Skip to main content

Genetic Alteration of Embryos

The Ethical Issues

  • Chapter
Genetics and the Law III

Abstract

Sometime in the next two years, clinical trials with human gene therapy will begin.1 The trials will be aimed at two rare, very serious single-gene defects. One is Lesch-Nyhan syndrome, a serious and nontreatable disesase characterized by mental retardation, cerebral palsy, self-mutilation, and an accumulation of uric acid in the body. The other is adenosine deaminase deficiency, a disease of the immune system that leads to early death. Like most single-gene defects, they cause their ill effects because the gene essential to turning on the production of a crucial enzyme is missing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Schmeck, H., Treatment of genetic defects is nearing, New York Times (Apr. 10, 1984), 17; Grobstein, C, Gene therapy: Proceed with caution, The Hastings Center Report (Apr. 1984), 13.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Schmeck, n. 1, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Kolata, G., Gene therapy method shows promise, Science 223:1376–9 (1984).

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  4. Schmeck, n. 1, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  5. An account of the Cline affair is presented in the Gore Hearings, pp. 442–460. See n. 9, infra.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Schmeck, n. 1, supra ,reported that the IRB at the University of California at San Diego has approved a trial in carefully selected patients. The Recombinant DNA Advisory Committee of NIH has not yet approved the research but has announced plans to begin reviewing gene therapy on humans. Chronicle of Higher Education (January 4, 1984) 17.

    Google Scholar 

  7. McKusick, V., Diseases of the Genome, JAMA 252:1041 (1984); Bishop, J., Scientists are focusing on genes predisposing people to illnesses, Wall Street Journal (Sept. 12, 1984), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Of course, prevention by means other than gene therapy could occur (E.G., exercise or diet) once the predisposing gene is identified.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Gene Splicing (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Human Genetic Engineering, Hearings before the Subcommittee on Investigations and Oversight of the Committee on Science and Technology, U.S. House of Representative, Nov. 16, 17, 18, 1982 (hereinafter, Gore hearings).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Harsanyi, I., Gore hearings, 231–2.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Friedmann, T., Gore hearings, 275–7.

    Google Scholar 

  13. From Chance to Purpose: An Appraisal of External Human Fertilization, (1981), 116.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Despite the Ethical Advisory Board’s recommended guidelines for research with embryos, 44 Fed. Reg. 35033 (June 18, 1979), several witnesses at the Gore hearings on human embryo transfer in August 1984 continued to list experimentation as a major unsolved issue.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The idea of extracting and reinjecting fetal bone marrow is not very different from many other fetal interventions that now occur.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Robertson, J., The right to procreate and in utero fetal therapy, /. of Legal Medicine 3:333–62 (1982). But see contra., Annas and Elias, “Fetal Surgery” chapter, this volume.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  17. Ethical Advisory Board, 44 Fed. Reg. 35033 (June 18, 1979); Report of the Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilization and Embryology (“Warnock Committee”) (July 1984); Waller Committee Report.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  19. If the damage of Lesch-Nyhan disease occurs during pregnancy, it would be a candidate for gene therapy on the embryo.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bayles, MReproductive Ethics ,Prentice Hall, NJ (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gene therapy, Nature 298:416 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  22. The importance of viewing gene therapy at any level as one component of a large system of identification and treatment is also discussed by Dr. Harsanyi, n. 10, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Several technical problems now make it impossible to screen the embryo, but these undoubtedly will be removed in the future. Until embryo screening is perfected, a heterozygous couple reproducing by means of IVF could insert the missing gene in all fertilized eggs, as a way of being sure that a defective one is not implanted. Alexander Capron, Remarks at Genetics and Law Conference, April 4, 1984. Although this option may prove risky to the unaffected embryos, it may be that the extra gene will not harm them. The absence of harm would first have to be established by animal studies before it would be ethical to try it on humans.

    Google Scholar 

  24. This is true even if chorion villi sampling allows prenatal diagnosis of the fetus to occur at 8 weeks, rather than at the 15–18 weeks now required for amniocentesis.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Remarks of John Fletcher and Richard McCormack concerning the effect of the emergence of fetal therapy on our perception of the status of the fetus and our obligations to it are applicable here as well.

    Google Scholar 

  26. One may take this position either because he or she believes that the embryo is a moral entity in its own right or because he or she finds its potential to become a person deserving of respect. For a fuller exposition of these points, see Robertson, J., Procreative Liberty and Embryo Transfer (unpublished paper, available from the author).

    Google Scholar 

  27. We can imagine a scenario where four eggs are removed and fertilized. Three are implanted and one is frozen. The three do not implant, and the frozen one, on inspection, is found to have a single-gene defect that could be corrected before transfer to a uterus.

    Google Scholar 

  28. The position asserted here is that true wrongful life claims are in principle plausible but, in actuality, arise in very small percentage of handicapped births. Although there is much room for debate, as the Baby Doe controversy indicates, about whether a given handicap amounts to wrongful life, the courts have almost uniformly rejected wrongful life claims asserted on behalf of unavoidably handicapped children. The recent acceptance of limited wrongful-life claims by the California, Washington, and New Jersey Supreme Courts is only apparent. The claim has been recognized in those cases to ensure that the tortfeasor will bear the full medical and educational costs of the handicapped child. They firmly reject the claim of the child to damages for pain and suffering, which should be awarded if they adopt the position that the child has been wronged by being brought into existence.

    Google Scholar 

  29. These witnesses included Dr. Leroy Walters, pp. 388–9, and Dr. Bernard Davis, pp. 507–9.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Gore hearings, 389.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Id. at 539.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Dr. Leroy Walters, Director of the Kennedy Institute of Bioethics, made this point at the Gore hearings, 388–389.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See n. 19, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See the analysis of this issue in Robertson, J., Procreative Liberty and Embryo Transfer ,n. 25, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Because the technology must be very advanced for this issue even to arise, the person claiming the right would probably be able to replace the gene herself or himself. Should not she or he, rather than her or his parents, have the duty of doing so, if it is so important to her or him?

    Google Scholar 

  36. Abramowitz, S., A stalemate on test-tube baby research, The Hastings Center Report 14:5 (1984). See also Maker v. Roe ,432 U.S. 464 (1977); McCrae v. Harris ,448 U.S. (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  37. The right to a healthy genome could be satisfied by somatic therapy, but in many cases, the therapy will affect the germ line. There is also the question of one’s duties to a future generation.

    Google Scholar 

  38. This paragraph recapitulates the argument made at greater length in Robertson, J., Procreative liberty and the control of conception, pregnancy and childbirth, Va. L. Rev. 69:45 (1983).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 John A. Robertson

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Robertson, J.A. (1985). Genetic Alteration of Embryos. In: Milunsky, A., Annas, G.J. (eds) Genetics and the Law III. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4684-4952-5_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4684-4952-5_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4684-4954-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4684-4952-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics