Is (Self-)Deception an Indispensable Quality of Exchange?

A New Approach to Adam Smith’s Concept
  • Caroline Gerschlager

Abstract

Ever contradicting other scholars, be they moral philosophers or economists, Adam Smith did not condemn the widespread practice of man’s exchange accompanied by deception. As his inquiry “is not concerning a matter of right, …but concerning a matter of fact”1, he assumed that illusions and deceptions are nevertheless inherent in man’s exchange. Smith gave special credit to what most of his contemporaries saw as an anomaly, affirming that “it is deception which rouses and keeps in continual motion the industry of mankind”2.

Keywords

Fatigue Manifold Assure Expense Gall 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Brown, Vivienne (1994). Adam Smith’s discourse: canonicity, commerce and conscience. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Brown, Vivienne (1997). “Mere inventions of the imagination”: A survey of recent literature on Adam Smith. Economics and Philosophy, 13, 281–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bryson, Gladys (1968) [1945]. Man and society. The Scottish inquiry of the eighteenth century. New York: Augustus M. Kelley Publishers.Google Scholar
  4. Buchanan, J.M. & Tullock, G. (1965). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
  5. Butler, B. Joseph & Sermon 1995 [1726]. “Upon self-deceit.” Sermons. In W.E. Gladstone (Ed.), The works of Joseph Butler (Vol. II, pp. 168–184). Bristol: Thoemmes Press (reprint of 1896 edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
  6. Campbell, T.D. (1971). Adam Smith’s science of morals. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.Google Scholar
  7. Costelloe, Timothy M. (1997). Contract or coincidence: George Herbert Mead and Adam Smith on self and society. History of the Human Sciences, 10(2), 81–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Danner, P.L. (1976). Sympathy and exchangeable value: Keys to Adam Smith’s social philosophy. Review of Social Economy, 43(3, December), 317–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dumont, Louis (1985) [1977]. Homo aequalis I. Genèse et épanouissement de l’idéologie économique. Gallimard.Google Scholar
  10. Dupuy, J.-P. (1992). Adam Smith et la sympathie envieuse. In J.-P. Dupuy, Le sacrifice et l’envie (pp. 75–106). Paris: Calmann-Lévy.Google Scholar
  11. Eckstein, W. (1985) (First edition in two volumes 1926) [1756]. Einleitung des Herausgebers. In Adam Smith, Theorie der ethischen Gefühle. Nach der Auflage letzter Hand übersetzt und mit Einleitung, Anmerkungen und Registern (edited by W. Eckstein). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
  12. Fiering, N.S. (1976). Irresistible compassion: An aspect of eighteenth-century sympathy and humanitari-anism. Journal of the History of Ideas, XXXVII(2), 195–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Fontaine, P. (1997) Identification and economic behaviour. Sympathy and empathy in historical perspective. Economics and Philosophy, 13, 261–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gordon, Robert M. (1995). Sympathy, simulation, and the impartial spectator. Ethics, 105 (July), 727–742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hirschman, A.O. (1987) [1977], Leidenschaften und Interessen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.Google Scholar
  16. Inayatullah, N. (1997). Theories of spontaneous disorder. In Review of International Political Economy 4(2, Summer), 319–348.Google Scholar
  17. Marshall, David (1984). Adam Smith and the theatricality of moral sentiments. Critical Inquiry, 10 (June), 592–613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Morrow, Glenn R. (1923). The significance of the doctrine of sympathy in Hume and Adam Smith. The Philosophical Review, XXXII-1923, 60–78.Google Scholar
  19. Nagel, Thomas (1983) Das objektive Selbst. In Ludwig Siep (Ed.), Identität der Person (pp. 46–67). Basel & Stuttgart: Schwabe & Co.Google Scholar
  20. Nagel, Thomas (1986) The view from nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1990) The holy lie. In P. Kerr (Ed.), The Penguin Book of Lies (pp. 265–266). London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  22. Raphael, D.D. & Macfie, A.L. (1984). Introduction. In Adam Smith, The theory of moral sentiments (pp. 1–52). Glasgow Edition.Google Scholar
  23. Ritter, J. & Gründer, K. (Eds.). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Basel: Schwabe & Co AG Verlag.Google Scholar
  24. Rothschild, Emma (1994). Adam Smith and the Invisible Hand. The American Economic Review, 84(2), 319–322.Google Scholar
  25. Smith, Adam (1976) [1776]. An inquiry into the causes of the wealth of nations (edited by R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  26. Smith, Adam 1984 [1756]. The theory of moral sentiments (Glasgow Edition, edited by D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie). Ann Arbor: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
  27. Smith, Adam (1985) (first edition in two volumes 1926). [1756]. Theorie der ethischen Gefühle. Nach der Auflage letzter Hand übersetzt und mit Einleitung, Anmerkungen und Registern (edited by W. Eckstein). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
  28. Stiglitz, Joseph 1999 [Economics 1997]. Volkswirtschaftslehre. München & Wien: Oldenbourg Verlag.Google Scholar
  29. Streminger, Gerhard (1995). Der natürliche Lauf der Dinge. Essays zu Adam Smith und David Hume. Marburg: Metropolis.Google Scholar
  30. The Oxford English Dictionary (2nd ed.. XVII, edited by J.A. Simpson & E.S.C. Weiner; 1st ed.: New English dictionary on historical principles, edited by J.A.H. Murray) (1989). Oxford et al.: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media New York 2001

Authors and Affiliations

  • Caroline Gerschlager

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations