Skip to main content

The Objectivity, or Otherwise, of the Present

  • Chapter
  • 238 Accesses

Abstract

Exponents of both sides of the controversy concerning whether or not ‘the present’ is objective have claimed that the issue should be capable of being resolved scientifically. It is here suggested that this is a mistaken view. The t-coordinate of physics has been widely endowed with overmuch ontological significance and there is no scientific warrant for the view, espoused by some of the B-theorists, that past, present and future are necessarily ‘equally real’. From an epistemological point of view, ‘the present’, at any particular location, is simply the terminus of all events which can be known with certainty and thus the temporal order, as it applies to any assumed events later than the present, is no more than a schematic construction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. C. D. Broad, Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy, Cambridge 1938.

    Google Scholar 

  2. R. M. Gale, The Language of Time, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. N. Prior, Past, Present and Future, Oxford 1967; Papers on Time and Tense, Oxford 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  4. H. Reichenbach, The Direction of Time, University of California, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  5. G. J. Whitrow, The Natural Philosophy of Time, Nelson, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  6. A. J. Ayer, The Problem of Knowledge, pg. 170, Macmillan 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  7. D. C. Williams, Principles of Empirical Realism, Charles C. Thomas, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A. Grünbaum in Essays in Honor of Carl G, Hempel, ed. N. Rescher, Reidel Publ. Co., Dordrecht; also Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, Knopf, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  9. J. J. C. Smart, Between Science and philosophy, Random House, 1968; also Philosophy and Scientific Realism, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  10. D. Park in The Study of Time, Ed. J. T. Fraser, et al, Springer-Verlag, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Philosophy & Scientific Realism, pg. 133

    Google Scholar 

  12. Between Science & Philosophy, pg. 255

    Google Scholar 

  13. loc. cit., pg. 155–6

    Google Scholar 

  14. See for example J. A. Ornstein, The Mind and The Brain, Nijhoff, The Hague, 1972. For a critique of what has been called the’ strong correlation thesis’ see R. C. Solomon, Brit, J. Philosophy of Science, 1975, 26, 27.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. E. Cassirer in The Study of Time, ed. J. T. Fraser et. al., Springer-Verlag, 1972. Concerning the notion of ‘becoming’ see also P. Fitzgerald in Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. XX, Reidel Pubi. Co. Dordrecht, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  16. loc. cit. pg. 16

    Google Scholar 

  17. Annales de L’Institut Henri Poincaré, 1952–3, 13, 109–158.

    Google Scholar 

  18. loc. cit. pg. 295

    Google Scholar 

  19. loc. cit. pg. 167–8

    Google Scholar 

  20. Philosophy and Scientific Realism, pg. 141–2

    Google Scholar 

  21. My attitude to this particular issue was described in my contribution to The Study of Time, ed. J. T. Fraser et al., Springer-Verlag, 1972. Also in my book. An Inventive Universe, Hutchinson, London, 1975; Braziller, New York, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  22. On this point see, for example, Lawrence Sklar, Space, Time and Space-Time, pp. 272–5, University of California Press, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The Physicist’s Concept of Nature, ed. J. Mehra, Reidel Pubi. Co., Dordrecht, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Philosophy of Science, 1968, 35, pg. 375.

    Google Scholar 

  25. J. T. Fraser, Of Time, Passion, and Knowledge, Braziller, New York, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

Notes

  1. Grünbaum (loc. cit. pg. 159) writes as follows: “... if nowness were a mindindependent property of physical events themselves, it would be very strange indeed that it could be omitted as such from all extant physical theories without detriment to their explanatory success.” As against this Gale (loc. cit. pg. 224) has pointed out that any law or theory “is general: the statement of it is temporally unrestricted since it quantifies over all times. Since the law or theory holds true for any time it obviously cannot serve as a criterion for picking out some one time as the present: if it holds for all times it cannot hold for just one time.” And therefore “... there is no physical criterion for determining what is the present.” To Gale’s point it may be added that although physical laws and theories also do not pick out a spatial location, this analogical situation does not imply that there may not be a distinguished ‘present’ even if there is no distinguished ‘place’.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The term ‘objective’ will be used in this paper in the strong sense — i. e. as referring to whatever may be said to exist or to happen quite independently of man’s own presence in the world, or of his thoughts and perceptions. Thus I shall not be concerned with the we aker sense of the term which refers to whatever can be publicly agreed.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Hinckfuss is among those who still regard relativity as having disposed of an objective present. He writes: “... if the simultaneity of events is relative to a frame of reference rather than absolute, then there is no such thing as The Present.” (The Existence of Space and Time, pg. 106, Oxford, 1975). This seems to me an illicit extrapolation from the non-existence of a universal reference frame to the supposed non-existence of a ‘now’ at each location. It is very significant that no ob server whatsoever can signal to me that he has observed an event at my own location before I have observed that event myself. In that respect the A-theorist might claim that there is something absolute about the occurrence of an event here and now.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Indeed it isn’t at all clear what he could mean by this. Is it that the physical content of the future is just as real as the physical content of the present? No doubt at any moment it can reasonably be expected that there will be some future and that it will have some physical content. But this seems to be saying little more than the old adage “What will be, will be.”

    Google Scholar 

  5. Even though the possibilities in question may refer to an earlier present; for instance when it is said “It was a possibility yesterday that he might be coming.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. It is of interest that Grünbaum in one of his footnotes (no. 13 of ref. 8) remarks that the conceptualized awareness on which ‘now-awareness’ depends must surely require a physical sub-stratum and therefore this awareness might also inhere in a suitably complex piece of hardware.

    Google Scholar 

  7. According to E. A. Burtt, the representation of time as a straight line was first adopted by Galileo and was associated with his concept of natural law as expressing necessity. E. A. Burtt, Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science, Second Ed. pg. 86, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Mario Bunge Has made the further point th at the world-line of an elementary particle is necessarily ‘fuzzy’ because of the Uncertainty principle. Philosophy of Science, 1968, 35, 355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. In this discussion I am referring, of course to events as experienced and not to events at the source of origin of the experienced signals which may be light-yearsaway.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cantorean concepts are, of course just as applicable to a series which is bounded at one or both ends as to a series which is endless.

    Google Scholar 

  11. This transition between micro- and macro-concepts of time has been particularly clearly brought out in various papers by P. T. Landsberg; for example in his contribution to The Study of Time, Ed. J. T. Praser et. al.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1978 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Denbigh, K.G. (1978). The Objectivity, or Otherwise, of the Present. In: Fraser, J.T., Lawrence, N., Park, D.A. (eds) The Study of Time III. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-6287-9_14

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-6287-9_14

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4612-6289-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4612-6287-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics