletin, 99, 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engle, R. F., Hendry, D. F., and Richard, J. F. (1983), “Exogeneity,” Econometrica, 51, 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1953), “Notes on Causality,” in Readings in the Philosophy of Science, eds. H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck, New York: Appleton-Century Crofts, pp. 408–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. H. (1988), “Probabilistic Metaphysics,” in Probability and Causality: Essays in Honor of Wesley C. Salmon, ed. J. H. Fetzer, Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 109–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, F. M. (1970), “A Correspondence Principle for Simultaneous Equation Models,”Econometrica, 38, 73–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florens, J. P., and Mouchart, M. (1982), “A Note on Noncausality,” Econometrica, 50, 583–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, D. A. (1987), “As Others See Us: A Case Study in Path Analysis” (with discussion), Journal of Educational Statistics, 12, 101–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gail, H. M., Wieand, S., and Piantadosi, S. (1984), “Biased Estimates of Treatment Effects in Randomized Experiments with Nonlinear Regression and Omitted Covariates,”Biometrika, 71, 431–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasking, D. (1955), “Causation and Recipes,” Mind, 64, 479–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geweke, J. (1984), “Inference and Causality in Economic Time Series Models,” in Handbook of Econometrics (Vol. 2 ), eds. Z. Griliches and M. D. Intriligator, Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 1101–1144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1980), “Causal Systems and Statistical Hypotheses” (with discussion), in Applications of Inductive Logic, eds. L. J. Cohen and M. Hesse, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 251–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberger, A. S. (1959), Impact Multipliers and Dynamic Properties of the Klein-Goldberger Model, Amsterdam- North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1961), “A Causal Calculus I,”British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 11, 305–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1962), “A Causal Calculus II,” British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 12, 42–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, C. W. (1969), “Investigating Causal Relations by Econometric Models and Cross-Spectral Methods,” Econometrica, 37, 424–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granger, C. W. (1980), “Testing for Causality: A Personal Viewpoint,”Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 2, 329–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, C. W. (1986), Comment on “Statistics and Causal Inference,” by P. W. Holland, Journal of the American Statistical Association, 81, 967–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1972), The Philosophies of Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., and Madden, E. H. (1975), Causal Powers: A Theory of Natural Necessity, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, J. A. (1983), “Specification and Estimation of Simultaneous Equation Models,” in Handbook of Econometrics(Vol. 1), eds. Z. Griliches and M. D. Intriligator, Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 392–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. J. (1974), “Shadow Prices, Market Wages, and Labor Supply,” Econometrica, 42, 679–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. J. (1976), “The Common Structure of Statistical Models of Truncation, Sample Selection and Limited Dependent Variables and a Simple Estimator for such Models,” Annals of Economic and Social Measurement, 5, 475–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. J., and Hotz, V. J. (1989), “Choosing Among Alternative Nonexperimental Methods for Estimating the Impact of Social Programs: The Case of Manpower Training” (with discussion), Journal of the American Statistical Association, 84, 862–880.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. J., Hotz, V. J., and Dabos, M. (1987), “Do We Need Experimental Data to Evaluate the Impact of Manpower Training on Earnings ?” Evaluation Review, 11, 395–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1968), “Maximal Specificity and Lawlikeness in Probabilistic Explanation,” Philosophy of Science, 35, 116–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. W. (1986), “Statistics and Causal Inference” (with discussion), Journal of the American Statistical Association, 81, 945–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. W. (1987), Comment on “The Role of a Second Control Group in an Observational Study,” by P. R. Rosenbaum, Statistical Science, 2, 306–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. W. (1988), “Causal Inference, Path Analysis, and Recursive Structural Equation Models” (with discussion), in Sociological Methodology, 1988, ed. C. C. Clogg, Washington, D. C.: American Sociological Association, pp. 449–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. W., and Rubin, D. B. (1983), “On Lord’s Paradox,” In Principals of Modern Psychological Measurement, eds. H. Wainer and S. Messnick, Hillsdak, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 3–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739)1978, A Treatise of Human Nature,Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740) 1988, An Abstract of a Treatise of Human Nature, in An Enquiry Concerning Human UnderstandinglDavid Hume: Introduction, Notes, and Editorial Arrangement by Anthony Flew, ed. A. Flew, La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748) 1988, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, in An Enquiry Concerning Human UnderstandinglDavid Hume: Introduction, Notes, and Editorial Arrangement by Anthony Flew, ed. A. Flew, La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 53–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jöreskog, K. G. (1977), “Structural Equation Models in the Social Sciences: Specification, Estimation and Testing,” in Applications of Statistics, ed. P. R. Krishnaiah, Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 265–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Judge, G. G., Griffiths, W. E., Hall, R. C., Lütkepohl, H., and Lee, T. C. (1985), The Theory and Practice of Econometrics ( 2nd ed. ), New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempthorne, O. (1952), The Design and Analysis of Experiments, New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, D. A. (1979), Correlation and Causality, New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Learner, E. E. (1985), “Vector Autoregressions for Causal Inference?” (with discussion), in Understanding Monetary Regimes, supplement to Journal of Monetary Economics, eds. K. Brunner and A. Meltzer, pp. 255–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, R. E. (1976), “Econometric Policy Evaluation: A Critique” (with discussion), in The Phillips Curve and Labor Markets, supplement to Journal of Monetary Economics, eds. K. Brunner and A. Meltzer, pp. 19–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1974), The Cement of the Universe, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843) 1973, A System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive, in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (Vol. 7), ed. J. M. Robson, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman, J. S. (1923) 1990, “On the Application of Probability Theory to Agri-Cultural Experiments. Essay on Principles. Section 9” (with discussion), Statistical Science, 4, 465–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otte, R. (1981), “A Critique of Suppes’ Theory of Probabilistic Causality,” Synthese, 48, 167–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J., and Verma, T. S. (1991), “A Theory of Inferred Causation,” in Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the Second International Conference, eds. J. A. Allen, R. Fikes, and E. Sandewall, San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann, pp. 441–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, J. W., and Schlaifer, R. (1984), “On the Nature and Discovery of Structure” (with discussion), Journal of the American Statistical Association, 79, 9–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, J. W., and Schlaifer, R. (1988), “On the Interpretation and Observation of Laws,” Journal of Econometrics, 39, 23–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ragin, C. C. (1987), The Comparative Method, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956), The Direction of Time, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robins, J. M. (1992), “Identifiability and Exchangeability for Direct and Indirect Effects,” Epidemiology, 3, 143–155.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, J. M. (1994), “Correcting for Non-Compliance in Randomized Trials Using Structural Nested Mean Models,” forthcoming in Communications in Statistics, Ser. A.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R. (1984a), “From Association to Causation in Observational Studies: The Role of Tests of Strongly Ignorable Treatment Asignment,”Journal of the American Statistical Association, 79, 41–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R. (1984b), “The Consequences of Adjustment for a Concomitant Variable That Has Been Affected by the Treatment,” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Ser. A, 147, 656–666.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R. (1986), “Dropping Out of High School in the United States: An Observational Study,” Journal of Educational Statistics, 11, 207–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R. (1987), “The Role of a Second Control Group in an Observational Study” (with discussion), Statistical Science, 2, 292–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R. (1992), “Detecting Bias with Confidence in Observational Studies, ” Biometrika, 79, 367–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. R., and Rubin, D. B. (1983), “The Central Role of the Propensity Score in Observational Studies for Causal Effects, ” Biometrika, 70, 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. B. (1974), “Estimating Causal Effects of Treatments in Randomized and Nonrandomized Studies,” Journal of Educational Psychology, 66, 688–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. B. (1977), “Assignment to Treatment Groups on the Basis of a Covariate,” Journal of Educational Statistics, 2, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. B. (1978), “Bayesian Inference for Causal Effects: The Role of Randomization,” The Annals of Statistics, 6, 34–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. B. (1980), Comment on “Randomization Analysis of Experimental Data: The Fisher Randomization Test,” by D. Basu, Journal of the American Statistical Association, 75, 591–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. B. (1990), “Formal Modes of Statistical Inference for Causal Effects,” Journal of Statistical Planning and Inference, 25, 279–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1913), “On the Notion of Cause,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 13, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1952), “On the Definition of the Causal Relation,” Journal of Philosophy, 49, 517–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1953), “Causal Ordering and Identifiability,” in Studies in Econometric Methods, eds. W. Hood and T. Koopmans, New York: John Wiley, pp. 49–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1954), “Spurious Correlation: A Causal Interpretation,” Journal of the American Statistical Association, 49, 467–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A., and Rescher, N. (1966), “Cause and Counterfactual,” Philosophy of Science, 33, 323–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sims, C. A. (1977), “Exogeneity and Causal Ordering in Macroeconomic Models,” in New Methods in Business Cycle Research: Proceedings from a Conference, ed. C. A. Sims, Minneapolis: Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sims, C. A. (1982), “Policy Analysis with Econometric Models,” Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1, 107–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1988), “Probability and Causation,” Journal of Econometrics, 39, 53–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. L. (1990), “Problems of Specification Common to Experimental and Nonexperimental Social Research,” in Sociological Methodology, 1990, ed. C. C. Clogg, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 59–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. E. (1990), “Effect Analysis and Causation in Linear Structural Equation Models, ” Psychometrika, 55, 495–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. E. (1993), “Causation, Spurious Correlation and Recursive Structural Equation Models: A Reexamination,” unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. E. (1994), “Causal Inference in Latent Variable Models,” forthcoming in Analysis of Latent Variables in Developmental Research, eds. A. von Eye and C. C. Clogg, Newburg Park, CA: S age.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1982), “Frequency-Dependent Causation,” Journal of Philosophy, 79, 247–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1970), A Probabilistic Theory of Causality, Amsterdam- North Holland. von Wright, G. H. (1971), Explanation and Understanding, Ithaca, N. Y.: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, P. (1990), “Ideas About Causation in Philosophy and Psychology,” Psychological Bulletin, 108, 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wold, H. O. A. (1966), “On the Definition and Meaning of Causal Concepts,” in La Technique des modèles dans les sciences humaines, ed. H. O. A. Wold, Monaco: Union Européenne d’Editions, pp. 265–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. (1921), “Correlation and Causation,” Journal of Agricultural Research, 20, 557–585.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. Z. (1978), Programs of the Brain, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zellner, A. (1979) 1984, “Causality and Econometrics,” in Basic Issues in Econometrics, ed. A. Zellner, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 35–74.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1995 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sobel, M.E. (1995). Causal Inference in the Social and Behavioral Sciences. In: Arminger, G., Clogg, C.C., Sobel, M.E. (eds) Handbook of Statistical Modeling for the Social and Behavioral Sciences. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-1292-3_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-1292-3_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4899-1294-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4899-1292-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics