Skip to main content
  • 118 Accesses

Abstract

The subordinate First Amendment status of over-the-air broadcasting is long-standing and well-known. Red Lion Broadcasting v. Federal Communications Commission (FCC) 1 authorized the Commission to require broadcasters to air material (free of charge) that the broadcaster did not wish to air. FCC v. Pacifica Foundation 2 authorized the Commission to impose sanctions on stations airing programming that the Commission deemed indecent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. 395 U.S. 367 (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  2. 438 U.S. 736 (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Miami Herald v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241 (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15 (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  5. 395 U.S. at 390.

    Google Scholar 

  6. 438 U.S. at 748.

    Google Scholar 

  7. 438 U.S. at 749.

    Google Scholar 

  8. 438 U.S. at 749.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Part IV 438 U.S. at 749.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Thomas G. Krattenmaker & L.A. Powe, Jr., Converging First Amendment Principles for Converging Communications Media, 104 Yale L.J. 1719 (1995).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Does Everyone Have to Own Everything? Wall St. J., Jan. 12, 2000, at B1.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Harry Kalven, A Worthy Tradition (Harper & Row 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Debs v. United States, 249 U.S. 211 (1919).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616 (1919).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357 (1927).

    Google Scholar 

  18. United States v. Associated Press, 52 F. Supp. 362, 372 (S.D.N.Y. 1943), aff’d, 326 U.S. 1 (1946).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Turner Broadcasting System v. FCC, [I], 512 U.S. 622, 641 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  20. United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, 120 S.Ct. 1878, 1889 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 840 (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  22. James Landis, The Administrative Process 75 (Yale Univ. Press 1938).

    Google Scholar 

  23. E.g., 47 U.S.C. §§ 303 (General Powers of the FCC), 307 (Allocation of Facilities), 309(a) (Initial Licensing), and 309(k)(Renewals). Even the new statutory framework for the transition to digital television technology incorporates the public interest standard. 47 U.S.C. § 336(e).

    Google Scholar 

  24. 47 U.S.C. § 326: “Nothing in this Act shall be understood or construed to give the Commission the power of censorship over … any radio station, and no regulation or condition shall be promulgated or fixed by the Commission which shall interfere with the right of free speech by means of radio communication.”

    Google Scholar 

  25. KFKB v. FRC, 47 F. 2d 670 (D.C. Cir. 1931); Trinity Methodist Church v. FRC, 62 F.2d 850 (D.C. Cir. 1932).

    Google Scholar 

  26. 395 U.S. at 389.

    Google Scholar 

  27. 395 U.S. 444 (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Schenck, 249 U.S. 47 (1919); Abrams, 250 U.S. at 624 (dissent); Gitlow, 268 U.S. At 672 (dissent).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Yates v. United States, 354 U.S. 298 (1957).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Gerald Gunther, Learned Hand and the Origins of the Modern First Amendment Doctrine, 27 Stan. L. Rev. 719 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hess v. Indiana, 414 U.S. 105 (1973); NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co., 458 U.S. 886 (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  32. All the gushing quotes come from Lucas A. Powe, Jr., the Warren Court and American Politics 333 (Belknap Press of Harvard Univ. Press 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  33. 395 U.S. at 376.

    Google Scholar 

  34. 35 Telecommunications Research & Action Center v. FCC, 801 F.2d 501, 508, reh’g denied, 806 F.2d 1115 (D.C. Cir. 1986), cert. denied, 482 U.S. 919 (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Thomas G. Kraitenmaker & Lucas A. Powe, Jr., Regulating Broadcast Programming 204 (MIT/AEI Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  36. NBC v. United States, 319 U.S. 190, 212 (1943).

    Google Scholar 

  37. NBC v. United States, 319 U.S. 190, 212 (1943). at 213.

    Google Scholar 

  38. 395 U.S. at 388–89.

    Google Scholar 

  39. 395 U.S. at 399.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ronald J. Krotosynski, Jr., Into the Woods: Broadcasters, Bureaucrats, and Children’s Television Programming, 45 Duke L.J. 1193, 1207 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  41. 395 U.S. at 390.

    Google Scholar 

  42. 395 U.S. at 390. at 389, 390.

    Google Scholar 

  43. 376 U.S. 254 (1964). A chilling effect argument notes the obvious. A penalty for engaging in certain actions will produce fewer such actions as well as a reluctance to engage in conduct that might be classified as within the proscribed actions. In the context of the Fairness Doctrine, the chilling effect postulated that since programming about controversial issues was penalized, there would be less of it. And there was. See Regulating Broadcasting Programming at 237–75. Contrast “Talk Radio” after repeal of the Fairness Doctrine.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241.

    Google Scholar 

  45. That emergence is discussed in Powe, The Warren Court at 303–57.

    Google Scholar 

  46. 205 U.S. 454 (1907).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Regulating Broadcast Programming at 180.

    Google Scholar 

  48. KFKB v. FRC, 47 F.2d 670, 672 (D.C. Cir 1931); Trinity Methodist Church v. FRC, 62 F.2d 850, 852 (D.C. Cir. 1932).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Zechariah Chafee, Law and Liberty in Freedom in the Modern World 98 (Horace M. Kallen ed., Coward-McCann. Inc. 1928).

    Google Scholar 

  51. Free Speech in the United States (Harvard Univ. Press 1941).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Carolene Products v. United States, 304 U.S. 144 (1938). Carolene Products, in its text and its famous “Footnote Four” suggested that the Court should not protect property rights, but should enforce the First Amendment, voting rights, and protect “discrete and insular minorities,” i.e., African-Americans and Jehovah’s Witnesses.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Free Speech in the United States at 361.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Free Speech in the United States at 361.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Mark A. Graber, Transforming Free Speech 159 (University of California Press 1991)

    Google Scholar 

  56. Mark A. Graber, Transforming Free Speech 159 (University of California Press 1991). at 161.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Chafee knew that misdistribution of economic resources biased the democratic process and wrote of “the increasing tendency for the most effective instrumentalities of communications to be bounded and shaped by persons who are often on one side of many public questions.” Zechariah Chafee, The Blessings of Liberty 108 (Lippincott 1956). Chafee’s willingness to advocate speech rights on the basis of arguments he knew were bogus is detailed as well in David Rabban, Free Speech in its Forgotten Years (Cambridge Univ. Press 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  58. Zechariah Chafee, The Blessings of Liberty 108 (Lippincott 1956).

    Google Scholar 

  59. 319 U.S. 192 (1943).

    Google Scholar 

  60. 319 U.S. at 226.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Justice Douglas did not participate.

    Google Scholar 

  62. 395 U.S. at 400.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Lee Bollinger, Images of a Free Press 72 (University of Chicago Press 1991): The Court “reconceived the fundamental theoretical underpinnings … of the relationship between the press and government.”

    Google Scholar 

  64. Lee Bollinger, Images of a Free Press 72 (University of Chicago Press 1991). at 390.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15 (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Young v. American Mini-Theaters, 427 U.S. 50 (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  67. 438 U.S. at 746. They did not state what that reason was.

    Google Scholar 

  68. There were six, but the two important ones were Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15 (1973) and Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49 (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  69. Erznoznic v. City of Jacksonville, 422 U.S. 205 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  70. Young v. American Mini-Theaters, 427 U.S. 50 (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  71. For a fuller discussion of the intersection of indecency and broadcasting see Regulating Broadcast Programming, Thomas G. Kraitenmaker & Lucas A. Powe, Jr., Regulating Broadcast Programming 204 (MIT/AEI Press, 1994), at 196–202.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 638 n.5.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 638 n.5. at 638, citing FCC v. League a/Women Voters, 468 U.S. 364, 376 n.11 (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  74. 512 U.S. 622 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  75. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241.

    Google Scholar 

  76. 512 U.S. at 649. See generally. Geoffrey R. Stone. Content Regulation and the First Amendment, 25 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 189 (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  77. First Amendment doctrine now revolves around concepts of viewpoint neutrality and content neutrality. For those who do not follow the Court, the current doctrine operates as follows. Viewpoint-based regulations are virtually per se unconstitutional. Content-based regulations are presumptively unconstitutional unless coming within certain narrow, well-defined categories: illegal advocacy, obscenity, commercial speech, libel. Regulations not based on content are invariably valid. See note 104 City of Erie v. Pap’s A.M., 120 S.Ct. 1382, 1409 (2000) on the secondary effects doctrine.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639. at 656.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639. at 639.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639. at 637–38: “We address first the Government's contention that regulation of cable television should be analyzed under the same First Amendment standard that applies to regulation of broadcast television. It is true that our cases have permitted more intrusive regulation of broadcast speakers than of speakers in other media. Compare Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367 (1969) (television), and National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U.S. 190 (1943) (radio), with Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241 (1974) (print), and Riley v. National Federation of Blind of N.C., Inc., 487 U.S. 781 (1988) (personal solicitation). But the rationale for applying a less rigorous standard of First Amendment scrutiny to broadcast regulation, whatever its validity in the cases elaborating it, does not apply in the context of cable regulation. The justification for our distinct approach to broadcast regulation rests upon the unique physical limitations of the broadcast medium. See FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364, 377 (1984); Red Lion, supra, at 388–389, 396–399; National Broadcasting Co., 319 U.S., at 226. As a general matter, there are more would-be broadcasters than frequencies available in the electromagnetic spectrum. And if two broadcasters were to attempt to transmit over the same frequency in the same locale, they would interfere with one another's signals, so that neither could be heard at all. Id., at 212. The scarcity of broadcast frequencies thus required the establishment of some regulatory mechanism to divide the electromagnetic spectrum and assign specific frequencies to particular broadcasters. See FCC v. League of Women Voters, supra, at 377 (“The fundamental distinguishing characteristic of the new medium of broadcasting…is that [b]roadcast frequencies are a scarce resource [that] must be portioned out among applicants”) (internal quotation marks omitted); FCC v. National Citizens Comm. for Broadcasting, 436 U.S. 775, 799 (1978). In addition, the inherent physical limitation on the number of speakers who may use the broadcast medium has been thought to require some adjustment in traditional First Amendment analysis to permit the Government to place limited content restraints, and impose certain affirmative obligations, on broadcast licensees. Red Lion, 395 U.S., at 390. As we said in Red Lion, “[w]here there are substantially more individuals who want to broadcast than there are frequencies to allocate, it is idle to posit an unabridgeable First Amendment right to broadcast comparable to the right of every individual to speak, write, or publish.” Id., at 388; see also Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic Nat’I Comm., 412 U.S. 94, 101 (1973).”

    Google Scholar 

  82. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639. at 638 n.5.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Turner Broadcasting I, 512 U.S. at 639. at 650.

    Google Scholar 

  84. 518 U.S. 727 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  85. 520 U.S. at 741–42.

    Google Scholar 

  86. 520 U.S. at 755.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Sable Communications. Inc. v. FCC, 492 U.S. 115 (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  88. 520 U.S. 742.

    Google Scholar 

  89. 520 U.S. 742. at 741. Justice Breyer is serious as witnessed in his dissent in United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group where he would have allowed Congress to deal with a non-problem — minors watching a signal bleed from an adult channel before 10 p.m. — without any commensurate matching of the legislative remedy.

    Google Scholar 

  90. 520 U.S. at 745.

    Google Scholar 

  91. 520 U.S. at 744.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Accord, Denver Area, 518 U.S. at 759; Sable Communications, 492 U.S. at 128; Bolger v. Youngs Drug Prods. Corp., 463 U.S. 60 (1983); Butler v. Michigan, 352 U.S. 380 (1957).

    Google Scholar 

  93. Sable Communications, 492 U.S. at 127.

    Google Scholar 

  94. 390 U.S. 629 (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  95. 475 U.S. 41 (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  96. Possibly the most absurd of the secondary effects cases is where the Court upheld Erie, Pennsylvania's ban on nude dancing (the women must wear pasties and g-strings) as a crime reduction measure. Justice Stevens's dissent wins the observation of the year award: the majority’s rationale was “a titanic surrender to the implausible.” City of Erie v. Pap’s A.M., 120 S.Ct. 1382, 1409 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  97. 521 U.S. at 867 quoting 438 U.S. 748.

    Google Scholar 

  98. 521 U.S. at 869.

    Google Scholar 

  99. 521 U.S. at 869.

    Google Scholar 

  100. 521 U.S. at 867.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Erik Barnouw, in his history of broadcasting, uses 195 pages before he gets to the Radio Act of 1927. A Tower in Babel (Oxford Univ. Press 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  102. 492 U.S. at 127.

    Google Scholar 

  103. United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, 120 S.Ct. 1878 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  104. 512 U.S. at 656.

    Google Scholar 

  105. 512 U.S. at 879.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Justice Souter expressed this when he stated that “in my own ignorance I have to accept the real possibility that ‘if we had to decide today … just what the First Amendment should mean in cyberspace … we would get it fundamentally wrong.’” Denver Area, 518 U.S. At 777.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Anyone interested in a rather unhappy demonstration of the point should read Frankfurter’s concurring opinion in Dennis v. United States, 34 I U.S. 494, 517 (1951) back to back with Justice Breyer’s majority opinion in Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Gov’t PAC, 528 U.S. 377 (2000). Their language of deference — abdication, actually — to the legislature is beyond similar; it is virtually identical.

    Google Scholar 

  108. That, of course, is unconstitutional under standard First Amendment doctrine. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  109. “[W]e decide this case by closely scrutinizing [the statute) to assure that it properly addresses an extremely important problem, without imposing, in light of the relevant interests, an unnecessarily great restriction on speech.” 518 U.S. at 743.

    Google Scholar 

  110. 518 U.S. at 744.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Power is more extensively discussed in Regulating Broadcast Programming at 221–24.

    Google Scholar 

  112. L.A. Times, Jan. 11, 2000, at C11.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Ben H. Bagdikian, The Media Monopoly (Beacon Press, 1st ed. 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  114. The Media Monopoly. at ix (2d ed. 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  115. That appears to be how the Ninth Circuit saw the matter in AT&T v. City of Portland, 216 F.3d 871, 879 (9th Cir. 2000) holding that local governments did not have jurisdiction to order open access.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Regulating Broadcast Programming at 327.

    Google Scholar 

  117. William E. Lee, Open Access, Private Interests, and the Emerging Broadband Market (Cato Institute Policy Analysis No. 379, 2000) argues that it is not wise.

    Google Scholar 

  118. The conclusion of the district judge in AT&T v. City of Portland, 413 F. Supp. 2D 1146, 1154 (D.Or. 1999), rev’d 216 F. 3d 871 (9th Cir. 2000), that Turner Broadcasting was satisfied could simply not be possible on the record before him. Turner Broadcasting required a factual record far beyond the competence of the Mount Hood Cable Regulatory Commission to create.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Regulating Broadcast Programming at 224.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Even as enthusiastic a regulator as Cass Sunstein acknowledges that “[I]t is possible to think that before long, it will not make sense to impose regulatory requirements on CBS, NBC, ABC, and Fox, any more than it makes sense to impose regulatory requirements on Newsweek, Time, The New York Times, USA Today, National Review, or The New Republic.” He immediately notes that he has “argued against this conclusion.” Television and the Public Interest, 88 Calif. L. Rev. 499, 562 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  121. 512 U.S. at 649–50.

    Google Scholar 

  122. J.M. Balkin, Media Filters, the Vi-chip, and the Foundations of Broadcast Regulation, 45 Duke L.J. 1131 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  123. Rowan v. Post Office, 397 U.S. 728, 738 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  124. Pacifica; Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U.S. 103 (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  125. 395 U.S. at 400.

    Google Scholar 

  126. FCC, Notice of Inquiry, Public Interest Obligations of TV Broadcast Licensees, 14 FCC Rcd 21633 (1999). “Free” air time for candidates is not exactly free. First, it is not free to broadcasters who are required to provide the subsidy to the candidate (or to the system in general). It is not free even to the candidates who, in order to participate, will be required to waive First Amendment rights related to campaign spending. Finally, it is not free to viewers who would prefer the programming the station would otherwise air. The migration of political broadcasting to cable may be lamentable, but unless broadcasters and cable operators are dumb, it reflects audience preferences. Thus it may be clear why politicians could be enthusiastic about free air time, but when Paul Taylor, the founder of Free TV for Straight Talk Coalition, asserts a “real hunger for political information,” it appears that a search looking for reality would find dieters instead. Lillian R. BeVier, Is Free TV for Federal Candidates Constitutional 49 (AEI Press 1998). Just try to find someone not professionally attached to politics who watched an Iowa or New Hampshire debate.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111, 131 (1942).

    Google Scholar 

  128. Quoted in BeVier, Free TV at 11. See also Reed E. Hundt, The Public’s Airwaves: What Does the Public Interest Require of Television Broadcasters?, 45 Duke L.J. 1089 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  129. BeVier, Free TV at 55.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Glen Robinson captures this perfectly. “[T[he public ownership claim here is a trope, a way of reifying the government’s claim to regulatory authority. The spectrum itself is simply a phenomenon produced by the transmission of electromagnetic energy through space ….[T]o say that [the government] owns the ‘airwaves’ is merely to give a property label to its regulatory powers….In common discourse the assertion of ownership is that assertion of a power that demands no further explanation. When it is said that the government (or the individual) can do something with its property because it ‘owns’ it, it is said by way of ending a conversation about the source of power and the reasons for acting.” Spectrum Property Law 101, 41 J.L. & Econ. 609, 620 (1998).

    Google Scholar 

  131. Professor BeVier wisely notes Takings Clause problems in the proposed regulations, but for purposes of my analysis, I am assuming that the requirements are placed on a licensee at the time of renewal of the license. BeVier, Free TV at 13–21.

    Google Scholar 

  132. BeVier, Free TV. at 38.

    Google Scholar 

  133. President Clinton thus claims that free television for candidates would restore the “broad confidence of the American people but also of the American press that comments upon it.” Clinton press conference, Mar. 11, 1997 quoted in BeVier, Free TV. at 42. The integrity of the democratic process, while overwhelmingly important, is a little hard to get a grip on since Americans vote, and losers abide the outcomes, peacefully leaving office when necessary, all of which seem to suggest the integrity of the process is well accepted. Specifics are necessary in order to know whether, say, keeping the polls open for another day or opting for cumulative voting might not be less restrictive alternatives in keeping democracy afloat. They turn out not to be because when specifics are requested, proponents claim that free air time will decrease the influence of money on politics, level the playing field, and elevate the quality of debate (by going beyond the hated thirty-second spots). These go to how we campaign, not how we vote. The specifics, of course, are also the rationales for campaign finance reform generally. What is different here is only that free air time has been added to the standard package of contribution and expenditure limitations.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Seemingly this would also authorize free advertising in the print media. But some constitutional rights are construed as not being subject to the compelling interest test and many core First Amendment rights are among them. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241; Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech, Permissible Tailoring, and Transcending Strict Scrutiny, 144 U. Penn. L. Rev. 2417 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  135. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. at 48–49.

    Google Scholar 

  136. FCC, Annual Assessment of the Status of Competition in Markets for Delivery of Video Programming, 15 FCC Rcd 978, 980-86 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  137. Broadcasting & Cable Yearbook (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  138. “Media companies continue to offer increasing amounts of video over their Web sites in the expectation that the pictures will be acceptable for the intended use or eventually improve to broadcasting or VCR quality.” 15 FCC Red at 983-84, para. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  139. 15 FCC Rcd. at 1031-32, para. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  140. United States v. Associated Press, 52 F. Supp. at 372.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Taking Turner Broadcasting at face value. But see text at note 518 U.S.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Powe, L.A. (2001). Program Content Regulation Revisited. In: Eisenach, J.A., May, R.J. (eds) Communications Deregulation and FCC Reform: Finishing the Job. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-1521-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-1521-0_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4613-5595-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4615-1521-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics