Skip to main content

Logical vs. Nonlogical Concepts: An Untenable Dualism?

  • Chapter
Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, And The Unity Of Science ((LEUS,volume 1))

One of the greatest disasters that befell twentieth-century analytic philosophy was Quine's (1953) rejection of the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths as an “untenable dualism”, to use Morton White's (1950) phrase. Or rather, the disaster was the widespread acceptance of this untenable rejection. It deprived philosophers of the means of mastering the defining concept of our era, the notion of information. It made it apparently pointless for them to use axiomatization or other kind of logical systematization as a tool of serious philosophical analysis, and hence encouraged the currently popular no-brainer appeals to “intuitions”. (cf. Hintikka 1999) These unfortunate consequences follow because on Quine's view a deduction of a theorem from axioms (and more generally a deduction of a consequence from premises) can introduce what for us is new factual information, for according to Quine such information cannot be separated from what for us is purely linguistic information. Hence the cognitive content (factual information) of a theory cannot be summed up in its axioms, for new assumptions can be introduced by the logical and mathematical methods used in the derivation of the theorems. This was precisely the kind of conundrum that the great David Hilbert sought to eliminate by means of his axiomatic approach, as shown by the sixth problem in his famous list of open problems. (See here e.g., Cory 1997, 1998; Majer 2001; and Yandell 2002)

In this paper, I will discuss one of the assumptions on which Quine's argument for rejecting the analytic-synthetic distinction rests. As I have pointed out before (Hintikka forthcoming (c)) the terms “analytic” and “synthetic” are most unfortunate from a historical point of view. What is meant is in fact a distinction between conceptual and factual information. Quine is right in effect pointing out that one cannot tell from a person's behavior whether the information he is relying on is factual or conceptual. But this interwovenness of factual and conceptual information can be much better explained by distinguishing from each other two different kinds of logical truths and accordingly two different kinds of information — much better than by abolishing the borderline between logical (conceptual) truths and factual truths, as Quine wants to do. (See here Hintikka, forthcoming (c)) Accordingly, Quine's accurate insight into (in effect) the behavioral indistinguishability of the two kinds of information does not mean that one cannot define the distinction by some other means. Indeed, it can be shown beyond any reasonable doubt that the usual logical truths of first-order logic are uninformative aka “tautological” in one basic sense of information.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Carnap, Rudolf: 1937 (original 1934), The Logical Syntax of Language, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cory, Leo: 1998, ‘Hilbert on Kinetic Theory and Radiation Theory (1912–1914)’, The Mathematical Intelligencer 20, 52–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cory, Leo: 1997, ‘David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1894–1905)’, Archive of the History of Exact Sciences 51, 83–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, John: 1990, The Concept of Logical Consequence, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: forthcoming a, ‘An Epistemology for Game-theoretical Semantics’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: forthcoming b, ‘What is the True Algebra of Logic?’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: forthcoming c, ‘A Distinction Too Many or Too Few?.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: 2002, ‘Quantum Logic as a Fragment of Independence-friendly Logic’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 31, 197–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: 1999, ‘The Emperor's New Intuitions’, Journal of Philosophy 96, 127–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko: 1996, Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a Half Truths, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko, and Gabriel Sandu: 1996, ‘Game-theoretical Semantics’, in Johan van Benthem and Alice ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language, Amsterdam, Elsevier, pp. 361– 410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Merrill B. and Jaakko Hintikka: 1986, Investigating Wittgenstein, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, Eckehart: 1991, ‘Gödel und der Wiener Kreis’, in Paul Kruntorad (ed.), Jour fixe der Vernunft: Der Wiener Kreis und die Folgen, Vienna, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, pp. 127–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majer, Ulrich: 2001, ‘The Axiomatic Method and the Foundations of Science’, in Miklós Redei and Michael Stöltzner (eds.), John von Neumann and the Foundations of Quantum Physics, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic, pp. 11–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V.: 1953 (original 1951), ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, in From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, pp. 20–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V.: 1970, Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, Morton, N. J.: 1950, ‘The Analytic and the Synthetic: An Untenable Dualism’, in Sidney Hook (ed.), John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom, New York, Dial Press, pp. 316–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: 192, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: 1953, Philosophical Investigations, Oxfored, Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yandell, Benjamin H., 2002, The Honors Class: Hilbert's Problems and Their Solvers, Natck, MA, A.K. Peters.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hintikka, J. (2009). Logical vs. Nonlogical Concepts: An Untenable Dualism?. In: Rahman, S., Symons, J., Gabbay, D.M., Bendegem, J.P.v. (eds) Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Logic, Epistemology, And The Unity Of Science, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-2808-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-2808-3_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-2486-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4020-2808-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics