Skip to main content

Delusion and Double Book-Keeping

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

This chapter introduces Jaspers’ understanding of delusion with regard to the question of comprehensibility and incomprehensibility. After a historical introduction, the characteristic feature of derealization is discussed and related to what Bleuler called “double book-keeping.” Then, the methodological relevance of phenomenology and the similarity between delusional states and phenomenological imagination and bracketing (as emphasized by authors such as Blankenburg) are discussed. Different stances taken toward the world already in the realm of the natural attitude can be described within the Schutzian framework of “multiple realities.” This framework is analyzed with regard to the notion of double book-keeping. It shows that some elements of schizophrenic experience can be seen—in Heideggerian terms—to preserve and reveal something about human authenticity.

“For any true grasp of delusion, it is important to free ourselves from this prejudice that there has to be some poverty of intelligence at the root of it.” (Jaspers 1963, p. 97)

“Les non-dupes errent.” (Jacques Lacan 1973/1974, seminar XXI)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Jaspers (p. 48) demurred: “It is wrong to call this book ‘the principal text of phenomenology.’ The phenomenological attitude is one point of view and one chapter has been devoted to it …. But the whole book is directed to showing that it is only one point of view among many and holds a subordinate position at that.” The chapter to which Jaspers refers is, however, 100 pages long, and many passages elsewhere in the book bear upon the phenomenological perspective.

    For helpful comments on drafts of this article, the author thanks Greg Byrom and Nev Jones.

  2. 2.

    Reimer (2011) mentions three forms of detachment in delusion: from action, emotion, and web of belief.

  3. 3.

    One important difference between the delusional and religious contexts is the idiosyncratic and isolated nature of the former as against the conventional and shared nature of the latter. The religious person may have a special role or relationship with the divine, but not so very special that it would amount to denying the very existence of other consciousnesses or other persons—as may sometimes (but only sometimes) occur in schizophrenia.

  4. 4.

    All subsequent quotations from Sophie are from emails sent to the author in 2010 or 2011. Some are in response to earlier drafts of this article. Sophie is well read in philosophy and psychology. As her reports will make clear, she not only describes her experience with considerable eloquence but is, in a sense, doing phenomenology herself. I am extremely grateful and indebted to Sophie for her crucial contribution to this article.

  5. 5.

    One recent philosopher coins the term “bimagination” (Egan 2009). Some would argue as to whether we should classify delusions as “beliefs” or not (Bortolotti 2009). From a Wittgensteinian as well as phenomenological standpoint, this emphasis on semantics and conceptual analysis can seem somewhat beside the point. The important question is: “What is it like?”

  6. 6.

    Since the translators found these phrases distracting and felt they did “not add to the sense,” they omitted them from the English translation (M p. 26).

  7. 7.

    The psychiatrist Müller-Suur (1950, p. 45) asked his paranoid and schizophrenic patients how certain they were about their delusions. Paranoiacs believed in their basic experience (Grunderlebnis) with a relative certainty, and this certainty increased only gradually with the passage of time. By contrast, his schizophrenia patients claimed to be absolutely certain (100 % certainty; as certain as that 2 × 2 = 4) about their delusions, even when these delusions seemed absurd to the listener. Müller-Suur describes the delusional certainty of schizophrenics as something that is “suffered”—that is, registered passively, akin to feeling a sensation—whereas the paranoid’s was “achieved” or “hard-earned.” (For this reference, I thank Claudia Welz, whose account is paraphrased here.)

  8. 8.

    A passage from the photographer Diane Arbus captures, on a non-psychotic, schizoid level, the sense of actual vulnerability that accompanies all but the most total experiences of derealization: “I have this funny thing which is that I’m never afraid when I’m looking in the round glass [of the camera lens]. This person could be approaching with a gun or something like that and I’d have my eyes glued to the finder and it wasn’t like I was really vulnerable. It just seemed terrific what was happening. I mean I’m sure there are limits. God knows, when the troops start advancing on me, you do approach that stricken feeling where you perfectly well can get killed” (pp. 12–13).

  9. 9.

    From article in The Advocate, statewide newsletter of N.A.M.I.—Oregon, July/August 1998, p. 7.

  10. 10.

    One issue I cannot discuss in detail is the question of motivation or defense: Is delusion something that simply happens to a patient, as a kind of affliction, or something that has a purposive or even purposeful quality? Should it, in any important sense, be understood as an act, albeit an unconscious act whose defensive or compensatory purpose may or may not be consciously recognized by the patient herself? This question is complicated by the diversity of types of delusional experience. The sheer immediacy of classic “delusional percept” might, for example, preclude the prominent compensatory motivations present in the more elaborated, late-stage delusions of a patient who (like Wölfli) finds a kind of psychic equilibrium through withdrawal from the common world. The notion that wish-fulfillment can motivate the occurrence of delusions is an ancient idea. The emphasis has typically been placed more on content than on form. In recent years preservation of self-esteem is often mentioned—as may fit the case of a patient who bolsters his self-esteem by, say, imagining himself a great scientist. Phenomenology would certainly not deny such motivations, which can indeed be important. Its particular contribution, however, is to emphasize formal or structural features of experience. In Psychology of Imagination, for example, Sartre (1950) describes the “morbid dreamer” who is drawn to the delusional world precisely because of its unreality, since this allows escape from the very “form of the real.” The delusional memories of Adolf Wölfli afford excellent examples (Sass 2004b). It is noteworthy as well that in at least some schizophrenic delusions, the unreal or subjective nature of reality (whether delusional or actual) may emerge as the overt theme of the delusion itself, which may express a certain solipsism. This was the case of Wölfli’s “omnipotence horn,” a device whereby he himself created worlds (Sass 2004b). Here, however, we must bear in mind a distinction suggested to me by a man who suffers from schizophrenia: this is between the “triumphant solipsism” expressed by Wölfli, and the mostly “miserable lonely solipsism” that was more typical of himself (email to author, May 2007).

  11. 11.

    For a similar critique, from an eminent psychiatrist, of the emphasis on supposed “inferential failures,” see Berrios (1996, p. 114).

  12. 12.

    Bégout (2005, p. 428) quotes a line from Hölderlin to which Heidegger devoted much attention: “… for the spirit is at home/Not in the beginning, not at the source. He is consumed by the homeland./Colonies loves…” (“nehmlich zu Hauss ist der Geist/Nicht im anfang, nicht an der Quell, Ihn zehret die Heimath./ Kolonien liebt …” (in Melberg 1999 p. 343; Heidegger 1996 p. 126). Hölderlin, the poet Heidegger most admired, suffered from schizophrenia in the final decades of his life; his mental troubles had begun at the time he wrote these lines (1803 or 1805) (Hölderlin 1984, p. 267).

  13. 13.

    Here is another comment Sophie made on reading a draft of this chapter: “Yes, and this is such a struggle in therapy—it would always be so much easier to simply capitulate and agree that such and such is not reasonable, even though one continues to experience it… I often feel like the stereotypical political prisoner in the Gulag undergoing psychological torture who is told again and again to repeat (and evince true belief) that the sky is pink or that 2 + 2 = 5….”

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (DSM IV-R). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aviv, R. (Dec. (2010). Which way madness lies: Can psychosis be prevented? Harper’s Magazine, 35–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bégout, B. (2005). La découverte du quotidien. Paris: Editions Allia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, G. (1996). The history of mental symptoms: Descriptive psychopathology since the 19th Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blankenburg, W. (1971). Der Verlust der Natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleuler, E. (1911/1950). Dementia praecox or the group of schizophrenias (trans: J. Zinkin). New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2009). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casey, E. (2000). Imagining: A phenomenological study. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cermolacce, M., Sass, L., & Parnas, J. (2010). What is bizarre in bizarre delusions: A critical review. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34, 667–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conrad, K. (1958). Die beginnende Schizophrenie: Versuch einer Gestatlanalyse des Wahns. Stuttgart: Thieme.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2009). Imagination, delusion, and self-deception. In T. Bayne & J. Fernandez (Eds.), Delusions and self-deception (pp. 263–280). London: Psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ey, H. (1996). Schizophrénie: Études cliniques et psychopathologiques. France: Synthelabo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2005). Delusional mood and delusional perception—A phenomenological analysis. Psychopathology, 38, 133–139.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. (2011). The hidden reality: Parallel universes and the deep laws of the cosmos. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Hölderlins Hymn “The Ister,” (trans: W. McNeill & J. Davis). Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hemsley, D. R. (2005). The schizophrenic experience: Taken out of context? Schizophrenia Bulletin, 31, 43–53.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Henriksen, M. (in press). On incomprehensibility in schizophrenia. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hölderlin, F. (1984). Hymns and fragments (trans: R. Sieburth). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active syntheses (trans: A. Steinbock). Boston: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1963). General psychopathology (trans: J. Hoenig & M. Hamilton). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1973/1974). Les non-dupes errent. (Lacan’s Seminar XXI, 1973–1974, unpublished but available in various forms on the internet.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Manonni, O. (2003). “I know well but all the same…” In M. A. Rothenberg, D. A. Foster, & S. Zizek (Eds.), Perversion and the social relationship (pp. 69–92). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melberg, A. (1999). Turns and echoes: Two examples of Hölderlin’s poetics. In A. Fioretos (Ed.), The solid letter: readings of friedrich hölderlin (pp. 340–355). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, C.S. (1970). First rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117, 15–23.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Møller, P., & Husby, R. (2000). The initial prodrome in schizophrenia: Searching for naturalistic core dimensions of experience and behavior. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 26, 217–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Suur, H. (1950). Das Gewissheitsproblem beim schizophrenen und beim paranoischen Wahnerleben. Fortschritte der Neurologie, Psychiatrie under ihrer Grenzgebiete, 18, 44–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., et al. (2005). EASE: Examination of anomalous self-experience. Psychopathology, 38, 236–258.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Read, R. (2001). On approaching schizophrenia through Wittgenstein. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 449–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (2011). Only a philosopher or a madman: Impractical delusions in philosophy and psychiatry. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 17, 315–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rümke, H. (1990). The nuclear symptoms of schizophrenia and the praecox feeling. History of Psychiatry, 1, 331–341.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1950). Psychology of imagination. London: Rider.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (1992). Heidegger, schizophrenia, and the ontological difference. Philosophical Psychology, 5, 109–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (1994). The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (2003). Incomprehensibility and understanding: On the interpretation of severe mental illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 10, 125–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (2004a). Some reflections on the (analytical) philosophical approach to delusion. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11, 71–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (2004b). Affectivity in schizophrenia: A phenomenological perspective. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11, 127–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (2011). Autonomy and schizophrenia: Reflections on an ideal. In C. Piers (Ed.), Personality and psychopathology: critical dialogues with David Shapiro (pp. 99–131). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L., & Pienkos, E. (in press). Delusion: The phenomenological approach. In W. Fulford, et al. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, G. (1987). A review of the German literature on delusion between 1914 and 1939. In J. Cutting & M. Shepherd (Eds.) The clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept (pp. 104–134). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schreber, D. P. (1988). Memoirs of my nervous illness (trans: I. Macalpine & R. Hunter). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1945). On multiple realities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 533–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, M. (1990). On defining delusion. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 31, 377–397.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, H. S. (1953). The interpersonal theory of psychiatry. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. (1976). Schizophrenia: The sacred symbol of psychiatry. British Journal of Psychiatry, 129, 308–316.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tatossian, A. (1997). La Phénoménologie des Psychoses. Paris: LArt du Comprendre (juillet 1997, Numéro double, hors série).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, T. (2004). Wittgenstein and the limits of empathic understanding in psychopathology. International Review of Psychiatry, 16, 216–224.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, A. (2011). The sublime object of psychiatry: Schizophrenia in clinical and cultural theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments on drafts of this article, the author thanks Greg Byrom and Nev Jones.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Louis A. Sass PhD .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sass, L. (2014). Delusion and Double Book-Keeping. In: Fuchs, T., Breyer, T., Mundt, C. (eds) Karl Jaspers’ Philosophy and Psychopathology. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-8878-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics