Skip to main content

Mie's Theories of Matter and Gravitation

  • Chapter
The Genesis of General Relativity

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 250))

Unifying physics by describing a variety of interactions—or even all interactions— within a common framework has long been an alluring goal for physicists. One of the most ambitious attempts at unification was made in the 1910s by Gustav Mie. Mie aimed to derive electromagnetism, gravitation, and aspects of the emerging quantum theory from a single variational principle and a well-chosen world function (Hamiltonian). Mie's main innovation was to consider nonlinear field equations to allow for stable particle-like solutions (now called solitons); furthermore he clarified the use of variational principles in the context of special relativity. The following brief introduction to Mie's work has three main objectives.1 The first is to explain how Mie's project fit into the contemporary development of the electromagnetic worldview. Part of Mie's project was to develop a relativistic theory of gravitation as a consequence of his generalized electromagnetic theory, and our second goal is to briefly assess this work, which reflects the conceptual resources available for developing a new account of gravitation by analogy with electromagnetism. Finally, Mie was a vocal critic of other approaches to the problem of gravitation. Mie's criticisms of Einstein, in particular, bring out the subtlety and novelty of the ideas that Einstein used to guide his development of general relativity.

In September 1913 Einstein presented a lecture on the current status of the problem of gravitation at the 85th Naturforscherversammlung in Vienna. Einstein's lecture and the ensuing heated discussion, both published later that year in the Physikalische Zeitschrift, reflect the options available for those who took on the task of developing a new theory of gravitation. The conflict between Newtonian gravitational theory and special relativity provided a strong motivation for developing a new gravitational theory, but it was not clear whether a fairly straightforward modification of Newton's theory based on classical field theory would lead to a successful replacement. Einstein clearly aimed to convince his audience that success would require the more radical step of extending the principle of relativity. For Einstein the development of a new gravitational theory was intricately connected with foundational problems in classical mechanics, and in the Vienna lecture he motivated the need to extend the principle of relativity with an appeal to Mach's analysis of inertia. According to Einstein Mach had accurately identified an “epistemological defect” in classical mechanics, namely the introduction of a distinction between inertial and non-inertial reference frames without an appropriate observational basis.2 The special theory of relativity had replaced Galilean transformations between reference frames with Lorentz transformations, but the principle of relativity still did not apply to accelerated motion. Extending the principle of relativity to accelerated motion depended on an idea Einstein later called “the most fortunate thought of my life,” the principle of equivalence. This idea received many different formulations over the years, but in 1913 Einstein gave one version of this principle as a postulate: his second postulate requires the exact equality of inertial and gravitational mass. He further argued that this equality undermines the ability to observationally distinguish between a state of uniform acceleration and the presence of a gravitational field. The principle of equivalence gave Einstein a valuable link between acceleration and gravitation, tying together the problem of gravitation and the problem of extending the principle of relativity. At the time of the Vienna lecture Einstein was in the midst of an ongoing struggle to clarify the connections among Mach's insight, a generalized principle of relativity, and the formal requirement of general covariance, a struggle that would continue for several more years. Although he also drew heavily on classical field theory in his work, he was convinced that this cluster of ideas would provide the key to a new theory of gravitation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 749.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Abraham, Max. 1912. “Relativität und Gravitation. Erwiderung auf eine Bemerkung des Herrn A. Einstein.” Annalen der Physik (38) 1056–1058.

    Google Scholar 

  • Born, Max. 1914. “Der Impuls-Energie-Satz in der Elektrodynamik von Gustav Mie.” Königliche Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen. Nachrichten (1914): 23–36. (English translation in this volume.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchwald, Jed Z, and Andrew Warwick (eds.). 2001. Histories of the Electron. The Birth of Microphysics. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • CPAE 4: Martin J. Klein, A. J. Kox, Jürgen Renn, and Robert Schulmann (eds.). 1995. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Vol. 4. The Swiss Years: Writings, 1912–1914. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • CPAE 6: A. J. Kox, Martin J. Klein, and Robert Schulmann (eds.). 1996. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Vol. 6. The Berlin Years: Writings, 1914–1917. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • CPAE 6E: The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Vol. 6. The Berlin Years: Writings, 1914–1917. English edition translated by Alfred Engel, consultant Engelbert Schucking. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • CPAE 8: Robert Schulmann, A. J. Kox, Michel Janssen, and József Illy (eds.). 1998. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Vol. 8. The Berlin Years: Correspondence, 1914–1918. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • CPAE 8E: The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Vol. 8. The Berlin Years: Correspondence, 1914–1918. English edition translated by Ann M. Hentschel, consultant Klaus Hentschel. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, Leo. 1999. “From Mie's Electromagnetic Theory of Matter to Hilbert's Unified Foundations of Physics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 30 B (2):159–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——. 2004. David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1898–1918): From Grundlagen der Geometrie to Grundlagen der Physik. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, Albert. 1913. “Zum gegenwärtigen Stande des Gravitationsproblems.” Physikalische Zeitschrift 14: 1249–1262, (CPAE 4, Doc. 17).

    Google Scholar 

  • ——.1914. “Zum Relativitätsproblem.” Scientia 15: 337–348, CPAE 4, Doc. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, Michel and Mecklenburg, Matthew. Forthcoming. “The Transition from Classical to Relativistic Mechanics: Electromagnetic Models of the Electron.” To appear in a volume edited by Jesper Lützen based on the proceedings of the conference, The Interaction between Mathematics, Physics and Philosophy from 1850 to 1940, Copenhagen, September 26–28, 2002. Earlier version available as Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Preprint 277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohl, Gunter. 2002. “Relativität in der Schwebe: Die Rolle von Gustav Mie'” Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Preprint 209.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormach, Russell. 1970. “Einstein, Lorentz, and the electron theory.” Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences, 2: 41–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mie, Gustav. 1908. “Beiträge zur Optik trüber Medien, speziell kolloidaler Metalllösungen,” Annalen der Physik 25, 378–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——. 1910. Lehrbuch der Elektrizität und des Magnetismus. Stuttgart: F. Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——. 1914. “Bemerkungen zu der Einsteinschen Gravitationstheorie. I und II.” Physikalische Zeitschrift 14: 115–122, 169–176.” (English translation in this volume.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ——. 1915. “Das Prinzip von der Realität des Gravitationspotentials.” In Arbeiten aus den Gebieten der Physik, Mathematik, Chemie. Festschrift Julius Elster und Hans Geitel zum sechzigsten Geburtstag. Braunschweig: Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn, 251–268. (English translation in this volume.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pais, Abraham. 1972. “The Early History of the Theory of the Electron: 1897–1947.” In A. Salam and E. P. Wigner (eds.), Aspects of Quantum Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 79–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pauli, Wolfgang. 1921. “Relativitätstheorie.” In A. Sommerfeld (ed.), Encyklopädie der mathematischen Wissenschaften, mit Einschluss ihrer Anwendungen. Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 539–775.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——. 1958. Theory of Relativity. (Translated by G. Field.) London: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, Henri. 1906. “Sur la dynamique de l'électron.” Rendiconti del Circolo Matematico di Palermo 21: 129–175. Reprinted in (Poincaré 1934–54), Vol. 9, 494–550. (English translation of excerpt in vol. 3 of this series.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, Tilman. 1999. “The Relativity of Discovery: Hilbert's First Note on the Foundations of Physics.” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 53: 529–575.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vizgin, Vladimir. 1994. Unified Field Theories in the First Third of the 20th Century. (Translated by Barbour, Julian B, edited by E. Hiebert and H. Wussing.) Science Networks, Historical Studies, Vol. 13. Basel, Boston, Berlin: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, Hermann. 1918. Raum-Zeit-Materie. Vorlesungen über allgemeine Relativitätstheorie. (First edition.) Berlin: Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2007 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Smeenk, C., Martin, C. (2007). Mie's Theories of Matter and Gravitation. In: Janssen, M., Norton, J.D., Renn, J., Sauer, T., Stachel, J. (eds) The Genesis of General Relativity. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 250. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-4000-9_35

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics