Popper's Continuing Relevance

  • Ian Jarvie
Part of the Boston Studies in The Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 272)

Popper claims that error indicates what to avoid and there is no recipe for how to proceed. Most rationalist philosophers ignore his arguments and still try to justify their views instead of trying to improve upon them by criticizing them and conjecturing alternatives. In public discourse barren forms of justification are widespread. More and better critical institutions are required, and these require political compromise on shared aims.

Keywords

Titan Logical Positivism Defend Stake Blindness 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Agassi, Joseph. 2003. The politics of science. In Science and culture. Boston Studies vol. 231 Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  2. Agassi, Joseph. 2008. A philosopher's apprentice. In Karl Popper's workshop (second edition). Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  3. Bartley, III, William Warren. 1962 (1964). The retreat to commitment. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
  4. Bartley, III, William Warren. 1964. Rationality versus the theory of rationality. In The critical approach to science and philosophy, ed. Mario Bunge, pp. 3–31. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bartley, III, William Warren. 1990. Unfathomed knowledge, unmeasured wealth: On universities and the wealth of nations. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
  6. Black, Max. 1964. A companion to Wittgenstein's Tractatus. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bunge, Mario. 1967. Scientific research: Strategy and philosophy. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  8. Coady, David. 2006. Conspiracy theories. The philosophical debate. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  9. Crick, Bernard. 1962. In defence of politics. London: Weidenfeld & NicolsonGoogle Scholar
  10. Hacohen, Malachi Haim. 2000. Karl Popper: The formative years, 1902–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Harré, Rom (ed.). 1975. Problems of scientific revolution: Progress and obstacles to progress in the sciences. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  12. Hofstadter, Richard. 1964. The paranoid style in American politics. Harper's Magazine, November 1964, 77–86.Google Scholar
  13. Jarvie, Ian. 2001. The republic of science: The emergence of Popper's social view of science 1935–1945. Series in the Philosophy of Science of Karl R. Popper and Critical Rationalism. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  14. Jarvie, Ian. 2007. Relativism and historicism. In Handbook of the philosophy of science. Philosophy of anthropology and sociology, eds. Stephen P. Turner and Mark W. Risjord, pp. 553–589. Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kean, Thomas Howard and Hamilton, Lee Herbert. 2004. The 9/11 commission report: Final report of the National Commission on Terrorist Attacks upon the United States, Washington, DC: USGPO.Google Scholar
  16. Latour, Bruno and Woolgar, Steve. 1979. Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Long, Jancis. 1998. Lakatos in Hungary. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 28, 244–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Miller, David. 2006. Out of error. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  19. Nails, Debra. 1995. Agora, academy and the conduct of philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  20. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1935. Logik der Forschung. Wien: Springer.Google Scholar
  21. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1945. The open society and its enemies. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  22. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1957. The aim of science. Ratio, 1, 24–35.Google Scholar
  23. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1958. Back to the presocratics. Reprinted as Chap. 5 of Popper (1963).Google Scholar
  24. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  25. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1963. Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  26. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1970. Normal science and its dangers. In Criticism and the growth of knowl edge, eds. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, pp. 51–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1972. Objective knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  28. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1975. The rationality of scientific revolutions (Harré 1975, pp. 72–101). Reprinted as Popper (1994, Chap. 1).Google Scholar
  29. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1976. Unended quest: An intellectual autobiography. Glasgow: Fontana.Google Scholar
  30. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1979. Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.Google Scholar
  31. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1983–1985. Postscript to the logic of scientific discovery, 3 Volumes. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  32. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1990. A world of propensities. Bristol: Thoemmes.Google Scholar
  33. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1994. The myth of the framework. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  34. Popper, Karl Raimund. 2006. Frühe Schriften (1925–1936), ed. Troels Eggers Hansen. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.Google Scholar
  35. Popper, Karl Raimund. 2008. After the open society: Selected social and political writings, eds. Jeremy Shearmur and Piers Norris Turner. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  36. Popper, Karl Raimund and Eccles, John Carew. 1977. The self and its brain. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  37. Rousseau, Jean Jacques. 1762. The social contract or principles of political right. Ryle, Gilbert. 1947. Review (untitled) of Popper, The open society and its enemies. Mind, 56, 167–172.Google Scholar
  38. Sarkar, Sahotra and Pfeifer, Jessica (eds.). 2006. The philosophy of science. An encyclopedia. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  39. Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.). 1974. The philosophy of Karl Popper. La Salle, IL: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
  40. Steup, Matthias, 2001 (rev. 2006), The analysis of knowledge. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/.Google Scholar
  41. Vlastos, Gregory. 1994. Socratic studies. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Wettersten, John. 1992. The roots of critical rationalism. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  43. Whyte, William Hollingsworth. 1956. The organization man. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
  44. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routldege & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ian Jarvie
    • 1
  1. 1.York UniversityTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations