Advertisement

Intentionality and the Use of Language

  • John R. Searle
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Language Library book series (SLAP, volume 3)

Abstract

It is possible to make a reasonably clear distinction between intensionality with an s and intentionality with a t. Without putting too fine a point on it one can say that intensionality-with-an-s is a property of a certain class of sentences. A sentence is intensional if literal utterances of it have at least one interpretation where they fail to satisfy one or more of the standard tests for extensionality. The two tests most relevant to the present discussion are these: if existential generalization over the occurrence of referring expressions is not a valid form of inference or if the sentence fails to allow the substitution salva veritate of expressions which normally have the same reference, then it is intensional-with-an-s. Thus for example, the sentence “John is looking for the lost city of Atlantis” has at least one literal use to make a statement which does not entail that there is a lost city such that John is looking for it. And the sentence “The sheriff believes that Mr. Howard is an honest man” has a literal use to make a statement which together with the true statement that Mr. Howard is identical with Jesse James does not entail that the sheriff believes that Jesse James is an honest man. Because intensional sentences normally derive their intensionality from the occurrence of certain expressions it is possible to speak not only of intensional sentences, but also of intensional verbs, intensional contexts, etc. It is also possible to speak of intensional statements and intensional propositions. No doubt these two tests need some refinement to enable them to cope with sentences other than those used to make statements but the basic idea of intensionality-with-an-s seems reasonably straightforward.

Keywords

Intentional State Actual Object Propositional Content Intentional Object Lost City 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    Zettel, § 56 and Remarks on Fraser, p. 5.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    “Problems of Intentionality,” in: Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding,E. Pivcevic (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 1975, p. 48.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    It is a mistake to say that there are different senses of “belief,” a “notional” and a “relational” sense. Rather there are different kinds of reports of belief. One and the same belief can be reported in several different ways, e.g., “John believes truly that fa,” “John believes of a that fa,” and “John believes that fa.”Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    “Actions, Reasons, and Causes,” reprinted in: The Philosophy of Action, A. White (ed. ), Oxford University Press, 1968.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    It is fairly easy to extend our criteria of intensionality to apply to intentional states. If the satisfaction of the state requires the existence of the objects represented and if the satisfaction value of the state is not altered by the substitution of other representations of the same object, then the state is extensional.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    For an explanation of the notion of direction of fit, see J.R. Searle, “A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts,” in: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (1975): Language, Mind and Knowledge,K. Gunderson (ed.), pp. 344–369.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    This looks as if it leads to an infinite regress but it does not. The understanding of the conditions of satisfaction of our intentional states is not an additional intentional state.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 1979

Authors and Affiliations

  • John R. Searle
    • 1
  1. 1.The University of California at BerkeleyUSA

Personalised recommendations