On the Margins: Experimental Philosophy and Mathematics in Britain, 1790–1830

  • Elizabeth Garber

Abstract

Experimental philosophers in Britain developed their own forms of theoretical physics during the same period as the Germans. In broad outlines, the processes through which these transformations occurred were the same. Socially experimental philosophy became a profession rather than an avocation; passage into the research community narrowed from self-education to formal, certified educational levels within the universities of Britain. Access to entry into the research communities was consequently constrained by these formal, educational gateways. Training became the modern apprenticeship of graduated courses, problems sets, and textbooks along with laboratory courses. Access narrowed to the social institutions of science that had appeared as open and serving many cultural, economic, and social purposes in the late eighteenth century. Their memberships and purposes became limited to the professional, research oriented physicist. The institutions that had been intellectually universal and geographically local became narrowly specialized and geographically national.

Keywords

Europe Steam Mold Income Coherence 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1a.
    For the diversity represented in such organizations, see Metropolis and Province: Science in British Culture, 1780–1850, Ian Inkster and Jack Morrell, eds. (London: Hutchinson, 1983).Google Scholar
  2. 1b.
    See also Ian Inkster, “Cultural Enterprise: Science, Steam, Intellectual and Social Class in Rochdale, circa 1833–1900,” Soc. Stud. Sci. 18 (1988): 291–330;Google Scholar
  3. 1c.
    Jack Morrell, “Early Yorkshire Geological and Polytechnic Society,” Ann. Sci. 45 (1988): 153–167Google Scholar
  4. 1d.
    Jack Morrell, “Bradford Science, 1800–1850,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 18 (1985): 1–23;Google Scholar
  5. 1e.
    J. N. Hays, “Science in the City: The London Institution 1819–1840,” British J. Hist. Sci. 1 (1974): 146–162Google Scholar
  6. 1f.
    J. N. Hays, “London Institution,” Ann. Sci. 39 (1982): 229–274.Google Scholar
  7. 1g.
    The localism and attempts to preserve it in Edinburgh as natural philosophy became science, and national rather than local, are detailed in Steve Shapin, “The Audience of Science in Eighteenth-Century Edinburgh.” D. S. L. Cardwell Organization of Science in England in the Nineteenth Century second edition (1973), makes little mention of these institutions while focussing on mechanics institutes and the redbrick universities. The narrative of the mechanics institutes is well known, its meaning still contested.Google Scholar
  8. 1h.
    See Roy Heyden, “The Glasgow Mechanics Institution,” Phil. J. 10 (1973): 107–120;Google Scholar
  9. 1i.
    Steve Shapin and Barry Barnes, “Science, Nature and Control: Interpreting Mechanics Institutes,” Soc. Stud. Sci. 1 (1977): 31–74;Google Scholar
  10. 1j.
    Ian Inkster, “Science and Mechanics Institutes, 1820–1850: The Case of Sheffield,” Ann. Sci. 32 (1975): 451–474Google Scholar
  11. 1k.
    Ian Inkster, “The Social Context of the Educational Movement: A Revisionist Approach to English Mechanic’s Institutes, 1820–1850,” Oxford Rev. Educ. 2 (1976): 277–307.Google Scholar
  12. 1l.
    See also Gordon W. Roderick and Michael D. Stephens, Scientific and Technical Education in Nineteenth-Century England (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1972) chaps., 8 and 9.Google Scholar
  13. 2.
    For a sense of the networks these institutions formed see, Jack Morrell and Arnold Thackray, Gentlemen of Science: Early Years of the British Association for the Advancement of Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), chap. 2 and Appendix II, 544.Google Scholar
  14. 4a.
    Arnold Thackray, John Dalton: A Critical Assessment of his Life and Science (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1972) chaps. 4 and 5, details the ways John Dalton fashioned his career at the Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society.Google Scholar
  15. 4b.
    Dalton was not the first to do this through the Manchester institution, see Frank Greenaway, John Dalton and the Atom (Ithaca NY.: Cornell University Press, 1966), 91–95 on Thomas Henry. There were also Humphry Davy and Michael Faraday at the Royal Institution.Google Scholar
  16. 4c.
    For John Phillips at the Yorkshire Philosophical Society see Morrell and Thackray, Gentlemen of Science and Martin Rudwick, The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Scientific Knowledge among Gentlemanly Specialists (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.)Google Scholar
  17. 4d.
    On Charles Lyell’s use of London institutions in his early career see, Jack Morrell, “London Institutions and Lyell’s Career, 1820–41,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 9 (1976): 132–146.Google Scholar
  18. 5.
    The Royal Institution and many Mechanics institutes were caught in this situation. For the links between architectural form and social values see Sophie Forgan, “The Architecture of Science and the Idea of a University,” Studies Hist. Phil. Sci. 20 (1989): 405–443.Google Scholar
  19. 7.
    See Dorinda Outram, “Science and Political Ideology, 1790–1848,” in Companion to the History of Modern Science R. C. Olby, G. Cantor, J. R. R. Christie, and C. Hodge, eds. (New York: Routledge, 1990), 1008–1023.Google Scholar
  20. 9a.
    Physicians were a significant percentage of its membership. It was still important for ambitious physicians to be seen as learned advisers as well as mere healers, and as having social contact with the wealthy and powerful. See Harold Cook, “The New Philosophy and Medicine in Seventeenth-Century England,” in Reappraisals of the Scientific Revolution, David Lindberg and Robert S. Westman, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990) 397–436.Google Scholar
  21. 9b.
    For the Royal Society’s social function and political ties, see Marie Boas Hall, All Scientists Now: The Royal Society in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), chap. 1.Google Scholar
  22. 11.
    Thomas Young, A Course in Natural Philosophy (London: Joseph Johnson, 1807) 2 vols.Google Scholar
  23. 17.
    The empirical foundation of the sciences assumed in Britain in this period has been emphasized more than once. See Michael Shortland, “A Mind for the Facts, some Antimonies of Scientific Culture in early nineteenth century Britain,” Arch. Int. Hist. Sci. 36 (1986): 294–324.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  24. 21a.
    For Cambridge see the textbooks discussed in chapter II. In the Scottish universities the same pattern prevailed. See, John Playfair, Outline of Natural Philosophy (Edinburgh: A. Constable, 1812–1814), 2 vols., as 1. The volumes are clearly from notes for lectures. They are too cryptic for delivery to students.Google Scholar
  25. 21b.
    See also John Robison, Elements of Mechanical Philosophy, being the Substance of a Course of Lectures on that Science (Edinburgh: Constable and Co., 1804).Google Scholar
  26. 21c.
    The broad sweep of the meaning of the term “physics” in this era is in Michael Shortland, “On the Connexion of the Physical Sciences: Classification and Organization in Early Nineteenth-Century Science,” Hist. Scientiarium 41 (1991): 17–36.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  27. 22.
    For a discussion of mechanical philosophy and its inclusive character, see Crosbie Smith, “‘Mechanical Philosophy’ and the Emergence of Physics in Britain: 1800–1850,” Ann. Sci. 33 (1976): 3–29, 6–14. Smith locates the beginnings of this tradition in Robison’s lectures and sees the same patterns in William Meikleham’s lectures in natural philosophy at Glasgow University from William Thomson’s notebooks on those lectures.MATHGoogle Scholar
  28. 23.
    Gerald L. E. Turner, “Experimental Science in Early Nineteenth-Century Oxford,” in Hist. Univ. 8(1989): 117–135, 123.Google Scholar
  29. 24.
    The ends of science, as expressed by natural philosophers themselves in this era, are discussed by G. A. Foote, “Science and its Function in Early Nineteenth-Century England,” Osiris 11 (1954): 438–454.Google Scholar
  30. 26.
    A need was however seen for such a text because Biot was translated. See Jean-Baptiste Biot, Traité de physique expérimentale et mathématique 4 vols., (Paris: Dateville, 1816), translated by John Farrar.Google Scholar
  31. 27.
    John Robison, “Dynamics,” A System of Mechanical Philosophy, with notes by David Brewster (Edinburgh: John Murray, 1822) 4 vols., vol. 1,157–158. These are Robison’s articles for the Encyclopedia Brittanica.Google Scholar
  32. 29a.
    John Playfair, A General View of the Mathematical and Physical Sciences since the Revival of Letters in Europe in Stewart, Mackintosh, Playfair and Leslie, Dissertations on the History of Metaphysical and Ethical and of Mathematical and Physical Sciences (Edinburgh: Adam and Charles Black, 1824–1835), (Edinburgh: 1824), 2 vols., as one, 433–572.Google Scholar
  33. 29b.
    Richard Yeo, “Reading Encyclopedias: Science and the Organization of Knowledge in Dictionaries of Arts and Sciences, 1730–1850,” Isis, 82 (1991): 24–49 discusses the function of these discourses.Google Scholar
  34. 33.
    Hutton, “Mixed Mathematics,” in Mathematical and Philosophical Dictionary containing An Explanation of Terms and an Account of the several Subjects under the Heads Mathematics, Astronomy, and Philosophy, both Natural and Experimental, C. Hutton, ed. (New York: Georg Ohms Verlag, reprint of 1796 edition, 1973), 2 vols.Google Scholar
  35. 34.
    For a recent study of this opposition see, L. A. Wzhitt, “Atoms or Affinities? The Ambivalent Reception of Daltonian Theory,” Studies Hist Phil. Sci. 21 (1990): 57–89.Google Scholar
  36. 35.
    For Dalton’s theory, see Greenaway, John Dalton and Atomism, and for a critical appraisal, see Thackray, John Dalton. For the arguments surrounding his theory and chemists’ claims of empiricism, see Allen J. Rocke, Chemical Atomism in the Nineteenth Century from Dalton to Cannizzaro (Columbus OH.: Ohio State University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
  37. 42a.
    Young was further hampered by an inability to communicate his own work and ideas, especially to a general audience. See George Peacock, Life of Thomas Young (London: John Murray, 1855), 135Google Scholar
  38. 42b.
    Alexander Wood, Thomas Young, Natural Philosopher, 1773–1829 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1954), 137.MATHGoogle Scholar
  39. 50.
    See G. Cantor, “The Changing Role of Young’s Ether,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 5(1970): 44–62, for a discussion of Young’s ether.Google Scholar
  40. 51a.
    Henry Brougham, “Bakerian Lecture on Light and Colors,” Edinburgh Rev. 1 (1803): 450–456. Brougham was writing for the same kind of audience that attended Young’s lectures.Google Scholar
  41. 51b.
    See also G. Cantor, “Henry Brougham and the Scottish Methodological Tradition,” Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2 (1971): 69–89. I would put more weight on the significance of this challenge because of the central place of method in defining experimental philosophy.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  42. 57a.
    Recent biographers see Davy’s commitment to certain key ideals of romanticism one of the few aspects of his life that gave it any coherence. David Knight, Humphry Davy: Science and Power (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).Google Scholar
  43. 57b.
    See also Trevor H. Levere, “Humphry Davy, “The Sons of Genius” and the Idea of Glory,” in Science and the “Sons of Genius”: Studies on Humphry Davy, Sophie Forgan, ed. (London: Science Reviews, 1980), 33–58, and Christopher Lawrence, “The Power and the Glory: Humphry Davy and Romanticism,” in Romanticism and the Sciences, Cunningham and Jardine, eds., 213–227.Google Scholar
  44. 60.
    Niccolo Guicciardini, The Development of Newtonian Calculus in Britain, 1700–1800 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) details the development of fluxional calculus. He discusses the level of competence of mathematicians in Britain in the later decades of the century in chap. 7, and the place of mathematics in general culture in chap. 8.Google Scholar
  45. 61.
    Hutton, Mathematical and Philosophical Dictionary. For comments on Hutton’s dictionary see Grattan-Guinness, “French calcul and English Fluxions around 1800: some comparisons and Contrasts,” Jahrbuch Überblicke Mathematik (1986): 167–178, 171–172. See also Grattan-Guinness, “Before Bowditch: Henry Harte’s Translation of Laplace’s Mécanique Célèste,” NTM, 24 (1987): 53–55 on early translations.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  46. 62a.
    Playfair, “Review of Laplace’s, Mécanique Célèste,” Edinburgh Rev. 11 (1807): 249–284Google Scholar
  47. 62b.
    Playfair, “Review of Laplace’s System of the World,” Edinburgh Rev., 15 (1808): 396–417. Playfair was not alone in this lament.Google Scholar
  48. 62c.
    See, John Toplis, “On the Decline of Mathematical Studies, and the Sciences dependent upon Them,” Phil. Mag. 20 (1805): 25–31.Google Scholar
  49. 65.
    For Wallace’s role in the mathematical importations from the continent see M. Pantiki, “William Wallace and the Introduction of Continental Calculus to Britain: A Letter to George Peacock,” Hist. Math. 14 (1987): 119–132.Google Scholar
  50. 66a.
    See James Ivory, “On Attraction of Homogeneous Ellipsoids,” Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London, 99 (1809): 345–372Google Scholar
  51. 66b.
    See James Ivory, “On Attraction of Homogeneous Ellipsoids,” Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London 102 (1812): 1–45.Google Scholar
  52. 67.
    For a reassessment of the role of the Cambridge group see Phillip Enros, “The Analytical Society, 1812–1813: Precursor to the Renewal of Cambridge Mathematics,” Hist. Math. 16 (1983): 24–47.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  53. 68a.
    Robert Woodhouse, The Principles of Analytical Calculation (Cambridge: University Press, 1803).Google Scholar
  54. 68b.
    See J. M. Dubbey, “The Introduction of the Differential Notation into Great Britain,” Ann. Sci. 19 (1963): 37–48. Much of Dubbey’s argument on the role of the Cambridge Analysts has been superseded.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  55. 71a.
    For the development of the Senate House examinations into the Tripos, see W. W. R. Ball, A History of the Study of Mathematics at Cambridge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1889)MATHGoogle Scholar
  56. 71b.
    For the development of the Senate House examinations into the Tripos, see W. W. R. Ball, The Origin and History of the Mathematical Tripos (Cambridge: E. Johnson, 1880).Google Scholar
  57. 71c.
    The change in the function of the examination is mapped by John Gascoigne, “Mathematics and Meritocracy: The Emergence of the Cambridge Mathematical Tripos,” Soc. Stud. Sci. 14 (1984): 547–584.Google Scholar
  58. 72.
    An easily available example of this is in Ball, Origin, in the examination questions for 1801, 30–33, and in Cambridge Problems: Being a Collection of the Printed Questions proposed to the Candidates for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts at the General Examination, 1801–1810 (Cambridge: J. Deighton, 1810).Google Scholar
  59. 73.
    James Wood and Samuel Vince, The Principles of Mathematics and Natural Philosophy (Cambridge: J. Burges, 1795–1799) 4 vols.Google Scholar
  60. 74a.
    Woodhouse An Elementary Treatise on Astronomy (Cambridge: J. Smith, 1812) was largely descriptive. The equation of time and method of computing eclipses derived from the tradition of observational astronomers. Woodhouse explained that unlike geometry astronomy did not spring from simple principles followed by logically deductible results. Everything was connected and accuracy achieved through successive approximations.Google Scholar
  61. 74b.
    Woodhouse, Treatise on Astronomy, Theoretical and Practical (Cambridge: J. Smith, 1821) separated the physical from the mathematical treatment of the subject. He included the mathematical techniques of Laplace but no discussion of the physical implications of all these manipulations.Google Scholar
  62. 75.
    For example, Woodhouse, A Treatise on Isoperimetrical Problems and the Calculus of Variations (New York: Chelsea Pub. Co. reprint, 1964), “On the Independence of the Analytical and Geometrical Methods of Investigation,” Phil Trans. R. Soc. London, (1802): 85–125, and “Methods of Investigation of the Integration of Certain Expressions with which Problems in Physical Astronomy are connected,” same journal, (1802): 85–125, and, same journal (1804); 219–278. After his appointment, Woodhouse, “Account of the Transit Instrument made by Mr. Dolland and lately put up at Cambridge University,” Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London, (1825): 418–428, (1826): 15–36, and “On the Derangement of Certain Instruments by the Effects of Temperature,” same journal, (1827): 144–158.Google Scholar
  63. 79.
    For the struggles of the geologists see, Rudwick, “The Foundation of the Geological Society of London: Its Scheme for Cooperative Research and its Struggle for Independence,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 1 (1962): 325–355.Google Scholar
  64. 80.
    For example, see the humiliations that Michael Faraday was prepared to endure to become elected to the Royal Society in 1824, June Z. Fullmer and Melvyn C. Usselman, “Faraday’s Election to the Royal Society: A Reputation in Jeopardy,” Bull Hist. Chem. 11 (1991): 17–28.Google Scholar
  65. 81.
    For example see John Cawood, “The Magnetic Crusade: Science and Politics in Early Victorian Britain,” Isis, 70(1979): 493–518.Google Scholar
  66. 82.
    See William J. Ashworth, “The Calculating Eye: Baily, Herschel, Babbage and the Business of Astronomy,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 27 (1994): 409–441.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  67. 83b.
    For a narrative of these events, see Marie Boas Hall, All Scientists Now. For a sociological analysis, see Roy Macleod, “Whigs and Savants: Reflections on the Reform Movement in the Royal Society, 1830–1848,” in Metropolis and Province, Inkster and Morrell, eds. 55–90. On Davy’s tenure as president, see David P. Miller, “Between Hostile Camps: Sir Humphry Davy’s Presidency of the Royal Society, 1820–1827,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 16 (1983): 1–47.Google Scholar
  68. 84.
    For the patronage of the sciences in this era, see, Cawood, “The Magnetic Crusade,” and J. B. Morrell, “The Patronage of Mid-Victorian Science in the University of Edinburgh,” in The Patronage of Science in the Nineteenth Century, G. L’ E. Turner, ed. (Leiden: Noordhoff, 1976), 53–93.Google Scholar
  69. 85a.
    The preeminent examples are Jane Marcet in chemistry and Mary Somerville in astronomy. See Somerville, Mechanism of the Heavens (London: J. Murray, 1831), a translation and commentary on Laplace’s Mécanique Célèste Google Scholar
  70. 85b.
    See Somerville, Preliminary Dissertation on the Mechanism of the Heavens (London: 1832).Google Scholar
  71. 85c.
    See Elizabeth Patterson, Mary Somerville and the Cultivation of the Sciences, 1815–1840 (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1983). Faraday became his own mediator, establishing Friday evening lectures at the Royal Institution.Google Scholar
  72. 86.
    See J. B. Morrell, “Science and Scottish University Reform: Edinburgh in 1826,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 6 (1972): 39–56.Google Scholar
  73. 88a.
    See George A. Foote, “Mechanism, Materialism, and Science in England, 1800–1850,” Ann. Sci. 8 (1953): 152–161Google Scholar
  74. 88b.
    See George A. Foote, “Science and Its Function,” Osiris, 11 (1954): 438–454.Google Scholar
  75. 89a.
    The interaction of experiment and hypothesis in the development of Faraday’s thought is explored in David Gooding Experiment and the Making of Meaning (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1990).Google Scholar
  76. 89b.
    Faraday’s reactions to Ampère are detailed in L. Pearce Williams, Michael Faraday (New York: Basic, 1965)Google Scholar
  77. 89c.
    Faraday’s reactions to Ampère are detailed in L. Pearce Williams, “Faraday and Ampère: A Critical Dialogue,” in Faraday Rediscovered: Essays on the Life and Work of Michael Faraday, 1791–1867, David Gooding and F. A. J. L. James, eds. (London: Macmillan, 1985), 83–104.Google Scholar
  78. 90a.
    Sources on Green are few. See H. Gwynedd Green, “George Green,” in Studies and Essays in the History of Science and Learning, offered in Homage to George Sarton (New York: Schumann, 1947), 552–593.Google Scholar
  79. 90b.
    For the richness of the local Nottingham scientific culture in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, see Ian Inkster, “Scientific Culture and Education in Nottingham, 1800–1843,” Transactions of the Thoroton Society of Nottinghamshire, 82 (1978): 45–50.Google Scholar
  80. 91a.
    George Green, An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism (Nottingham: 1828)Google Scholar
  81. 91b.
    Mathematical Papers, N. M. Ferrers, ed. (New York: Chelsea Pub. Co. reprint of 1871 edition, 1970), 1–117, p. 7.Google Scholar
  82. 95.
    Another sign of change was the small, yet enthusiastic group of students and faculty attending John Henslow’s lectures, field trips, and laboratory exercises in natural history. See Adrian Desmond and James Moore Darwin: Tortured Evolutionist (London: Michael Joseph, 1992), and Browne, Darwin.Google Scholar
  83. 97.
    See Peter Allen, The Cambridge Apostles: The Early Years (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978).Google Scholar
  84. 98a.
    See A Don [Leslie Stephen] Sketches from Cambridge (London: Macmillan, 1865), 32–47.Google Scholar
  85. 98b.
    Frances M. Brookfield, The Cambridge Apostles (London: Pittman and Sons, 1906), chap. 1.Google Scholar
  86. 98c.
    Arthur Gray, Cambridge University, an Empirical History (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1927), p. 276, on Tennyson’s view of his tutor, William Whewell, “Billy Whistle.” Thackray got revenge in The Book of Snobs where Crump, Master of St. Boniface was based on William Whewell, as was Dr. Sargent in Lowe the Widower.Google Scholar
  87. 98d.
    John Clive, Macaulay: The Shaping of the Historian (New York: Knopf, 1973), p. 21 recounts the disappointment of both Macaulay and his family in the 1830s at his Cambridge record. Macaulay saw himself as an academic failure because he was not a mathematician. See also the agonies of Darwin trying to understand mathematics and struggles to achieve a pass degree. See Desmond and Moore Darwin, and Browne Darwin.Google Scholar
  88. 98e.
    On students see Sheldon Rothblatt, “The Student Sub-Culture and the Examination System in early Nineteenth-Century Oxbridge,” in The University in Society, Stone, ed. (Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1973) 2 vols., vol. 1, 247–303.Google Scholar
  89. 99.
    For the establishment and the initial aims of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, see A. Rupert Hall, The Cambridge Philosophical Society: A History, 1819–1969 (Cambridge: Philosophical Society, 1969).Google Scholar
  90. 100a.
    The same process occurred at Oxford in the same period. See Sheldon Rothblatt, The Revolution of the Dons (New York: Basic Books, 1968) and Arthur Engel, “Emerging Concepts of the Academic Profession at Oxford, 1800–1854,” in The University in Society, Stone, ed. vol. 1, 305–351.Google Scholar
  91. 104a.
    John Herschel and Charles Babbage published on functional equations and operational methods of the calculus. Herschel’s first papers appeared in Memoirs of the Analytical Society (1813) and continued into the 1820s in the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London and the Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. They continued to appear even as his research began to focus on chemistry and observational astronomy. See Gunther Buttman, The Shadow of the Telescope: A Biography of John Herschel, Bernard Pagel, trans. (New York: Scribner’s Sons, 1970)Google Scholar
  92. 104b.
    John Herschel and Charles Babbage published on functional equations and operational methods of the calculus. Herschel’s first papers appeared in Memoirs of the Analytical Society (1813) and continued into the 1820s in the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London and the Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. They continued to appear even as his research began to focus on chemistry and observational astronomy. See Gunther Buttman, Aspects of the Life and Thought of Sir J. F. Herschel, S. S. Schweber ed. (New York: Arno Press, 1981), 2 vols. Babbage’s first paper on functional analysis appeared in 1815.Google Scholar
  93. 104c.
    See J. M. Dubbey, The Mathematical Work of Charles Babbage (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978). His assessment of Babbage’s achievement must be modified in light of contemporary French work in the same field.MATHGoogle Scholar
  94. 104d.
    See Grattan-Guinness, “Babbage’s Mathematics in its Time,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 12 (1979): 82.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  95. 105.
    See, Buttman Shadow. His work on double refraction was published as Herschel, “Double Refraction as a Deviation from Newton’s Scale,” Trans. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 1 (1822): 21–42, and that on polarization as, Herschel, “Polarization,” Trans. Cambridge Phil. Soc. (1823): 1–52.Google Scholar
  96. 106.
    See Herschel, Admiralty Handbook of Scientific Enquiry (London: Dawson reprint, 1974). His ideas also appeared in his various encyclopedia articles that are examined below.Google Scholar
  97. 107a.
    Systematic discussion of Herschel’s ideas on the place of hypotheses in “science” appear in Richard Yeo, “Reviewing Herschel’s Discourse” Studies Hist. Phil. Sci. 20 (1989): 541–542, “Reading Encyclopaedias,”Google Scholar
  98. 107b.
    Systematic discussion of Herschel’s ideas on the place of hypotheses in “science” appear in Richard Yeo, Defining Science: William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in early Victorian Britain (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 92–99.Google Scholar
  99. 110.
    Herschel, “Mathematics,” Edinburgh Encyclopedia, David Brewster, ed. (Edinburgh: W. Blackwood, 1830) vol. 13, pt. 1,359–383. On Clairaut see p. 381. See also p. 382 where Herschel noted that Clairaut was a mathematician not an astronomer. For Lagrange see p. 383.Google Scholar
  100. 112.
    George Biddell Airy, Mathematical Tracts on Physical Astronomy, The Figure of the Earth, and the Calculus of Variations designed for the Use of Students in the University (Cambridge: Deighton, 1826).Google Scholar
  101. 113.
    See Harvey Becher, “Voluntary Science in Nineteenth-Century Cambridge to 1850,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 19 (1986): 57–87, 68–70.ADSGoogle Scholar
  102. 114a.
    James Challis, Notes on the Principles of Pure and Applied Calculation: and the Application of Mathematical Principles to Theories of Physical Force (Cambridge: Deighton, Bell and Co., 1869). Challis reduced gravity, heat and other forces of nature to mechanical pressure in a fluid ether. While analytically defensible, James Clerk Maxwell described Challis’ work as self-consistent mathematically, but physically indefensible. Challis’ fluids could not behave as ordinary fluids.Google Scholar
  103. 114b.
    See Maxwell, “Challis’ ‘Mathematical Principles of Physics’,” Nature, 8 (1873): 279–280Google Scholar
  104. 114c.
    See Maxwell, “Challis’ ‘Mathematical Principles of Physics’,” Maxwell on Molecules and Gases, Garber, Brush and Everitt, eds. (Cambridge MA.: MIT Press, 1986), 126–132.Google Scholar
  105. 115a.
    Whewell’s opinions on analysis and its place in the curriculum changed over time and in the context in which he was placed and the subject discussed. As his career at Cambridge developed his defense of geometry against the inroads of French analysis grew. For the arguments over the Cambridge curriculum and the meaning of a liberal education see, Martha McMackin Garland, Cambridge before Darwin: The Ideal of a Liberal Education, 1800–1860 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
  106. 115b.
    M. V. Wilkes has explored the roles of Peacock, and Herschel in shaping the Cambridge curriculum in the middle of the nineteenth century in Wilkes, “Herschel, Peacock, Babbage and the Development of the Cambridge Curriculum,” Notes Rec. Roy. Soc. London 44 (1990): 205–219MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  107. 115c.
    that of Whewell in Harvey Becher, “William Whewell and Cambridge Mathematics,” Hist. Stud. Phys. Sci. 11 (1980): 1–48.Google Scholar
  108. 116a.
    Peacock, Treatise on Algebra (Cambridge: Deighton, 1830).Google Scholar
  109. 116b.
    For a survey of the historiography and the development of symbolic algebra, see Menachem Fisch, “‘The Emergency which has arrived’: the Problematic History of Nineteenth-Century British Algebra-a Programmatic Outline,” Brit. J. Hist. Sci. 27 (1994): 247–276.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  110. 116c.
    For the development of British explorations of “foundational” issues in mathematics see, Elaine Koppelman, “The Calculus of Operations and Rise of Abstract Algebra,” Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 8 (1971): 155–242MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  111. 116d.
    Joan Richards, “The Art and Science of British Algebra: A Study in the Perception of Mathematical Truth,” Hist. Math. 1 (1980): 343–365MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  112. 116e.
    Helen Pycior, “George Peacock and the British Origins of Symbolical Algebra,” same journal 8 (1981): 23–45, “Early Criticism of the Symbolic Approach to Algebra,” same journal 9 (1982): 392–412, Joan Richards, “Rigor and Clarity: Foundations of Mathematics in France and England, 1800–1840,” Sci. Context 4 (1991): 297–319.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media New York 1999

Authors and Affiliations

  • Elizabeth Garber
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of HistorySUNY-Stony BrookStony BrookUSA

Personalised recommendations