Skip to main content
  • 281 Accesses

Abstract

For a long time the major task in the field of the laws of nature was seen in finding necessary and sufficient criteria for the lawlikeness of a statement occurring in physics.1 But all attempts of this kind have failed, and the papers of this chapter, full of mistakes as they might be, do not repeat the mistake of adding one more proposal of what it is for a statement to be lawlike. Instead the major topic of the chapter is an astonishingly unnoticed phenomenon that may be called the polarity (or complementarity or reciprocity) of generality and coherence. It is treated in all papers (except [15]), with special care in [18] and [19], whereas in [16] and [17] the two side issues of predication and substances in modern physics are added. In [15] the concept of coherence is confronted with that of contingency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Cf. Scheibe 1973d

    Google Scholar 

  2. See also: [4], §III, Scheibe 1973d, 1986b, 1987a and for examples of reduction: Scheibe 1997b and 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  3. First published as Scheibe 1989c

    Google Scholar 

  4. Blanshard 1939 and 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Blanshard 1939, vol. II, p. 264

    Google Scholar 

  6. Wittgenstein 1922

    Google Scholar 

  7. Blanshard 1961, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Scheibe 1987a

    Google Scholar 

  9. In his later writings Heisenberg liked to give this situation in elementary particle physics an interpretation in Platonic terms; see Heisenberg 1984 and 1985

    Google Scholar 

  10. Popper 1958, p. 26

    Google Scholar 

  11. More details in Scheibe 1984b and 1986c

    Google Scholar 

  12. Oppenheim/ Putnam 1958, p. 3f

    Google Scholar 

  13. Minkowski 1909, p. 54

    Google Scholar 

  14. K. J. Lambert suggested to me not to use the term “contingency” in this (major) sense because it could easily lead to misunderstandings. I feel that he is right. But in spite of honest efforts during our discussions we could not find a suitable substitute.

    Google Scholar 

  15. First published as Scheibe 1991b

    Google Scholar 

  16. On Aristotle’s usage and its gradual distortion see Ch. I of Patzig 31969

    Google Scholar 

  17. Russell 1946, pp. 614 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kant 21787, B VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Frege 1879

    Google Scholar 

  20. Whitehead/ Russell 1910.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The beginning of modern semantics was Tarski 1936. Today the model relation is defined in every textbook of logic.

    Google Scholar 

  22. An introduction to this tradition is Praenkel et al. 21973.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Scheibe 1986d (this vol. ch. VIII.36); Ludwig 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Sneed 1971, Ch. IV; Balzer et al. 1987, Ch. II. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Scheibe 1982c (this vol. VII.31)

    Google Scholar 

  26. A more detailed presentation of this viewpoint is given in Scheibe 1991c (this vol. IV. 18)

    Google Scholar 

  27. From a slightly different viewpoint this subject is treated more fully in Scheibe 1989c (this vol. ch. IV.15)

    Google Scholar 

  28. First published as Scheibe 1991g

    Google Scholar 

  29. Weingartner 1971

    Google Scholar 

  30. Scheibe 1991b (this vol. ch. IV.16) and 1991c (this vol. ch. IV.18)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Pauli 1961, p. 94

    Google Scholar 

  32. Russell 1946, pp. 614ff

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ludwig 21990; Scheibe 1986d (this vol. ch. VIII.36) and 1988c

    Google Scholar 

  34. Locke 1700, II. XXIIL3

    Google Scholar 

  35. Leibniz 1765, II. XXIII. 2

    Google Scholar 

  36. Schrödinger 1961, pp. 18f; Heisenberg 1953, 1954, and 1969, Ch. 20

    Google Scholar 

  37. Leibniz 1686, Sect. 8

    Google Scholar 

  38. Leibniz/ Couturat, p. 520

    Google Scholar 

  39. Einstein/ Podolsky/ Rosen 1935

    Google Scholar 

  40. First published as Scheibe 1991c.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Pauli 1961, p. 94

    Google Scholar 

  42. Hund 1972, p. 274; see also Wigner 1979, p. 3, no.l; Vollmer 1986, pp. 53ff

    Google Scholar 

  43. Schrödinger 1932, p. 2

    Google Scholar 

  44. See the quotations in Mc Mullin 1967, pp. 329f and 356f

    Google Scholar 

  45. For the following view on theories see Scheibe 1979 (this vol. III.11)

    Google Scholar 

  46. See, for instance, Hempel 1965, pp. 264ff, 335ff and 354ff; Nagel 1961, Ch. 4

    Google Scholar 

  47. The problem how the domain of application of a physical theory can be described is treated more fully in Stegmüller 1976, Ch. IX.4 and 5

    Google Scholar 

  48. Kant 21787, B 39

    Google Scholar 

  49. First published as Scheibe 1998

    Google Scholar 

  50. Cartwright 1983

    Google Scholar 

  51. Aristotle, Anal.Post. 71 b33 ff; Metaph. Z 1029 b31 ff

    Google Scholar 

  52. Einstein 1950, p. 15

    Google Scholar 

  53. Moore 1959, pp. 33 and 53

    Google Scholar 

  54. Russell 1956, p. 179

    Google Scholar 

  55. Bohr 1939, p.24

    Google Scholar 

  56. Bohr 1991, pp. 396ff; see also Scheibe 1973c, Ch.I

    Google Scholar 

  57. p. 3; similar formulations on pp. 54, 56, 72, 73; references to pages only refer to Cartwright 1983

    Google Scholar 

  58. p. 4; italics mine

    Google Scholar 

  59. Boltzmann 1979

    Google Scholar 

  60. Mittelstaedt 1970, p.66

    Google Scholar 

  61. p. 61

    Google Scholar 

  62. Hüttemann 1997

    Google Scholar 

  63. Heisenberg 1943, p. 32, italics mine

    Google Scholar 

  64. p. 56

    Google Scholar 

  65. p. 4; italics mine

    Google Scholar 

  66. p. 17

    Google Scholar 

  67. p. 139

    Google Scholar 

  68. Scheibe 1995c

    Google Scholar 

  69. cf. Stegmüller 1983, Ch.VI

    Google Scholar 

  70. cf. Bourbaki 1968, Ch.IV

    Google Scholar 

  71. Stegmüller 1976, Ch.IX.4; see also NC’s “as if” operator in 1983, pp. 128ff

    Google Scholar 

  72. Cf. Blanchard 1939

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Scheibe, E. (2001). Laws of Nature. In: Falkenburg, B. (eds) Between Rationalism and Empiricism. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-0183-7_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-0183-7_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4612-6555-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4613-0183-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics