Skip to main content

Quantum Theory of Measurement

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Theoretical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics
  • 3186 Accesses

Abstract

A quantum entity, as discussed in Sect. 2.12, consists of an inseparable pair, namely, its degree of freedom and state vector. One of the most enigmatic features of a quantum entity is that its degree of freedom can never be directly observed. On attempting to observe its degree of freedom, what one ends up observing is the state vector of the degree of freedom, as illustrated in Fig. 3.3. In fact, as discussed in Sect. 7.9, one does not even observe the state vector; every experiment ultimately observes only the effect of the state vector on the projection operators, which are physical detectors. Quantum probability assigns probabilities to the likelihood of a projection operator detecting the state vector.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It should be noted that there is no experimental proof that von Neumann’s postulate is correct.

  2. 2.

    The more general statement is that the eigenvalues λ n can be reconstructed from the collection of all the counter readings \(x_{i};\ i = 1, 2,\,\ldots,\,N\). The assumption that λ n depends only on x n is made for simplicity.

  3. 3.

    Schrödinger illustrated the paradox of superposing macroscopic states by the famous cat example. A device releases a poison, if triggered by the (uncertain) alpha decay of an unstable atom, that kills a cat. Before the cat is observed, the state of the cat is the following superposed state, namely, \(\vert \text{cat}\rangle = \vert \text{cat; dead}\rangle \vert + \vert \text{cat; alive}\rangle\). The paradox lies in explaining how can the cat be dead and alive at the same time.

  4. 4.

    More advanced books on the foundations of quantum mechanics take issue with this interpretation arguing that a measurement in fact leads to UρM U  †  that brings back the mixing of all the detector states [4]. The transformation by U can, in principle, be undone by a rotation of the basis states being used to make the measurements.

  5. 5.

    One can create a more complicated experiment where a subsequent measurement is performed on the final state with another device and come to the same conclusion as the thought experiment.

  6. 6.

    Note the notation used implies that \(\mathcal{O}_{E\vert \chi } = E_{\chi }[\mathcal{O}_{E}]\) is an operator on \(\mathcal{V}_{\mathrm{D}}\) and not equal to \(E_{\chi }[\mathcal{O}]\), which is a real number.

  7. 7.

    A partial erasure of the symbol is also possible, as discussed in Sect. 8.8 on the Quantum Erasure.

  8. 8.

    Static electric fields alone cannot act as a trap since the electron will drift along the direction of the electric field and finally hit the electric charge that is the source of the electric field.

  9. 9.

    This asymmetry of time and position is resolved in relativistic quantum field theory by “demoting” position from being a degree of freedom, as is the case for nonrelativistic quantum mechanics, to being a parameter like time; both space and time coordinates label the quantum field’s degrees of freedom. Thus, having both \(t,\vec{x}\) as parameters allows one to have exact relativistic invariance under Lorentz transformations on \(t,\vec{x}\).

  10. 10.

    All three concepts of time, namely, external, intrinsic, and observed time, can be employed to study a quantum process [28].

References

  1. Peres, A.: Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer, Holland (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aspect, A.: Bell’s inequality test: more ideal than ever. Nature 398(189), 1408–1427 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baaquie, B.E.: Quantum Finance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Ballentine, L.E.: Quantum Mechanics: A Modern Development. World Scientific, Singapore (1998)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Baaquie, B.E.: Path Integrals in Quantum Mechanics, Quantum Field Theory and Superstrings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Bell, J.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Odom, B., Hanneke, D., D’Urso, B., Gabrielse, G.: New measurement of the electron magnetic moment using a one-electron quantum cyclotron. Phys. Rev. Lett. 97, 030801 (2006)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  8. DeWitt, B.S., Graham, N.: The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Clauser, J.F., Horne, M.A., Shimony, A., Holt, R.A.: Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880–884 (1969)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  10. Dirac, P.A.M.: The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777–780 (1935)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Wigner, E.P.: The problem of measurement. Am. J. Phys. 31, 6–15 (1963)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Feynman, R.P.: The Character of Physical Law. Penguin Books, Baltimore (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Feynman, R.P., Hibbs, A.R.: Quantum Mechanics and Path Integrals. McGraw Hill, New York (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gottfried, K., Yan, T.-M.: Quantum Mechanics. Springer, Germany (2003)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Greenstein, G., Zajonc, A.G.: The Quantum Challenge, 2nd edn. Jones and Bartlett, Boston (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Heisenberg, W.: The Physical Principals of the Quantum Theory. Dover, New York (1949)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Heisenberg, W.: Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science. Prometheus Books, New York (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Isham, C.J.: Lectures on Quantum Theory. Imperial College Press, London (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Klyachko, A.A., Can, M.A., Binicioğlu, S., Shumovsky, A.S.: Simple test for hidden variables in spin-1 systems. Phys. Rev. Lett. 101, 020403 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  21. Kochen, S., Specker, E.P.: The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 17 (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kurzyński, P., Ramanathan, R., Kaszlikowski, D.: Entropic test of quantum contextuality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 109, 020404 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  23. Lawden, D.F.: The Mathematical Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Dover, New york (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Feynman, R.P., Leighton, R.B., Sands, M.: The Feynman Lectures on Physics. Addison-Wesley, Reading (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Mackey, G.W.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Dover, New York (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Major, F.G., Gheorghe, V.N., Werth, G.: Charged Particle Traps: Physics and Techniques of Charged Particle Field Confinement. Springer, Germany (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Nielsen, M.A., Chang, I.L.: Quantum Computation and Quantum Information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Muga, G.: Time in Quantum Mechanics. Springer, Berlin (2008)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Muller, H., Peter, A., Chew, S.: A precision measurement of the gravitational redshift by the interference of matter waves. Nature 463(3), 926–929 (1983)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  30. Newton, R.G.: The Truth of Science: Physical Theories and Reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Healy, R.: The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ramanathan, R., Soeda, A.A., Kurzyński, P., Kaszlikowsk, D.: Generalized monogamy of contextual inequalities from the no-disturbance principle. Phys. Rev. Lett. 109, 050404 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  33. Schlosshauer, M.A.: Decoherence: and the Quantum-to-Classical Transition. Springer, Germany (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Stapp, H.P.: The Copenhagen interpretation. Am. J. Phys. 40 (1963)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Streater, R.F.: Classical and quantum probability. J. Math. Phys. 41, 3556–3603 (2000)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. von Neumann, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Yu, S., Oh, C.H.: State-independent proof of Kochen-Specker theorem with 13 rays. Phys. Rev. Lett. 108, 030402 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Baaquie, B.E. (2013). Quantum Theory of Measurement. In: The Theoretical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-6224-8_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-6224-8_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4614-6223-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4614-6224-8

  • eBook Packages: Physics and AstronomyPhysics and Astronomy (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics