Skip to main content

Darwinism and Ethics

A Response to Antony Flew

  • Chapter
Book cover Darwin, Marx and Freud

Part of the book series: The Hastings Center Series in Ethics ((HCSE))

  • 797 Accesses

Abstract

What bearing should Darwinism (that is, the theory of the origin of species, including the human species, by natural selection) have on ethics (that is, on our thoughts about how we as human beings should live our lives)? This question is but a recent and specific example of the age-old and general question about the relation between our knowledge of nature and our thoughts about ethics. This broader question, in turn, presupposes prior questions, both about the nature of nature and about the nature of ethics and the good for man. A full exploration of the former would carry us into questions about change, time, energy, cause, and, ultimately, about being itself. A full exploration of the latter would involve questions about justice, nobility, freedom, virtue, duty, happiness, pleasure, and, ultimately, about good itself. Both explorations would also necessarily consider the intelligibility of what is and what is good, as well as the powers and limits of the thinking mind to discover the intelligibly true and good.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For example, in his opening paragraph, Professor Flew asserts that most of Plato’s Laws and much of the Republic “is not philosophy” except in the loose sense that opinions about general matters constitute, say, my “philosophy” of life. Would Plato, or any other genuine philosopher in the tradition, agree? Later, he makes the peculiar remark, “No philosopher has any business either to despise or not to share such longings,” that is, longings “to see things as a whole, to find some deep, comprehensive, world picture against which they may set their lives” (p. 33). One would have thought such desires were the heart of the philosophical activity itself. Does any other kind of activity deserve the name of philosophizing?

    Google Scholar 

  2. Professor Flew, against his own strictures, often appears to commit the equivalent of the naturalistic fallacy, drawing conclusions about what we should believe or hold from his descriptions of what some men do believe or hold: (1) “The two understandings of philosophy thus illustrated should both be acceptable” (p. 4; ironically, this remark is but one sentence removed from his insistence on the paramount importance of the uought-is” question); (2) “There is indeed ‘a grandeur in this view of life,’ and it is something that should be part of the world outlook of every modern person” (p. 17; Why should it? Because it is grand? Modern? True? Why, according to Professor Flew, ought we to believe what is?); (3) “He [i.e., man] no longer ought to feel separated from the rest of nature, for he is part of it” (p. 33; Professor Flew is approvingly quoting Julian Huxley). Apparently Professor Flew believes that certain kinds of sentiments or judgments are not just arbitrary projections but fitting responses called forth by the way things are.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Indeed, Aristotle explicitly denies that there are any universally valid rules of action, and says, quite enigmatically, that all of justice—including natural justice—is changeable. (Nicomachean Ethics 1104a4, 1134b30)

    Google Scholar 

  4. It is true that Lucretius gave politics and civil virtue much lower marks than did Aristotle.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For example, “the polis comes to be for the sake of life, but it exists for the sake of living well.” (Aristotle Politics 1152b29). Another example: “[S]uch ‘means’ of survival as perception and emotion are never to be judged as means merely, but also as qualities of the life to be preserved and therefore as aspects of the end. It is one of the paradoxes of life that it employs means which modify the end and themselves become part of it.” (Hans Jonas, The Phenomenon of Life [New York: Dell, 1966], p. 106.)

    Google Scholar 

  6. See, for example, his discussion of what he calls “the teaching of nature” in the “Sixth Meditation” (Meditations) and in The Passions of the Soul.

    Google Scholar 

  7. ”Teleology and Darwin’s The Origin of Species: Beyond Chance and Necessity?” in Organism, Medicine and Metaphysics, ed. Stuart Spicker (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978), pp. 97–120. This article also elaborates on the remarks of the rest of this paragraph.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bearing on this subject of ascent, see the beautiful book Animal Forms and Patterns by the Swiss biologist, Adolf Portmann (New York: Schocken Books 1967). See also the very provocative writings of C. H. Waddington, especially The Ethical Animal (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See note 12.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For an excellent rebuttal to “evolutionary ethics,” see C. S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man (New York: Macmillan, 1947), especially chap. 2, “The Way.”

    Google Scholar 

  11. See, for example, Antonio Moreno, “Some Philosophical Considerations on Biological Evolution,” The Thomist, 37:417–54, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 The Hastings Center

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kass, L.R. (1984). Darwinism and Ethics. In: Caplan, A.L., Jennings, B. (eds) Darwin, Marx and Freud. The Hastings Center Series in Ethics. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4684-7850-1_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4684-7850-1_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4684-7852-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4684-7850-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics